Notes on: Deleuze, G and
Guattari, F. ( 2004) A Thousand
Plateaus.London: Continuum.
Chapter 12. 1227: Treatise on
Nomadology - the War Machine
Dave Harris
[Very long. Rather rambling structure, despite its
jokey organization into axioms with various
propositions. Impossible set of references as
usual, at least for someone unfamiliar with
French. Wide ranging, but turning on a series of
metaphorical oppositions: war machine/state;
nomadic/sedentary or nomadic/settled;
smooth/striated space; intensive/extensive or
metric; singularity/category; nomos/Logos. There
is the constant contrast between empirical and the
virtual. As we would expect, these
distinctions are not very fixed, of course. Again,
DeLanda seems
indispensable to grasp some of the implications,
not least because he has written an excellent book on {literal} war
machines. I think 1227 is significant because it
was when Genghis Khan died]
A French analysis of mythology [by Dumezil, who
does rather a lot of work in this] shows that
proper systems of domination require both
magician-king and jurist-priest [charisma and
bureaucracy?]. Here, we see the oppositions
obscure/clear, violent/calm, quick/weighty,
fearsome/regulated, bond and pact, but they need
to operate as a pair, so that developments on one
level induce specifications on others. This
is 'double articulation', and it turns the state
into a stratum.
There is no necessary generation of war here -
states can prevent military violence by using a
police system [or ideology, but we're not allowed
to use the term]. If they generate an army,
that requires them to integrate a separate
military function, a war machine, outside of the
state apparatus [outside in ideology
anyway]. The war machine offers more
flexibility, because it accesses a multiplicity,
and this represents potential against the power of
the state, 'a machine against the apparatus'[all
this is traced to the characteristics of 'Indra
the warrior god'(388). Normal bonds are
untied, relations of becoming appear instead of
binary divisions.
We can see this when we look at different sorts of
games, comparing chess with Go, for example (389)
[apparently, Go is played in a smooth space as
opposed to the striated space of chess, drawing on
nomos instead of polis [this time]
While chess decodes space, Go
territorializes and deterritorializes].
Then we move on to Bantu myth about nomadic armies
conquering states. This links with all sorts
of negative characteristics attributed to
warriors, who have no loyalties. European
historians have followed this 'negative tradition'
(390), and this has produced difficulties in
theorizing the war machine. We need to
see it as 'the pure form of exteriority', with the
state as the classic form of interiority, found
even in 'the habit of thinking'. In actual
cases, there are mixtures, and the State offers
the same forms as the war machine, on the surface
at least: hence the success of negative
conceptions of the war machine Nevertheless,
exterior figures dominate myths and Shakespeare
plays [typical of the 'evidence'!] .
Actually, the war machine is located between the
two branches of the state [military and
civil?]. It cannot be reduced to the
military apparatus the state uses. The
constant suspicion of the military is explained by
this connection with something more
exterior. As they are not firmly located,
men of war seem outmoded or dangerously
independent [Greek myth here, 391-2].
Kleist's commentary on Achilles is admired [Penthesilea
-- she is even more independent but possibly only
because 'love' leads her to abandon everything
else] The German war machine that challenged
the legions achieved victory, but was still seen
as dangerously outside the law. If war
machines are not to be incorporated into the
state, they seem only to offer suicide and
solitariness. Nevertheless, Kleist has
identified the key characteristics that link the
war machine to modernity - 'secrecy, speed, and
affect'(392) [In what follows, speed is to be
defined in that strange possibly 17th century way
as the ability to make seemingly instant
connections across space]. Kleist also notices the
radical form of exteriority that liberates
feelings from subjects, becoming 'an incredible
velocity, a catapulting force… they are no
longer feelings but affects'
Affects become weapons of war. They appear
as various kinds of becoming, including
becoming-woman and becoming-animal
[dehumanising?]. They are linked together by the
war machine. Time itself breaks down into
'an endless succession of catatonic episodes or
fainting spells', where affect is too strong, or
completely compelling. People are
'desubjectified', and 'no subjective interiority
remains' (393). These themes are pursued in
modern art as well. This ability to mobilize
affects is what challenges the stability of the
state, unless it has already been incorporated,
say in visions of the state that allegedly
transcend the individual [I think, maybe with
fascism in mind].
Why do 'primitive, sedimentary societies' not have
a state? The usual answer refers to their
lack of economic or political development, but
Clastres argues that they might actually have been
concerned to 'avert that monster' (394).
Permanent organs of power are the problem, and non
industrial societies had ways to prevent them
developing. War itself was an important
mechanism, offering a warrior alternative rather
than a statesman alternative: war prevents
exchange or alliance from turning into props for
state power. Such 'mechanisms of inhibition'
could operate at the micro level [a French study
of street gangs shows a constant system of
alliances between groups, preventing leaders from
emerging]. High society groups in France
operated in the same way, as Proust showed,
focusing on prestige rather than power. The
pack or band operates as a rhizome and therefore
'are metamorphoses of a war machine'. They
tend to operate with a certain indiscipline, a
questioning of authority, 'perpetual blackmail by
abandonment or betrayal' (395).
Clastres is right to say that the state produces a
development of productive forces and not the other
way around, and it seems to emerge all at once
rather than as a result of steady progress.
It could certainly never arise from the war
machine. The issue Clastres raises is why
people came to desire servitude at all [detailed
discussion of Clastres 396-7]. Perhaps the
state has always existed, always in a relation
with the outside as a way of maintaining its
sovereignty. Outside factors include 'huge
worldwide machines' like religious formations and
multinational organizations, but also local
mechanisms which assert themselves against the
organs of state power, like the new of tribalism
of Mcluhan. The outside forces can even
combine, as when religious formations develop into
bands. Here, their nomos challenges
the law, the state form. The war machines do
not require some consistent form of sovereignty,
but can exist in 'flows and currents' (398),
perpetual interactions, and they compete with the
state in these fields. [This reminds me of
Gellner on the constant tensions between
revolutionary and conservative forces in the
Soviet union, both equally licensed by Marxism]
We find the same divisions in epistemology, with
the contrast between royal and minor
sciences. Serres has identified the
characteristics of minor science: hydraulic rather
than a theory of solids, with an emphasis on flux
and flow as reality itself; an emphasis on
becoming and heterogeneity, with the example of
the discovery of the clinamen in Greek thought,
'the original curvature of the movement of the
atom' (398), replacing the notion of the straight
line with the curve, in anticipation of 'a
predifferential calculus' (399). Instead of
a geometry of straight line and parallels, we have
'curvilinear declination', a series of spirals and
vortices, a space in which 'things-flows' are
distributed, smooth spaces rather than 'a striated
(metric) one'. The model also focuses on
problems not theorems, and considers affects
[actually 'affections'] as things that operate on
figures, as 'sections, ablations, conjunctions,
projections'. Figures themselves are better
seen as events rather than something releasing
essences, connected to other figures, just as
squares exist within quadratures [HP Lovecraft
again, as in Difference
and Repetition]. In this sense,
problems are not obstacles but something that
illustrates what surpasses normal structures and
shows how to overcome them [maybe], 'in other
words, a war machine'... 'the problemata are
the war machine itself.' Royal science tries
constantly to reduce problems and subordinate them
to theorems. [Another feature of this
nonempirical world is the 'passage to the limit',
which I still do not properly understand - I think
it means going beyond empirical limits, or at
least making us aware of them and raising new
possibilities].
