Notes on: De Certeau,
M.(1984) The
Practice of Everyday Life,
University of California Press:
Berkeley
by Dave
Harris
This is a
particularly difficult book to
summarize. It is written in a
deliberately poetic style and the
argument is very academic, and
pretty self referential [that is
referring to de Certeau’s
contemporaries and to then current
debates in French philosophy]. I
have tried to extract the main
points which interested me -- one
of the earlier sections which sets
out his position as against
Foucault and Bourdieu, and one of
the most commonly cited chapters,
on walking in the city. Some of
the other chapters are very worth
while reading, on topics which
range from railway journeys,
through the difference between
tours and maps to some interesting
analyses of storytelling. As for
the beautiful style, and the dense
citation of examples, I hope you
know my approach by now -- I tend
to cheerfully and rather brutally
abstract one or two points and
render them in very plain English.
The General Introduction,
which offers a very useful summary
of the main themes, but which
makes more sense once you have
read the book, tells us that this
book is about the 'ordinary man'
[usual apologies for the gendered
terminology], who existed before
texts and any attempt to represent
him or his activities, especially
in the form of numbers. Everyday
practices are to be foregrounded
and articulated. This is not an
analysis of individuals, since
social relations are always
involved: indeed, the 'individual'
is but a plurality of these
relations. For that matter,
culture is best understood as
'systems of organizational
combination' (xi). It is about a
very ancient operational logic of
disguise and survival The goal is
to understand consumers, and how
they 'poach'.
This book is
about the uses consumers make of
the things that they purchase, for
example the uses of TV images.
Such usage reveals a hidden
'poesis', which is diffuse and not
offered a privileged space. An
example might be the way in which
Indians subverted the culture of
their Spanish colonizers, or what
students do to university culture,
or how individual sentences are
constructed on the basis of shared
vocabulary and syntax. And the
idea of a speech act can be used
to understand activities such as
walking or cooking.
There is an
argument with Foucault and his
work in Discipline and
Punish... In that book the
micro physics of power is
explained in some detail, but
which networks and resources help
people resist and evade the
discipline offered by
institutions? The disciplinary
functions in institutions are
deflected by tactics: the
participants offer an
anti-discipline. We need to
understand the logic of these
practices, the rules they obey.
Some examples are collected in
this work -- by readers, urban
users, those who engage in
everyday rituals, or use memory,
or interact in families, or while
cooking.
There is a need to
review some famous work on the
unconscious in Bourdieu, some on
anthropological bricolage, some on
ethnomethodology, and some on
formal logics of action. The
ordinary uses of language are
important. It is difficult to
study these matters because they
are so fleeting and dispersed.
Consuming activity, for example,
is widespread but little studied:
and it is 'unsigned, unreadable
and unsymbolized' (xvii). The
notion of tactics lends a
'political dimension to everyday
practices'. Consumers
develop their own erratic
'trajectories', 'unforeseeable
sentences, partly unreadable
paths'. These cannot be described
by formal analysis, including
statistics. They feature bricolage
and discursivenss, and lack the
homogeneity required by analysis.
There is a
difference between strategies and
tactics. Strategies
require a subject (an enterprise
or city and so on) separated from
an environment. They also require
a 'proper' place [later described
as a regularized, rule governed,
institutionalized location] from
which to generate relations with
an exterior (their competitors or
clients and so on). Strategies lie
behind political and economic
rationality. Tactics, on
the other hand, have no 'proper'
localization, and are not strongly
separated from the other. Indeed,
they often take place in the
territory of the other. They are
opportunistic, always on the
watch, and involve combining
disparate elements to gain a
momentary advantage.
Lots of everyday
practices are tactical in this
sense. They often involve
victories of the week over the
strong, via 'clever tricks,
knowing how to get away with
things, manoeuvres...'(xix). These
in turn are based on really
ancient, maybe even natural
survival techniques. It might be
possible to classify tactics
according to classifications of
rhetorical techniques.
The point for the
observer is to describe these
tactics without taking them over
and packaging them in terms of
some general theory. Reading, for
example, looks passive, but it is
an activity, a 'silent
production', involving
improvisation, the use of memory
to connect elements from other
texts, or activities such as
skipping. The world of the author
is really only 'rented' by readers
(xxi). Reading is as mobile as
conversation.
Everyday practices
are about spaces, for example
about inhabiting spaces. Space is
another accessible term, but an
important one. It has a role in
the increasing abstractions
pursued by science as well
[futurology is the rather odd
example cited here -- I think this
point makes more sense a bit lower
down]. Science also offers
combinations of formal discourses
and 'ancient tricks', masquerading
as methods -- these are tactical
too.
We need to rescue
the individual from their absence
and from systems, which is a
political problem again and we
need to rescue social relations
too. The hero here is the 'man
without qualities' [the title of a
famous novel by Musil. I have
always read this as a critique of
the modern soulless bureaucrat or
narcissist, but de Certeau reminds
us that this character is also a
sensible pragmatist, seeking
happiness from what is available,
and in the accumulation of small
pleasures. I still think he's a
prat!].
Chapter
IV
This chapter is
about Foucault and Bourdieu, and
how they connect the everyday to
notion such as ideology and
habitus. The critique begins by
denying the originality of
authorship, including de Certeau’s
own originality: there is always a
network of writings, and
influences are not easily accessed
-- for example, some work
contradicts an unacknowledged
author.
Foucault's work
suggests that everyday procedures
are not always articulated in
discourse. So what is the relation
between these procedures and
discourse? If we look at Discipline...
we find an example of the
colonization of reformist
projects. The struggle against the
feudal regime is materially
assisted by techniques, and
practicalities, and details. These
matters are described as a
semi-autonomous force. Similarly,
one effect arises from the
construction of special spaces in
prisons, via practices such as
'gridding': these activities are
duplicated in the social sciences.
Again, these important practices
are non-discursive.
In his more
general work, on archaeology,
Foucault selects from a number of
social activities and then traces
these back in order to explain
them. For example, we get the
optical and panoptical procedures
dominating the account, which
somehow emerge from a huge mass of
detailed policies and plans. But
what privileges these particular
procedures? What about all the
others that did not go on to
generate powerful discourses?
Foucault tells us that these other
practices are innumerable, [and
denies some common ways of
suggesting how particular ones
emerge as dominant -- in marxism,
for example]. Foucault himself
imposes a coherence. There is no
reason why these omitted
procedures could not colonize the
established ones -- surely the
development of institutions shows
the effects of these other
non-discursive practices, once
they're established?Disciplinary
procedures are given their proper
place in Foucault, but what about
the displaced ones?
Bourdieu,
like Foucault, seems to need
distant examples in order to
clarify current French practices
[in his Outline
of a Theory of Practice, which
is the text being discussed here.
Bourdieu begins by discussing his
own field work in Kabylia --
Algeria -- and then generalises
his theory of practice. I think
this is a clever point by de
Certeau, though, and it is
developed in more detail below. To
be brutal about this, the argument
is that exotic and foreign
examples are needed because they
seem to be so external and
objective to the theory -- the
theorist can then innocently use
these as examples to validate the
theory. The true connection is
that the theory is closely
involved in the description of
these examples in the first place,
as we shall see].
The notion of habitus
is based on this anthropology too,
as an abstraction from it. The
analysis then tries to use
anthropology to generate
sociological theory, and in the
process admits that which is
impenetrable and exterior,
anything which is unknowable. The
analysis cleverly shows how the
interiors of Kabylian dwellings
come to represent social order, a
problem for orthodox sociology.
This involves both analysis of the
data and the construction of a
theory.
What Bourdieu does
is to isolate 'strategies' from
his descriptions [for example, the
way certain ambiguities in the
official calendar can be exploited
to serve the interests of dominant
groups].This is of course an
abstraction, which assumes that
relationships between families and
their environments and texts are
the same in every case. What is
really happening is that
practitioners themselves are
concealing the specific
differences in order to help the
observer clarify [which is a point
Bourdieu makes himself, explaining
how participants do much of the
work in reconciling their
statements with theoretical
categories].