It's possible to extend these insights into
thinking of 'an abstract knowledge formally
different' from the normal one, and to see a nomad
science as developing from its assumptions.
There is a constant struggle with state
science. State science is happy to
appropriate whatever it can from nomad science,
but it tries to domesticate it as something that
might accompany science, or to ban it. Those
practicing nomad science are therefore 'caught
between a rock and a hard place' [SIC] (400),
trying to avoid both domestication and excessive
nomadism. Military engineers show this
ambiguity well. For example, there has long
been a state-inspired science of military
organization, based on 'descriptive and projective
geometry', which states attempt to show are simply
practical applications of 'analytic, or so-called
higher geometry' [DeLanda
is essential here]. The same reaction
greeted the development of differential calculus,
initially seen as only a convenient convention,
then as something to be domesticated so that 'all
the dynamic, and nomadic notions - such as
becoming, heterogeneity, infinitesimal, passage to
the limit, continuous variation' could be managed
by the imposition of standard rules. Even
the hydraulic model was itself subordinated with
the development of systems that eliminated
turbulence, making the fluid 'depend on the solid'
as in the regulation of flow. The real
implication was to consider a smooth space and
movements that affect all the points of the space,
instead of linear projections from one local
movement to another. Advocates of the
hydraulic model were also capable of seeing social
and political implications.
Or consider the sea? The notion of a 'fleet
in being' shows attempts to recognize the problems
of dominating open spaces [possibly, the
discussion is drawn from Virilio]. We can
also think of work on the rhizome whether it is
simply a matter of waves or whether it designates
form in general, a particular type of
movement. Rhythm can be metricated, but
there is 'also a rhythm without measure ... the
manner in which a fluid occupies a smooth space'
(401).
So we see oppositions like this in the development
of science at different times [to return to the
issue of nomadic vs. royal science]. For
example, gothic cathedrals in the 12th century, or
bridges in the 18th and 19th centuries illustrate
the possibilities. The gothic interest in
larger churches is not just quantitative but
qualitative, attempting to release a more dynamic
relation of form and matter, cutting stones to
coordinate forces of thrust. This produces
building construction seen as 'the line of
continuous variation of the stones' (402) as
opposed to the conventional striations, lines and
parallels. The task was managed by
attempting to affect construction to euclidean
geometry, which forms were seen as the best way to
organize surface and volumes, but original
architects saw all that this would be too
difficult, and preferred 'a projective and
descriptive geometry' instead. This was
echoed by actual advice to stonecutters, or 'an
operative logic of movement', generating equations
rather than trying to fit formal ones, to do with
forces of thrust, 'in a qualitative calculus of
the optimum'. In this way classic geometry
was brought to its limit, demonstrated in the work
of 'the remarkable 17th century mathematician
Desargues'. He was eventually banned by
royal science, who insisted on using conventional
templates to cut stone, even if this domesticated
perspective and removed all the 'heuristic and
ambulatory capacities'. The journeyman
themselves however pursued this more adventurous
approach, and they similarly happen to be
controlled, for example by regulating their guilds
[at first, through the Templars, it is argued].
Initially, modern bridges were subject to 'active,
dynamic, and collective experimentation',
sometimes even governed [designed?] by general
assemblies. One bridge builder saw it as
necessary not to choke the river, but to make the
bridge vary with the whole (403), but again the
state intervened to establish organized schools
[including the grandes ecoles].
State organizations can tell us something about
collective bodies here. They are
differentiated and hierarchical, they relate
particularly to families, but there is something
that does not neatly fit: they can occasionally
constitute themselves as war machines, introducing
dynamism and nomadism. We can see this with
the development of the lobby, an ambiguous and
fluid group. We can argue that the body
therefore is not reducible to an organism; for
example in the case of the military it has an esprit
de corps. This is also an aspect of
the nomadic band, which also shows a different
relation to families [the family for nomads is 'a
band vector'(404), drawing on the ability to
maintain solidarity, which might also involve
'genealogical mobility']. This illustrates
the potential of social groups like families,
which can act as 'vortical' bodies. They are
not saying that modern states are the same as Arab
tribes, but rather that collective bodies 'always
have fringes or minorities that reconstitute
equivalents of the war machine', as the examples
of architecture above indicate. Sometimes
collective bodies can form across the
hierarchies. Sometimes, official bodies are
forced to open themselves to something that
exceeds them, 'the short revolutionary instant, an
experimental surge'. The confusion that
results brings new thinking about tendencies,
poles, and movements. In those moments, the
collective body of the state regroups and
reorganises, acting like tribal nomads.
[back to geometry]. Husserl talked of
protogeometry, involving essential shapes or
essences, qualities that appear vague, something
'anexact yet rigorous'. We find these
problematic figures whenever theorematic ones
change. We need to talk about the figures
that are '"lens shaped," "umbelliform" or
"indented"'(405), for example. If circles
are ideal fixed essences, roundness is 'a vague
and fluent essence, distinct both from the circle
and things that are round'. What these vague
essences refer to is something that exceeds
thinghood - 'corporeality', perhaps even with an
esprit de corps. For Husserl, such
possibilities were still seen as supporting normal
science and geometry, as limit cases
[maybe]. However, we can suggest there are
two quite different notions of science which
interact 'ontologically' in a single field, with
royal science constantly appropriating elements of
vague or nomad science, and the latter constantly
reinvigorating the former. Huuserl and
others wanted to police this relation, as 'the man
of the State', to insist the royal science was
prime, so that nomad science could only be
parascientific. We can now see a war machine
as 'necessary to make something round', despite
the state's interest in ideal circles.
Nomad science is not connected to work in the same
way that royal science is. It has a
different division of labour. Bodies of
nomadic artisans have always caused problems for
states who have tried to settle and make them
sedentary, either regulating and through
corporations, or simply relying on force and
power. To go back to gothic architecture, we
can see how active these nomadic artisans were,
and how the state attempted to regulate them, in
ways which included making strong distinctions
between intellectual and manual, theoretical and
practical labour. In the process, they
developed a metric plane, as in official
architecture, while nomads developed a
different 'ground - level plane'[that is taking
into account the characteristics of the
ground?]. Metrication and templates also
deskilled artisans ['dequalification', 406], and
offered a licensed autonomy to the skilled and
intellectual. However, there is a constant
relation of domination and challenge.
In these cases, insisting on precision and
metrication is a way of enforcing a particular
division of labour, although it would be wrong to
see this as just an extrinsic constraint.
Instead, these characteristics get imported into
royal science, into its '"hylomorphic" model'
(407). This involves a split between form
and matter, and again the argument is 'that this
schema derives less from technology or life than
from a society divided into governors and
governed'. It also leads to the familiar
split between content and expression - matter
becomes content, form becomes expression.
Nomad science in contrast 'is more immediately in
tune with the connection' between them - matter is
never prepared and homogenized but is seen as
'essentially laden with singularities' as a form
of content, while expression is not just formal
but includes various 'pertinent traits'. We
see this in nomad art and its connections between
'support and ornament' which does not follow the
matter-form schema. Nomad science sees the
relation between singularities of matter and
traits of expression, 'whether they be natural or
forced', and this in turn requires another
conception of work and the social field.
We can see the two models of science in Plato's
terms -Compars and Dispars [pursued
407 - 10]. Compars is the model of royal
science based on discovering laws that control
constants, where constants are seen as something
invariable. Dispars is nomadic science,
focusing on 'material - forces rather than matter
- form', where variables are put in a state of
continuous variation, and equations are more like
adequations or differential equations:
singularities in matter are sought rather than
general forms; individuations are seen as events
or haecceities rather than as objects, 'a compound
of matter and form' (408). Vague essences
are also haecceities. Here, nomos opposes
logos, and people could see that the latter had a
moral element. For compars, space was
homogenous and striated, divided by verticals or
parallel layers. It had a tendency to spread
to colonise all the other dimensions [and turned
into something like Cartesian space, a
grid]. Gravity seemed important as a model
for universal attraction between bodies: even
chemistry was affected, even euclidean geometry
implied the force of gravity, as a kind of
invariable force. This was the basis for
metric or arborescent conceptions of
multiplicities, and had a genuine impact on
scientific thought [some scientists apparently
thought that gravity was literally the universal
force], becoming 'the form of interiority of
all science'.
Dispars did not deny the force of gravity, but
insisted on variable effects, something
supplementary, something in each scientific field
that was not reducible to the basic model,
something that insisted on an excess or
deviation. Thus chemistry added other forces
to those of gravity. Velocity itself blurs
the grid conception, with curvilinear motion, with
the clinamen as 'the smallest deviation, the
minimum excess'. Smooth space displays this
best, and therefore has no homogeneity either in
terms of the distribution of points or the path
between them, focusing instead on local
contacts. Here, there is a different notion
of multiplicity - 'nonmetric, acentric,
rhizomatic' (409) [the example is the system of
sounds or colours, which cannot be gridded
externally - this was before digitalization, of
course].
Oppositions like those between speed and slowness,
the quick and weighty refer to qualitative
differences in science. Speed, for example
its not just an abstract quality of movement, but
'is incarnated in a moving body that deviates,
however slightly, from its line of descent or
gravity'[no doubt some philosophically significant
definition]. Both slow and quick are 'two
types of qualified movement', and the qualitative
differences remain despite the measurable
qualities [the examples that follow involve
redefinitions of speed as decreasing slowness,
laminar movement as weighty, while rapidity refers
to movement that deviates and takes on a vortical
form, and this arises from 'a condition that is
coextensive to science and that regulates both the
separation and the mixing of the two models'- all
this is attributed to Serres]. There are two types
of science, one which reproduces, the other which
follows [through iteration]. Royal science
reproduces, induces and deduces, attempting to
perceive events externally, and to find laws about
them. Nomadic science on the other hand
searches for singularities, experiences vortical
flows and continuous variation of variables.
While the first reterritorializes, the second
constantly deterritorializes and extends territory
[with a quote from Castenada about how we follow
how seeds are dispersed to determine territory,
411].
[Then we get on to metals. Much more is to
come] Primitive metallurgy was undertaken by
nomadic smiths, despite attempts to see them as
following fixed paths on various layers.
This is because 'ambulant procedures and processes
are necessarily tied to a striated space', which
are then formalized as some kind of notion of
technology or applied science as an
abstraction. This recuperation is
chronically likely with nonmetrical
multiplicities, in a triumph of the logos.
However, there are always sources of resistance in
complexity, and the likely return to nomadic
procedure, where points becomes singularities
again, and smooth space reasserts itself.
The state needs both to resist and to integrate
such procedures, and often assigns them a minor
position. We should not see nomadic sciences
as irrational or mystical: they can look like that
when they are marginalised; anyway, royal science
also has its 'priestliness and magic'(412) [Adorno is very good on
that]. It is certainly not the case that
ambulant science somehow produces royal science
from itself: it continues to depend on following
flows in smooth spaces. However, there is a
constant attempt to reterritorialize, to produce
stable models, sometimes in the name of safety
[when building cathedrals][now in the name of
technological progress?]. The metric power
operated by royal science makes science autonomous
[in the sense of depersonalizing it - generally
regarded as a good thing]. A cosy division
of labour is often the result, where ambulant
science identifies problems, and royal science
offers scientific solutions, like the relation
between intuition and intelligence for Bergson,
and making a genuine move away from intuition and
the qualities of humanity [again I think they are
in favour of this move, although they do not say
so explicitly].
The very form of normal thought, not just its
content, is conformist, based on a model borrowed
from the state apparatus, with ready defined goals
and paths. Images of thought like this are
are studied by noology. The conventional
image operates with a dualism between true
thinking from magical capture, and
foundationalism, and 'a republic of free
spirits...a legislative and juridical
organization'(413). The two are interrelated
and necessary to one another, but this also allows
for something happening between them, something
outside the conventional model. We are not
operating with metaphors here -the imperium of
truth and a republic of spirits are necessary
components, and form a kind of interiority as a
stratum.
This gives thought a gravity, since it appears to
explain everything, including the state. The
state also benefits from the consensus.
Thought like this elevates the state to something
universal, rational and right, an ultimate
referee. Anything particular appears as an
accident, including any imperfections.
Before long, any 'realized reason is identified
with the de jure State' [classic Marxist
critique of Hegel]. These conceptions appear
in modern philosophy as well, anything that splits
a legislator and a subject in conferring
identity. If people obey the legislator,
they become masters of themselves, because this is
obeying pure reason in the interests of all.
Any philosophy 'of ground'[which I am translating
as foundationalism] ends by giving the established
powers credibility, seeing the organs of state
power as akin to subjective faculties, with common
sense as a state consensus. The philosopher
becomes 'a public professor or state functionary'
(415), while the state inspires the reciprocal
image of thought. 'In modern states, the
sociologist succeeded in replacing the
philosopher'[the example is Durkheim of
course]. Psychoanalysis also claims to
operate with some universal process of thought,
which somehow becomes 'the thought of the Law'
[the critique of Freud and Oedipus of
course]. Noology offers a non ideological
way to understand these effects. It would be
a mistake, however, to dismiss such thinking - if
we avoid serious thoughts, we end up even more
doing what the state wants.
There are however private thinkers who resist -
Kierkegaard, Nietzsche or Shestov [?]. These
people live in the desert. They destroy
images. [Apparently Nietzsche's Schopenhauer
as Educator is the key text for criticizing
the conformity of conventional thought].