Other variability
is also lost. For example, the
basic principles of a marriage are
not binding, so some degree of
tolerance and variability must
exist, and there are several other
cases where explicit rules are
limited, and traditions can be
played off against each other --
'like students maintaining a high
grade point average'
(54).Strategies arise when people
choose among traditions: these are
never simply 'applied'.[Again,
this is all in Bourdieu 's own
account]. What Bourdieu does is to
go on and abstract useful
properties from these traditions
and rules, such as their
substitutability, or the way they
may be used in analogies (long
seen as the basis of creative
thought, hardly needing to be
discovered from fieldwork).
Apparently, underlying principles
govern strategies, such as the
needs to maximize wealth or
preserve the body, and again these
are associated with the interior
'place’ or habitation.
Are these
principles always uniformly
related to actual practices?
Bourdieu manages deviant cases by
insisting that tactics always have
to be properly grounded in wealth
or the maintenance of the body: in
this way he glosses anomalous
practices. He has a strange
definition of strategies as well,
insisting that these are not
deployed in a calculating manner
but through a set of assumptions
[which is where habitus comes
in]. This is 'a cleverness which
does not recognize itself as such'
(56), and is a way of going back
to traditional ethnography where
action was understood as
unconscious, coherent, and
repetitive, based on roots
('places'), which can only be
discovered by the ethnographer
following theoretical abstraction.
Bourdieu simply
omits the issue of how structures
lead to practices. There are lots
of assumptions here generally --
that objective structures can only
be uncovered by sociological
discourse, for example. Bourdieu
manages to deny both sociological
determinism and the idea of a
calculating subject, so he has to
revert to mechanisms in the
sociology of education to explain
how structures actually work --
through knowledge acquisition, the
interiorisation of structures, and
then the exteriorisation of the
results of learning in the habitus.
This invisible habitus is
responsible for subsequent action,
rather than specific processes.
This process
involves a movement from
structure, which is a sociological
construct, to habitus, an assumed
reality, to the interpretation of
observed facts. Foreign examples
assist here in lending this model
coherence -- in this specific
case, some kind of primeval habitus
is supposed to be detected,
represented in the dwelling of the
Kabylia. This poses as a concrete
illustration, but Bourdieu focuses
mostly on its form rather than its
content, since its main role is to
illustrate the general theory. No
doubt it helps generate further
research, too! (59).[It is worth
pointing out that Bourdieu replies
to many of these criticisms,
mostly by denying them, in his
later work Pascalian
Meditations. See also his
meditations on methodology, or
rather on understanding].
So instead of a
concrete examination of tactics,
we get some 'violently imposed
truths', and instead of
complexity, dogmatic reason. This
is a way of domesticating the
impact of tactics on theory --
they are either subsumed under
normal rationality, or declared as
a matter for the unconscious. In
fact, a serious attention to
tactics would offer a real
challenge to scientific theory.
Tactics proliferate and resist
classification. They are singular
and unconscious. Bourdieu is torn
between acknowledging complexity
and adhering to sociology, and has
to resort to tactics himself,
including the very common one of
'affirming... the contrary of what
he knows' (60). Instead of telling
us about the Kabylia en route to
the concept of habitus, he
might have told us about his own
scientific dogmatism instead!
Chapter V
Several theorists
have tried to offer a discourse on
nondiscursive practices. This is
usually been managed by
interrogating a limited field of
activity, but that always leaves a
remainder, something excluded by
theory and method. The process of
application of theories is rather
like following a recipe in
cooking.
Turning to
Foucault and Bourdieu again, both
isolate a field of foreign
objects, Panoptical procedures or
Kabylian strategies. These are
assumed to be a metonym for
practices as a whole. The notion
of a field is then used to
illuminate the theory. The
exhaustive nature of details
gathered from different sources
illustrates universality for
Foucault. The notion of habitus
for Bourdieu shows an apparent
single principle for all the
examples. The principles of
construction of the theory are
then forgotten, although they are
really the same as for the ones
studied.
For Durkheim and
Freud, there is a similar attempt
to isolate a foreign and primitive
place (Australia for Durkheim, and
the unconscious for Freud). These
areas were literally foreign to
them too -- Durkheim never visited
Australia (and Marx never visited
a factory). This is a classic
'figure of modernity' (64) --
those foreign places are familiar
and ever-present now, yet they
were once far away, secret, and to
be theorized.