However, it's not just private thought, but
something exterior to thought, something that
places thought in a relation with the outside,
thought as a war machine. This explains the
forms like the aphorism in Nietzsche [which
apparently requires meaning to be added from a new
external force]. Nor are private thinkers
always on their own: instead, they comprise a
solitude that is also interwoven with a people to
come [or so they would like to think]. This
exterior thought maintains its externality and is
therefore not just another image of thought, but
'a force that destroys both the image and its
copies' (416). Conventional methods operate
with striated space and conventional paths, but
exterior thought finds itself in a smooth space
and there 'is no possible method...only relays,
intermezzos, resurgences'. Zen archery
offers another example. The war machine is
operated by 'an ambulant people of
relayers'. That this often leads to failure,
only goes to show that nature is not purposive
even if it is wise.
We can see this in Artaud's letters to Rivière,
referring to thought as a matter of central
breakdown, vitalised by its inability to take on
any form. We can see this also in a text by
Kleist, criticizing the notion of the concept as
an interior means of control, and stressing
instead thought as a proceeding and a process,
operating with intensity, not controlling language
(417). Such thinking encounters 'an
event-thought, a haecceity, instead of a
subject-thought, a problem-thought instead of an
essence-thought', a thought tackling exterior
forces, resisting all attempts to legislate.
However, both Kleist and Artaud have become
'monuments, inspiring a model to be copied'[and
the same fate awaits D and G].
The classical image of thought claims to be
universal, both offering the whole as the final
ground of being, and the subject as the principle
that personalizes such being. Nomad thought
rejects this image, denying a universal thinking
subject in favour of a 'singular race'(418),
operating without horizons in a smooth
space. Apparently, irruptions from Celtic
thinking can be detected in English
literature. However, there are dangers, of
racism or fascism, or the development of a sect,
'microfascisms'. Oriental thinking in
particular [specifically in yoga, Zen and karate]
can act as a fantasy to reactivate 'all the
fascisms in a different way'. The test is to
ask whether particular race-tribes are oppressed,
inferior, dominated. The point is to
construct a smooth space and then to traverse
it. We should think of thought as 'a
becoming, a double becoming, rather than the
attribute of the Subject and the representation of
a Whole'(419)
Can we discover what is a principle in nomadic
life and what is only a consequence? Much
will depend on whether conventional paths, through
the desert, become important in themselves [for
whom?] or act only as a relay, with points to be
left behind. The life of the true nomad 'is
the intermezzo'. Nomads are not migrants who
have a fixed point as a destination, although
sometimes the one turns into the other. The
nomadic road is not used as a boundary for spaces,
but rather 'it distributes people (or animals) in
an open space' (420). There is no codified
nomos but rather a fuzzy aggregate, again in
opposition to the polis. Nomad space is
smooth, not organized or subdivided, 'marked only
by "traits" that are effaced and displaced with
the trajectory'. Nomads occupy space as we
know from the famous quote from Toynbee [much
repeated elsewhere]: they occupy smooth spaces and
do not want to enter striated ones. Nomads
offer both immobility and speed, which leads to a
necessary distinction between speed and movement -
'movement is extensive; speed is intensive', and
while movement describes different states of the
body considered as one, speed 'constitutes the
absolute character of a body whose irreducible
parts of (atoms) occupy or fill a smooth space in
the manner of a vortex'. It is like making a
spiritual journey without relative movement,
operating in intensity but in one place.
Speed is therefore an important element of the
nomadic war machine.
Nomads do not reterritorialize, unlike migrants or
sedentary people. Deterritorialization is
the proper relation to the earth - ironically,
this means that nomads reterritorialize on
deterritorialization! (421). The earth
also has to offer the possibility of
deterritorialization: we think of it as land, but
nomads simply as grounds or supports.
Possibilities for deterritorialization can appear
at local spots affected by climate or changes in
vegetation. Once established, nomads 'make
the desert no less than they are made by it.
They are vectors of deterritorialization'.
They proceed in an endlessly flexible manner,
'like rhizomatic vegetation' following local
conditions. There is a local topology that
relies on haecceities and various relations
between the elements. We find a tactile or
haptic space, sonorous rather than visual.
Striated space by contrast is subdivided and
interlinked, crossed by boundaries: it's ubiquity
makes it the 'relative global' as opposed to the
'local absolute' of the nomad.
In some ways, we can see nomadism in terms of the
general characteristics of religion [in the sense
of making the absolute appear locally], but
religion usually opposes 'the obscure nomos'
(422), and attempts to found a centre. In
doing this, it converts the absolute and becomes a
part of the state apparatus. Nomads couple
locality and the absolute differently, through a
succession of local operations. In this,
they usually stand opposed to conventional
religion, with a 'singularly atheistic' sense of
the absolute, as a number of religious figures
have reported [including early Islam which rapidly
replaced the notion of nomadism with the
migration, 423]. However, even monotheistic
religion encounters fringe areas, largely because
it does not simply confine itself to the territory
of the state. In this way, even religion can
be an element in the war machine, as we know from
holy war [I think they have slipped themselves
from the war machine to military action
here]. The prophet opposes the King.
Mohammed did this, and created a particularly
powerful esprit de corps. The Christian view
of Islam as essentially military forgets or denies
military adventures by Christians. Overall,
religion as a war machine does tend to produce
nomadism, and offers an absolute state which is
beyond the conventional [as indeed we know from
ISIS]. Even the crusades began with variable
directions, as a war machine, and put into process
a chain of events sweeping away the old sedentary
regimes, even if they ended with new forms of
sedentary migrants [massively windy French salon
stuff].
Smooth spaces lie between striated ones, between
the forest and agriculture. The striated
ones limit developments and attempt to overcome
the smooth ones. Nomads had to deal with
both forest and farmer, and the relative
importance of factors associated with both have
been discussed by western historians (424).
Apparently what the argument shows is that the
state form tends to prevail, partly because it is
composed of a number of elements, including
natural resources: the difference between oriental
and western states is that the components were
organized in a different way, including some
despotic formations. All types faced
challenge, from revolt and secession to revolution
[with world history interpreted as various
relations to dominate smooth spaces, and to
confront nomadic war machines directly or
indirectly 425].
The state has to striate space, but it also need
smooth space 'as a means of communication'.
Mostly, it operates to control the exterior by
capturing flows of all kinds and turning them into
fixed paths. Virilo is right to argue that
the main technique involves creating the polis and
police. Speed has to be turned into
movement, and movement itself endlessly
transformed to regulate speed. Whenever
there is any form of challenge to the state, when
a war machine is been revived, a smooth space
appears [as in occupying the street]. States
attempt to appropriate war machines, often in the
form of blocking absolute movements. Any
flows that are not regulated tend to turn into war
machines [the example is China in the 14th century
withdrawing from regulating maritime flows and
rapidly encountering commercially sponsored
piracy].
The sea 'is perhaps principal amongst smooth
spaces' (427), and there were early attempts to
striate it, by deploying suitable
technologies. However, one unintended
consequence was that relative movements multiplied
and intensified [as technologies spread beyond
state control?], which produced a smooth space
again. We see this with the notion of the
'fleet in being' which holds space from being able
to move to and from any point. The air can
be dominated in the same way. We see from
these examples how the state can occasionally
produce absolute movements, reconstituting smooth
space. This produces 'a worldwide war
machine', exceeding state apparatuses and
empowering various military-industrial and other
multinationals. This should warn us that
smooth space is not always revolutionary and can
take on different meanings depending on the
interactions that produce them: we also see this
in the way that total war and popular war 'borrow
one another's methods'.
[Now a long and strange piece about nomads and
numbers]. Conventional armies
deterritorialize soldiers, by organizing them into
smaller units [we are really stretching the notion
of deterritorialization here]. Numbers are
always connected to war machines [as well as
armies?], as a matter of 'organization or
composition'(428). Nomads thought of
numerical organizations first, though [lofty salon
stuff about the Hyksos and Moses and the book of
numbers]. 'The nomos is fundamentally
numerical, arithmetic' [but not geometric].
So we have lineal, territorial and numerical types
of human organization. So called primitive
societies are lineal, with the clan lineages as
segments. There are also tribal segments,
however, requiring number again. Number acts
as an inscription [nominals?] written on the
earth. In state societies, the earth is
first of all deterritorialized, becoming an object
rather than something active, and property is
another example. This requires an
'overcoding', in the form of the territorial
organization, where segments are located in a
geometrical or astronomical space. In the
archaic state, there is 'a spatium with a
summit, a differentiated space with depths and
levels' (429), whereas the modern state is divided
more into a centre dominating a homogeneous space
with divisible parts. We find these mixed as
well. Both depend on 'metric power', the
political use of arithmetic as in imperial
bureaucracies operating taxation and election
systems, and, later, political economy and the
organisation of work. Numbers are used 'to
gain mastery over matter, to control its
variations and movements'. Number is now
neither independent nor autonomous.
'Autonomous arithmetical organization' can be
described as 'The Numbering Number', and it
relates to conditions of possibility and
effectuating the war machine. State armies
require the treatment of large quantities, for
example, but war machines operate with smaller
quantities with autonomous arithmetic, describing
the distribution of something in space, rather
than dividing space itself. 'The number
becomes a subject', it is independent of space:
this happens only with smooth space,
however. Numbers move through this smooth
space. The geometry of smooth space is
'minor, operative' (430), 'a geometry of the
trait'[the geometry of the intensive, one of those
higher order geometries mentioned by DeLanda].
Numbers are movable. They do not just
measure. In nomad culture, the number 'is
the ambulant [camp] fire'. Numbers suggest
directions [as in the flow between two
intensities?]. Numbers are not used to
organize armies on the march [rendered by these
pompous bastards as 'The numbering number is
rhythmic not harmonic']. Sometimes random
numbers are important [with a quote from Dune
on how to walk without attracting the attention of
the Great Worms - hard luck if you have not read
it]. Numbers becomes ciphers [that is
nominals, with all their other characteristics
made irrelevant -the ability to subdivide them,
for example]. It becomes an esprit de
corps [I belong to the chosen few?] and
leads to characteristic strategies such as ambush
and diplomacy [I am reminded of the old Maoist
maxim about marching divided to fight
united]. When it takes the form of a war
machine, this numerical organization looks
impersonal, but 'it is no crueller than the lineal
or state organization' (431). Numbers are
used to select from lineages and to direct action
against the state apparatus: in this sense, they
are themselves a deterritorializing activity which
cuts across lineal territory.
We always encounter complex and articulated
numbers, rather than some large homogenized
quantity. Heterogeneity is present, 'fine
articulation'. State armies attempt to copy
this principle with their own subdivisions, each
with a degree of autonomy and mobility. In
war machines, numbers are used to join together
'weapons, animals and vehicles' in 'a unit of
assemblage'- so one man requires one horse and one
bow, for example, or a more complex weapon
requires a particular size of crew and
animals. The proportion of combatants among
other members can be numbered. Logistics can
develop ['the art of these external relations'],
and is just as important as strategy.
Numbering numbers also act in a 'process of
arithmetic replication or doubling'(432) [the
repetition of the point made above, that lineages
are numbered, but also people are selected to make
up a special numerical body of fighters].
This is essential, and lends autonomy to the
number because a special body corresponding to it
is produced. [Lofty stuff about Genghis Khan
and Moses ensues]. This doubling process
provides the state with its own source of power,
independently of the clans and lineages, although
there are frequent struggles between the two
principles [necessary, our heroes argue, to limit
the powers of chiefs]. [And now in fashionable set
theory] aggregates or sets are numbered, the union
of subsets is performed, one elite subset
corresponds to the united set.
There are various ways to perform the last
operation, and the issue of correspondence also
affects state armies. One solution is to
draw the elite subset from an already privileged
lineage; or to select a representative of each
lineage; or to entrust the fighting to a totally
different exterior element, like foreigners [and
one example is the notion of military slavery with
the Mamelukes]. This sort of policy has led
to some bad publicity for nomads, as child
stealers for example [relating back to an earlier
example of Jewish policy of recruiting the first
born for military service]. At the same
time, the power of outsiders is an important
counter to the power of aristocracies or state
functionaries, although it can also empower chiefs
and their personal whims. For this reason,
there is often an emphasis placed on a particular
kind of becoming - becoming a loyal citizen,
becoming a soldier, while remaining an
outsider. Special schools are needed for
this, and states have often adapted such schools
to provide their own military leaders.
'The nomads have no history; they only have a
geography'(434). The triumph of the state
has led to a dismissal of nomads as backward,
lacking technology, although it is obvious that
they had 'strong metallurgical capabilities'[this
is going to lead to the extraordinary section on
metallurgy], and war machines clearly had some
positive aspects. [Winners' history has led
to] sedentary categories like feudalism being
employed, but what has really happened is that an
imperial state has appropriated the war machine,
and awarded land to warriors to encourage
dependence. Nomad organizations were
perfectly capable of distributing land and
gathering taxes, by producing a more mobile notion
of territoriality and fiscal organization - the
numerical principle again. We can still
detect a genuine nomadic system in terms of
whether land is distributed or occupied.
Much of the modern organization of the state can
be seen as survivals from nomadic systems.
The normal distinction between weapons and tools
is on the base of the usage, but this conceals
intrinsic convertibility, and the distinction is
only recent anyway. In other words 'the same
machinic phylum traverses both' (436). There
are still differences, however, such as weapons
are normally linked with the ability to project or
propel something, something ballistic, even for
handheld weapons. Tools are designed to
domesticate matter and appropriate it, even if it
acts at a distance. Tools meet resistance,
while weapons have to manage counter attacks, 'the
precipitating and inventive factor in the war
machine' (436). There is also a difference
in terms of the relation to movement and
speed. Speed [in this special sense of
immediate relations] is connected to projectile
weapons. War machines help us realize this
vector of speed more generally, as the specific
power of destruction or '"dromocracy" (=
nomos)'. This helps us distinguish between
hunting and war: they are not connected by
evolution, since Virilo says enemies are not seen
as prey, something that possesses a desirable
force to be captured. This is why we find war
machines among nomads who raise animals rather
than hunt them. Projectile systems are
involved in both cases [seeing breeding and
training as projection].