There seems to be
a classic procedure for all
theory: 'methods' have to be found
to domesticate something that is
foreign, to impose the
'fundamental schema of a
discourse' (65). Methodological
'know how' is involved, involving
a certain ingenious knowledge or
craft. Attempts to describe it
have taken a number of forms, such
as the distinction between art and
science [below]. However, the area
has been left largely unexamined,
certainly when compared to
discourses or to the elaborate
hermeneutics practised on texts.
The same goes for 'practice' as
opposed to theory. Theory emerges
at the top of a hierarchy of ways
of knowing, usually on the basis
that it is more 'reflexive',
although such reflection is still
very limited [couldn't agree more,
especially in educational theory,
which features a very rapid
retreat to the 'practical' or the
immediately 'relevant'].
The old
distinctions between art and
science, which used to carry this
discussion, are no less helpful,
because art also has a set of
abstract techniques which can even
be mechanized. Non-technical arts
have been devalued, although they
are still there, invisible, a
remainder.
The key technique
to manage and domesticate is
narrative, which once led to the
dominance of literary knowledge as
the key to understanding. Literary
knowledge is a good example of
privileged knowledge that is in
fact unstatable, a matter of
discernment or taste [this
literary aesthetic is also
apparent in the works of Foucault
and Bourdieu? And in the work of
de Certeau too?].
Freudian analysis
assumes some privileged knowledge,
which is supposed to appear
through symptoms, and which can
only be discovered by science, not
an ordinary consciousness. This
too is characteristic of modern
theory, which involves looking at
and showing. It is often
contrasted favourably to the
uncodified 'know how' of artisans.
This claim is also found in Kant's
exaltation of 'judgment'-- an
apparent balance between science
and know- how, between concrete
experience and universal
principles. However, such balance
and judgment is found commonly in
it every day life too, as in the
practice of 'la perruque’
[literally, a cosmetic wig. The
term originated to describe the
practice of workmen using the
bosses' time and materials to
create goods of their own .De
Certeau uses the term much more
widely, to include any practice of
'poaching' from an employer --
using company envelopes for your
own mail, for example]. This
practice is also a combination of
moral freedom, aesthetic creation,
and practical art.
Since Kant,
aesthetics has slowly become
isolated and codified, and the
discipline gradually becomes a
matter of relating theory to
practice. [Such relations always
subordinate and marginalize
practice -- as de Certeau says,
the last stage is to try and
develop a theory of practice,
precisely as do Foucault and
Bourdieu].
Chapter VI
Practice as an
activity in its own right
gradually slips from attention,
and becomes merely a source of
data to be explained by theory,
often via this pantomime of
originating somewhere else.
Practice itself is rarely
analyzed, except in the form of a
statement about it by someone, a
narration. These narrations:
(a)
Organize the construction of
objects, but are taken as objects
for theory themselves
(b)
Are integral to the theory of
practices, not just 'evidence' or
'case studies',or some remainder
outside discourse. We need to
revalue the structure of folk
tales, and the 'art of speaking',
not as something Other to theory,
but as a variant of a 'discourse
that knows and an authority in
what concerns theory' (78).
Narrations of this
kind are linked to practical
operations too --'the same
practices appear now in a verbal
field, now in a field of
non-linguistic actions' (78).
Narrations therefore are never
just descriptive, but involve the
creation of 'fictional space'
(79), which helps people escape
from, and 'balance with' the
present. For example, people tell
proverbs or a story to make a
point, as part of an art of
saying. Such utterances are not to
be taken literally. Foucault
happens to be very good at this
technique too, using rhetoric and
description -- ‘he makes what he
says appear evident to the public
he has in view' (79). He pretends
to be not there, he pretends to be
'eclipsed by the erudition and the
taxonomies that [his theory]
manipulates' (80). Theory as well
as folk tales clearly show a link
between narratives and tactics.
Detienne [who he?]
has collected and admired such
folk stories. He claims there are
no deeper meanings in them,
nothing 'outside'. Instead of
theorizing about them, in some
'museogeographical alteration', he
recites stories instead (80).