War also requires durable and unlimited violence
[some analysts, like Elias, say that hunting once
did as well]. Breeders want to preserve
'wild animality', and cavalrymen show how to join
human with animal movements in a distinctive
becoming-animal. This also offered an early
release of the speed vector, unconstrained by the
pursuit of prey animals. It is the idea of a
motor force that has been abstracted. Even
the apparent inertia of the war machine at times,
its 'immobility and catatonia', which are
important in war, can be related to the notion of
pure speed. State appropriation of the war
machine depends on managing speed by channeling it
into a striated space. Speed projected with
projectiles depends on immobile soldiers or weapon
systems. The counterattack classically
involves a change of speed to break equilibrium
and recreate smooth space. It could be
argued that speed is also a characteristic of
tools and is not specific to war machines, and
that motors also develop in other areas. But
it is a matter of comparing limited to free
action, which produces relative and absolute kinds
of speed. When we work, we apply a force to
a specific body, but in free action we liberate
elements of the body and work in 'absolutely a non
punctuated space' [all these are 'deductions' from
initial definitions, reassertions of the qualities
of smooth space]. It is a matter of linear
movement compared to vortical: the weapon becomes
almost self propelling. The tool presupposes
work, but the weapon implies a renewal of the
initiating cause.
It is clear that the technical element is
abstract, undetermined, dependent on a machinic
assemblage to provide specific uses and
extensions. These assemblages are
intermediaries that 'the phylum selects, qualifies
and [it] even invents the technical elements'
(439). These assemblages define the
differences between weapons and tools, or not
their intrinsic characteristics. A war
machine assemblage liberates free action, not the
weapons themselves, and the work machine
assemblage does the same for tools. The two
assemblages provide the different notions of
speed. [In one phrase, 'the "war machine"
assemblage [is] formal cause of the
weapons']. The war machine adds speed to
displacement or free action. 'Weapons and
tools are consequences, nothing but consequences'
(440). It is clear that specific weapons
arise from specific military uses and requirements
[the Greek shield from the phalanx, the stirrup
producing the cavalry who required a special
weapon, a lance]. The same goes for specific
tools [deep ploughs if you have a system that
produces long open fields].
Assemblages are 'compositions of desire', and
desire itself is not natural or spontaneous, but
'assembling, assembled, desire'. Assemblages
bring into play passions and desire [the Greek
phalanx involves a change from individuality, the
dismounted cavalryman forms a new relation with
his fellow men. These in turn lead to the
development of new kinds of soldiers like citizen
soldier, or even 'a group homosexual Eros',
441]. However, the assemblages might produce
['mobilize'] passions of different orders,
different effectuations of desire, different
conceptions of justice or pity, for example.
The 'passional regime' of work is directed at
evaluating matter and its resistance, attending to
form and force. Passions of the war machine
turn on 'affects, which relate only to the moving
body in itself', or the counterattack as a
discharge of emotion. This is not the same
as feelings, which are interior: affects [in war
machines only?] 'are projectiles', and are related
to weapons, as in the chivalric novel. In
war machines, absolute immobility is also a part
of the speed vector, producing the specific
'catatonic fits' that precede absolute speed
[according to Kleist again -'a becoming-weapon of
the technical element' combined with 'a
becoming-affect of the passional element'].
Martial arts show the same relation between
immobility and speed, the suspense of affect
before its release [leading to a section on the
martial arts as a matter of following the 'paths
of the affect', rather than a specific code, 442].
There are relations between tools and signs
['essential' ones]. This arises from work in
the modern state, as opposed to the [labour] of
primitive societies. Signs move from bodies
to objects or matter [signs are not associated
with persons any more, but with more abstract
objects]. The State must semiotize activity
by developing writing, in an 'affinity' between
two assemblages, 'signs- tools', and
'writing-organization'[seems you can find
assemblages anywhere]. Weapons are more
associated with jewelry, as in the decorated
weapons of barbarian or nomad art. Such
jewelry 'constitute traits of expression of pure
speed, carried on objects that are themselves
mobile'. They take the relation of
'motif-support'. Despite requiring effort to
produce, 'they are of the order of free action',
not work [they are not utilitarian?]. They
are produced by 'the ambulant smith', who works
metal to produce both weapons and jewelry, and
they show how gold and silver can become 'traits
of expression appropriate to weapons'(443).
Metalworking requires a power of abstraction equal
to, but not the same as, writing. Nomads
borrowed writing from imperial neighbours, but
metallurgy, especially gold and silversmithing is
the characteristic nomadic art. It did not
follow from the creation of a precise code, as in
modes of representation, but offered 'more of a
linear ornamentation'. Runic writing seems
to have been associated with jewelry as an
exception, but that was always limited to
expressing signatures, or short messages of war or
love [obscure references to Danish writing].
Again we see the results of assemblages affecting
traits differently. Thus music and drugs are
associated with nomadic war machines, but
architecture and cooking with the state.
What we are pointing to is five differences in the
assemblages of nomads and states: directions
[outward as projection or inward as introjection];
vector [speed or gravity]; the model [free action
or work]; the expression [jewelry or written
signs]; the passional or desiring totality
[affects or feelings]. Technologies of
various kinds are made uniform by the state, but
they can still enter into new assemblages and
other relations, and help reinvent war machines,
as in revolutions and popular wars. There is
'a schizophrenic taste' for converting tools to
weapons, and vice versa. 'Everything is
ambiguous' (444) [the usual insurance clause at
the end of each section]. We might even come
to see rebels as 'Transhistorical', drawing on
work and war, travelling 'down a shared line of
flight'. Certainly, the warrior has long had
turned into a military man, and the worker into a
functionary, but the old tendencies can still
reappear - men of war who know all of its dangers,
workers who want to engage in resistance and
technological liberation from work. These do
not just draw upon past tendencies, but can form
'the new figures of a transhistorical
assemblage'(445). They find themselves
caricatured in the figure of the military adviser
and the technocrats. They must resist the
temptation to go back to mythical times. The
point is to bring together 'worker and warrior
masses of a new type', and to harness the 'virtual
changes of knowledge and action' that arise from
the world order itself, and use those in new
assemblages, borrowing from war machine and work
machine [they must have had Italian autonomists in
mind, as Lotringer suggests].
The nomads were very innovative when it comes to
war, especially in inventing weapons, including
combinations of men and animals. Their
metallurgy was also particularly innovative,
producing breakthroughs such as the bronze axe or
the iron sword, particular variations of heavy and
light armament, such as sabres to deal with
infantry, and heavy iron swords for frontal
attacks. We can trace the migration of these
weapons to migrations of nomads. The usual
view is that these innovations stopped with the
advent of firearms, but nomadic inputs were also
important: eventually, only the necessary heavy
investment that the state could provide limited
innovation. This is controversial, and it is
not always easy to disentangle the contribution of
nomads, however [lots of amazing details about who
invented the sabre, 446]. There is often
prejudice about nomads too.
Much depends on the independent role played by
metallurgists, who are not always controlled
carefully by the state apparatus, and who
communicated innovations among themselves, along
'a technological line or continuum' (447).