Storytellers get lost in their
stories, but they also actively
interpret them. A basic
intelligence is uncovered in these
stories, sleights of hand, flair,
sagacity, the use of stratagems
and so on. Stories are always
related to the situation of the
moment. They can take on disguise,
using masks and metaphors, to undo
the properness of place [to appear
innocent, yet turn out to be
sneakily critical]. Good stories
also aim at the invisibility of
their practice [de Certeau also
refers to the ‘recit’ here. Film
buffs might know this as a common
form of French cinema, where an
off-camera voice tells a story
which is illustrated by the images
and action that we see -- try The
Hairdresser's Husband. As
with much off-screen commentary,
of course, it is not really
innocent description that we're
getting, but interpretation].
These techniques are designed to
produce a maximum of effects, as
an aesthetic. A great deal of
experience is important in
storytelling, involving the
ability to link the story with
other elements stored in memory
(and in the memories of the
audience). Experience is used to
multiply the possibilities [to
embellish in ways the audience can
understand, to develop additional
points, to add notes of humour or
other emotions, to make things
relevant -- sounds exactly like a
description of good teaching to
me]. [NB This is the kind of
narrative that Lyotard
sees as heavily undermined in
public life?]
There are
important qualitative dimensions
to telling effective stories as
well: memory can alter space, and
destabilize equilibrium. Memory
can disestablish order, since it
is invisible and thus escapes
power. Local order can be
disrupted [there are some rather
odd examples here, apparently
indicating how past knowledge can
disrupt present social relations,
or refer to miracles, transforming
moments from the past, with
destabilizing effects. I found it
hard to think of some homely
examples of this of my own. Maybe
it is the sort of thing that
happens when aged relatives bring
out some memory of the past which
reduces the authority of the
present generation, or when people
recall the humble origins of great
rulers in their presence --
whispering about Caesar's
mortality in the great man's ear?]
The introduction of memory
completes the tactical repertoire
of a story teller, permitting them
to take advantage of an
opportunity to transform. Memory
is always active in this way, and
constantly on the watch for
opportunities of this kind
[remembering precedents in
arguments about power relations
seems to be hinted at here, or
remembering past promises that
have not been kept, possibly, or
reminding present rulers of their
past obligations?]. In this way,
story tellers can gain authority
even though they have no power
(87).
Tactical moves of
this kind display:
(a)
alteration, in that they are
essentially other, secret,
something which is allowed to
emerge, something operative in
relationships. This otherness is
killed by institutionalization in
'proper places', [with official
records?] The example here is the
power of repartee [the example I
thought of was the marvellous
power of hecklers to disrupt the
smooth patter of politicians by
introducing topics that they have
not scripted].
(d)
singularity, in that memory
provides a number of possible
fragments, each one of which acts
as a metonym [which individualizes
storytelling and also makes it
impossible to script or contain?]
The amount of detail provides
power to the storyteller.
(c)
mobility, where memory provides
the opportunity for movement, as
when a recalled fragment is able
to mobilize a whole ensemble of
knowledge and emotions [in another
homely example, I thought of
occasions where I have been thrown
off course myself in the middle of
a lecture, say, by being reminded
that I have told the same joke
before, which immediately
denaturalizes my approach, and
reveals some of the artifice in
it].
The maintenance of
a proper place means meant that
memory and time must be
controlled, for example by
'scientific writing' (89). But
stories haunt science as well as
every day life. Tricks of the
storyteller include reversing the
significance of the story by the
inclusion of one detail [the only
example I can think of right away
is a rather literary one, Balzac's
Sarrasine, which, as
Barthes remind us, uses a number
of clever devices to convince the
main victim in the story that the
object of his love is a woman,
only to reveal finally that the
‘woman’ is a castrato -- the
'detail' of the castration
immediately changes everything and
turns the romantic love story into
a farce. Turning to sociology, I
have heard colleagues 'go through
the motions' of giving a 'fair'
account of the work of Althusser,
and then end with innocently
including the 'detail' that he had
killed his wife. Unsurprisingly,
it is that detail that students
tend to remember, and they give it
great importance in evaluating
Althusser’s work]. An effective
story is able to 'compose
harmonies... doing it by surprise'
(90) . [There is a strong
implication here, of course that
these tricks are found in
scientific writing too, maybe in
the work of the sociological
theorists discussed earlier on. De
Certeau also reminds us that
pulling off these rhetorical
tricks is a source of pleasure in
its own right, and may even be the
central pleasure in academic
writing]..
Chapter VII Walking
in the City
This piece offers
both a poetic and a semiotic
analysis, and can be seen as an
extension to the famous work on
the flaneur -- although this is
about ordinary people rather than
those extraordinary academics and
bourgeois who got pleasure from
wandering around cities looking at
people, but never communicating
with them.
The story begins
with looking down on the city of
New York from the top of the World
Trade Centre, and enjoying the
pleasures of seeing the city laid
out below. The pleasures are
voyeuristic ones, of course, and
this leads de Certeau to speculate
that any such holistic perspective
trying to look down on life and to
map it neatly as a whole is
equally voyeuristic. Obviously,
this includes using some abstract
general theory in social science
to understand every day life. You
need to get down onto the street
itself, to get a perspective of
the city as most people see it
The pedestrians on
the streets down below read the
city as a text, but, crucially
they also write it. They do not
have a single map or picture of
the city but a series of
‘migrational metaphors’ for it,
which change as they actually
walk. As with the city, so with
the State, which likewise is not
seen in some simple holistic terms
but as a conglomeration of
properties.
Every day
understanding is managed by
speculative and classificatory
operations. These always generate
contradictions, as social extremes
are encountered, for example. They
are impossible to administer
rationally, consisting of 'ruses
and combinations of power' (page
156). Thus the apparent decay of
the city, seen from above by
politicians and administrators (and
academics) is not supported by the
people who actually live or walk
in it.
This offers the
reciprocal of Foucault's analysis
of the mechanisms of top-down
power. However, space and spatial
practices are equally important in
coming to understand everyday
life, which can elude power and
discipline [we
can start see this by using
spatial metaphors like 'keeping
your distance'
from authority, or 'trying
to find your own space'. Buchanan
(2000) also suggests that the
spatial metaphor refers to
particular positions in time as
well]..
As
you walk through the city
you weave spaces together in a
subjective way: this can never be
captured objectively, say by
drawing maps to trace journeys,
since it is the experience of
walking or ‘passing by’ that
counts. Maps are typical forms of
fixation of the flux of everyday
life, which try to pin it down by
abstracting heavily from it.
There is a
rhetoric of walking, so that all
walkers actually articulate
sentences using a series of
signifiers, although this is often
done unconsciously
(as when one finds oneself
unconsciously drawn to particular
circuits of city streets or
locations in cities). Planners
give areas of the city names in an
attempt to make them signify in
their discourses, but walkers and
users take these over, so that a
'poetic geography'
emerges on top of the
objective one.
[An example that occurs to
me here is finding so many
monuments to revolutionary
activities dotted around Paris.
Whereas the students I was with
saw no particular significance in
these, walking from the site of
the Bastille past the Monument to
the 1848 revolution and then to
the monuments commemorating those
killed in the 1830 revolution had
considerable significance for me,
resonating with all sorts of
political sentiments, and also
enabling me to confirm the French
history I had learned while at
school]. Official names and plans
therefore become taken over by new
signifiers.
This
sort of self centred and often
unconscious process of
significations can be displaced
and condensed, as in dreams. [Buchanan
goes
on
to pursue the issue of what is
being wished for in these
travelling and walking dreams, and
finally concludes that it is a
rather strange dance with the
notion of otherness that is at the
source of pleasure here]. De
Certeau also refers to the role of
'legends' which once offered a
series of 'habitable spaces' but
which 'places nowadays lack'
(160). Travel can replace such
lost legends in one's own
vicinity, offering 'an exploration
of the deserted places of my
memory' [ an unattributed quote in
de Certeau here], or a 'return to
nearby exoticism by way of a
detour through distant places'
(160). Walking is a kind of
'story', composed of
'debris...leftovers...fragments of
scattered semantic
places...combined with
things extra and other' (160)
These interrupt the accepted
framework and order, which
'leaks... meaning: it is a sieve
order' (160). [Further, signifying
practices like these can even
'invent spaces' --
one
of
my own examples here refers to the
ways in which elderly inhabitants
in my home town still offer
strangers directions in terms of
buildings that were demolished in
the late 1940s!].
Reference
Buchanan I (2000) Michel
de Certeau: Cultural Theorist,
London: Sage
more notes
on social theorists
|