Metallurgy is one of those activities move that is
hard to codify into a science, since there is much
variation with raw materials, alloys, and the
operations that can be performed - in other words
singularities or 'spatiotemporal haecceities',
requiring transformation. There are also
'affective qualities or traits of expression'
associated with the singularities and operations
on them (448) [making a sabre is then
described in terms of transforming
singularities]. We have discovered 'a
machinic phylum', with 'the constellation of
singularities, prolongable by certain
operations… [which produce]… several
assignable traits of expression'.. Where the
singularities or operations diverge, there are
different phyla, and each phylum has its own
singularities, qualities and so on which
'determine the relation of desire to the technical
elements'[just a silly way of saying weapons
develop according to the purposes to which they
are to be put?]. Nevertheless the different
phyla can converge, since singularities can be
'prolonged', in a flow of matter and movement
between them, producing 'a single machinic
phylum'. Flows are both human and natural;
they take more concrete forms as assemblage,
'every constellation of singularities and traits
deducted from the flow'['deducted' means both
deduced and subtracted, as in the definition of
the rhizome?].
Assemblages can operate at different scales, with
very large constellations appearing as cultures or
even 'ages', producing differentiated phyla or
flows at different levels, selecting among
[disrupting] different possible continuities, and
producing differentiated lineages within an over
arching machinic phylum. Thus particular
singularities, such as 'the chemistry of carbon'
(449), will be selected, organized and used in a
particular assemblage. This implies a number
of very different lines, some phylogenetic[links
between blowpipes and cannon] , some ontogenetic,
operating within one assemblage, sometimes passing
it on to other assemblages [the example is the
horseshoe which spread through different
assemblages]. Just as assemblages select, so
the phylum displays 'evolutionary reaction' as it
moves along various threads, develops assemblages,
or leaves them - 'vital impulse?'. Some
authors have argued for technological vitalism,
positing a universal tendency dealing with all
sorts of singularities and traits of expression -
our heroes prefer a 'machinic phylum in
variation'.
This flow of matter and energy is 'destratified,
deterritorialized'. It can be seen in
Husserl's notion of vague essences, which are
neither formed things nor formal essences [and
have been discussed above], 'fuzzy aggregates'
(450), referring to corporeality rather than
thinghood. This corporeality lies beneath
changes of state of bodies, transformations, and
occupies 'a space-time itself anexact', but it
also contains expressive and intensive qualities
producing variable affects. This is what
causes 'ambulant couplings, events -
affects'. Husserl tried to use the term to
bridge the formally essential and the sensible,
but D and G want to see it [roundness is the
example] differently - 'as a threshold-affect
(neither flat nor pointed) and as a limit-process
(becoming rounded)', appearing as sensible things
and technical agents like wheels or lathes, but
itself autonomous: it produces 'a vague identity'
between things and thoughts [could be one of the
processes of differenTiation discussed in Difference and
Repetition?]
This is similar to other criticisms of the 'matter
- form model' which assume too much homogeneity,
partly because this is necessary if you want to
develop laws. This is the hylomorphic model,
which ignores activity and affect. However,
'energetic materiality' is implied in the ways in
which singularities become forms, and change takes
place [including resistance of the material, as
when wood fights back]. There are also
'variable intensive affects' affecting our
operations on material [the example is the
porosity of wood or its elasticity].
Craftsmen know that they should take these into
account rather than imposing a form on a matter,
treating the wood as 'a materiality possessing a
nomos' (451), material traits of expression.
We can translate these characteristics into a
formal model, but not without distorting them,
making variables fixed, imposing equations rather
than seeing them as 'immanent to matter - movement
(inequations, adequations)'. Such
translations are legitimate, but they lose
something. We need to think instead of
'perpetually variable continuous modulation'
between form and matter, fully recognizing an
intermediary dimension 'of energetic, molecular
dimension'.
We get a fuller picture of materiality by thinking
of the machinic phylum, matter in movement,
conveying singularities and traits of
expression. We can only follow such flows,
as artisans have always known. We can define
proper artisans as those who have gone off to find
the raw materials in the first place, and not have
them brought to them, which makes them merely
workers. Following the machinic phylum makes
proper artisans ambulant, following the flow,
'intuition in action'(452).
However, there is also the 'transhumant', on a
different sort of journey [the examples given are
farmer or animal raiser - their favourite
nomads. The term does NOT imply something
that exceeds humanity, but a human being who makes
transitions, like those who pasture their animals
on moorland in the summer and lowland in the
winter]. They trace a circuit not a flow,
and only follow parts of a flow, becoming
'itinerant only consequentially'. Merchants
can be transhumant when they travel only to get
things for markets. Nomads are not
transhumant, nor migrants, although they can
become these afterwards. Sometimes, smooth
space itself forces them to be itinerants or
transhumants, and mixed forms are common.
'But...we have wandered from the question' (453)
[!], And we need to get back to the role played by
metals in the machinic phylum. It is this
that accounts for the relation between itinerance
and metallurgy. Metals and their
characteristics help us to see this stuff about
corporeality and intermediary dimensions, better
than does, say, the relations between other raw
materials like wood or clay. Those materials
seem to validate the hylomorphic model as a fixed
process going through a series of thresholds, but
with metal, operations are more fluid, revealing
its 'energetic materiality', and providing
transformations that exceed fixed forms.
[One example is the need to quench metal even
after you have formed it to, or to continually
decarbonize steel, or to melts down one form to
reuse it - the 'ingot-form' was particularly
significant, as the basis for money]. Metals
seem particularly rigid and fixed, but they turn
out to be quite variable, just as does music - 'a
widened chromaticism sustains both music and
metallurgy'. The characteristics of matter
are brought to life, its 'material vitalism' that
is not so apparent elsewhere. [Getting into
their stride] 'metallurgy is the consciousness or
thought of the matter flow' (454). Metals
are everywhere, 'the conductor of all matter' [and
see DeLanda on
the role of metals in developing various kinds of
useful syntheses]. The machinic phylum 'has
a metallic head as its itinerant probe head or
guidance device'. Thought is born from
metal, 'metallurgy is minor science in person,
"vague" science or the phenomenology of
matter'. 'Metal is neither a thing nor an
organism, but a body without organs'. It has
always been closely connected with alchemy because
of its ability to demonstrate the 'immanent power
of corporeality'
[Let's hear it for artisans], 'the first and
primary itinerant'. They follow the matter
flow. Their ability to work metal has led
them to form collective bodies like secret
societies. They relate with farmers and with
state functionaries, but they also relate to
forest dwellers and nomads, because they have to
go where the mines are: 'Every mine is a line of
flight, that is in communication with smooth
spaces—there are parallels today in the problems
with oil'(455).
Mines are not important in all empires, so the
metal had to be acquired in some other way,
through trade, leading to the necessity for
politics and commerce. Again the role of
nomads and smiths have been underestimated [in the
accounts which they happen to be
criticizing]. Mines are particularly
interesting locations to examine 'flow, mixture,
and escape', political struggles including those
waged by alliances of miners. It is not
enough to operate at the level of feelings, 'the
usual platitudes' about ambivalence attached to
smiths - the reason for this ambivalence lies in
the social relations between smiths, nomads and
sedentaries and the 'the type of affects they
invent (metallic affect)' (456). Smiths are
themselves others and therefore have 'particular
affective relations with the sedentaries and the
nomads'[affects here meaning something that
affects you from the outside].
Smiths are always ambulant. They live in
temporary accommodation, 'like metal itself, in
the manner of a cave or a hole'[a certain Faure is
then used to describe itinerant people in India
who tend to create dwellings based on holes and
tunnels. In the minds of our delirious
heroes, there is a connection with Eisenstein and
the film Strike!, which shows 'a holey
space where a disturbing group of people are
rising', image on page 457]. Itinerants
passed through striated and smooth space 'without
stopping at either one', and metallurgists are
suspected of double betrayal as a result --
neither farmers nor animal raisers. They
have the mark of Cain. They feature in
various kinds of myth about strange invading
peoples.
Smiths display 'internal itinerancy', with their
vague essence. With their construction of
holey spaces, they can communicate with
sedentaries and nomads, and others, including
transhumants: 'holey space itself communicates
with smooth space and striated space' (458).
They are doubled, mixed. In Dogon society,
they have restricted marriage opportunities.
In other empires, they have been both mobile and
captured. They are reduced to the status of
the worker, but this encounters a problem in that
they are also prospectors with links to the
outside, to merchants. The ingot form linked
them to other metallurgists in 'a line of
variation'. They make both tools and
weapons. Their activities have diverged, for
example in producing different artistic
forms. We can explain this in terms of how
the machinic phylum 'has two different modes of
liaison', 'always connected to nomad space,
whereas it conjugates with sedentary space'.
When it connects with nomadic assemblages and war
machines, it takes the form of a rhizome 'with its
gaps, detours, subterranean passages, stems,
openings, traits, holes etc.', But when sedentary
assemblages capture the phylum and codify its
traits of expression, 'a whole regime of
arborescent conjunctions' arises.
[Last lap. We're going to link together the
war machine as a kind of expression, with
metallurgy as its corresponding content. The
thrilling diagram below is found on 459, just to
give us practice with Hjelmslev].
How do actual battles relate to war machines, and
how does the war machine relate to the state
apparatus? In the first case, battles
themselves can be both sought and avoided - with
guerrilla warfare as an example of the latter
[especially in the case of DH Lawrence, whom they
admire]. War also escalates beyond battles
into total war. However, guerrilla war and
'proper' war borrow from each other. We
certainly cannot argue that war is the same as the
battle. Similarly, war machines need not
necessarily have the war as their object - they
can organize a raid, for example. The war
machine was originally a nomadic invention to
occupy smooth space as its 'sole and veritable
positive object (nomos)' (460). We only get
military action when war machines collide with
states or cities. In this sense, war itself
supplements or necessarily accompanies the war
machine, but war machines can develop without
having war in mind at first—the example is Moses
only gradually coming to realize that he will have
to fight.
States were not originally formed to make war
either, and were able to dominate people using
other agencies like the police. However,
they soon learned from nomad war machines and
their success. The problem then became to
appropriate the war machine, and this changes the
original functions of the nomadic war machine:
only then does the state war machine focus on war
itself as its object. There is a great deal
of historical variation in terms of how this
happened. The nomad war machine did not aim
centrally at war, and so it was vulnerable to
being appropriated - 'the hesitation of the nomad
is legendary' (461), quite rightly because the
options are to return to the desert or be
incorporated into an empire [Genghis Khan managed
a compromise, they argue]. At the same time,
the state takes a risk when it appropriates the
war machine since it can require an enormous
system to subdue it.
There are other differences in the concrete forms
that state appropriated war machines can take -
whether to have a professional or conscripted
army, for example, or whether to fully integrate
the military or simply admit a particular caste of
warriors. We find mixtures and
transitions. The means of appropriation also
varies, for example between using 'territoriality,
work or public works, taxation' (462). Each
has its disadvantages.
Clausewitz famously argued that '"War is the
continuation of politics by other means"' (463),
but this is so only in a particular context or
aggregate, assuming a particular kind of war aimed
at bringing down enemies; wars submitted to state
aims and effectively pursued by states; the
management of the swing between limited and total
war. If we look at real wars not idealized
ones, we run into the problem that war machines do
not necessarily have war as their object [I think
the point here is to suggest other possibilities
which lead to a criticism of Clausewitz].
The nomad war machine was 'the content adequate to
the Idea'[the inspiration for the concept?].
[In their perverse way, they argue that this pure
war machine was only realized by nomads, who
therefore remain as an abstraction, because they
are not a pure category. They want to
preserve this notion of the ideal war machine,
which is not the same as the military or the state
version, and only actually turns to war once it
has been allied to the state - maybe, 464].
It is state appropriation of the war machine that
requires investigation, how it evolves into total
war [see DeLanda].
Capitalism is clearly a factor here, with its
development of constant and variable capital, so
that whole peoples get involved, turning
eventually into total war. There is a
tendency for war to exceed political limits and to
pursue unlimited objects: states unleash a war
machine which becomes greater than them. A
crucial figure here is fascism embracing war 'with
no other aim than itself', or but there is also a
postfascist figure focused on peace and the need
to dominate the whole earth to secure it, 'a form
of peace more terrifying still', a state formed
smooth space. The war machine dominates in
the name of order, moving beyond state control.
Thus the war machine has become stronger and
stronger 'as in a science fiction story'
(465). The enemies are no longer clearly
specified. A mixture of local wars and anti
guerrilla wars have ensued. However [and
there always is a however], advanced capitalism
also can 'continually recreate unexpected
possibilities for counterattack, or unforeseen
initiatives determining revolutionary, popular,
minority, mutant machines'. Anxiety about
unspecified enemies shows this.
War machines always have had a variable relation
to actual war. They have two poles:
destruction and war become objects without limits
as we have just seen; the other pole, which
'seemed to be the essence' (466) takes as its
object 'not war but the drawing of a creative line
of flight , the composition of a smooth space and
of the movement of people in that space', with
actual war as only a supplementary, which can even
be directed against the state.
The assignation of the war machine to nomads was
'done only in the historical interest' of showing
the ambiguity and shifts between these two
poles. Nomads themselves are not essential:
they 'do not hold the secret'. Artists or
other ideological movements can turn into a war
machine if they construct a plane of consistency,
act 'in relation to a phylum', a line of flight, a
smooth space. This constellation defines the
nomad and not the other way about. Modern
forms of people's war do conform to the essence of
a war machine if they 'simultaneously create
something else'. There are always dangers,
in that lines of flight can become lines of
destruction, and planes of consistency can become
'planes of organization and domination', and the
two poles interrelate and can borrow from each
other, as in the construction of a smooth space
by capitalist war machines. Luckily,
'the earth assert its own powers of
deterritorialization, it's lines of flight, its
smooth spaces that live and blaze their way for a
new earth' (467). The trick will be to
manage the incommensurable quantities in the war
machine, steering it towards the right pole.
If we manage this trick, we can use the war
machine against the apparatuses that appropriate
it [leading to ch.13].
back to menu page
|
|