Deleuze for the
Desperate #2 Rhizome
Dave Harris
Introduction:
The project involves looking at
some key concepts in Deleuze, as I explained in
another video. Incidentally, I have just
remembered that D follows this approach himself
with Spinoza's
work, (Deleuze 1988) picking out key
terms like attribute or mode. Deleuze puts them
in alphabetical order but I think that can be a
bit arbitrary.
The rhizome is perhaps the most
famous concept, well-liked by people trying to
'apply' Deleuze or D&G. Any gardener can
think of an example of a rhizome – plants like
the Iris, ginger, certain kinds of bamboo or
couch grass have underground roots or stems.
When you pull up a shoot of couch grass sticking
up through the soil you uncover a straggly white
tough fibrous stem that wanders off
unpredictably under the surface. Sometimes, you
find it connected unexpectedly to another green
shoot somewhere else. Lots of apparently
unconnected bits of couch grass are really
connected underground.
D&G get a bit defensive about
the term in A Thousand Plateaus, (ATP)
and say they now realize the need to convince
people with a list of properties. Rather than
just reproduce this list, which is not very
helpful at first, I suggest we do something
different. Of course, you don't have to just
follow my thinking or agree with me – try the
techniques for yourself.
One other difficulty is that the
term is used as an introduction to the major
philosophical arguments developed in ATP, and
the definitions themselves get a bit lost. I
suggest we focus on those definitions and what
is implied by them first, but also note the
wider implications. Of course, this is only one
suggestion for an approach and there are others.
I don't want people who are just
beginning to get distracted or overwhelmed by
the enormity of the work involved to track down
all the implications. First, I have been pretty
selective, inevitably. Second I have divided up
the commentary, and you will hear two voices to
indicate the split in focus – the second one is
Maggie Harris's.
M Harris
My sections discuss some
implications that arise. They need not worry
complete beginners right away, but others might
want to think about them as they go along. There
is a transcript available so you can follow some
issues up with that if you need to do so.
D Harris
As before, I suggest we think
about this while watching some slow video. I was
trying out my amateur steadicam gear and going
for a single take on a recent walk. I apologise
if anyone gets seasick with the wobbles or the
whippy pans. Ironically, the video features
shots of lots of trees.
First we need to locate where the
topic of the rhizome is discussed, and it is
fairly easy in this case. We'll start with A
Thousand Plateaus, (Deleuze and Guattari,
2004) where nearly all or perhaps all, the
references to the rhizome can be found. It has
an index too. If you look up the term rhizome,
you find quite a number of definitions.
Let's start with the specific
ones. It's not just plants that are rhizomes.
Ant colonies, rat burrows, the city of
Amsterdam, the Freudian Unconscious, liberated
sexual activity, musical forms, aspects of
American culture focused both on the cultural
underground and the Wild West, forms of guerilla
warfare, the path of a pool of oil as it runs
downstream. Even the book itself, ATP, is a
rhizome, D&G tell us (p. 24). Occasionally,
other things are called rhizomes as well,
throughout the book. Reading the text around the
actual definitions will help
Optional discussion 1
One thing to note right away is
that not all these examples relate to human
beings. In discussions like this, D&G want
to talk about things found in nature as well. It
would be limiting to confine what they say to
human affairs, although sometimes this is what
happens – concepts like the rhizome are
discussed in terms of human activities alone –
thinking, writing, wandering. This is an
anthropomorphic reading of Deleuzian work and it
is only one option. More on this in a minute,
but for now, the suggestion is that the more
general accounts of the rhizome stress that
human activity is connected to lots of other
areas. The 'pure' rhizome is infinitely
connectable,with each point having the capacity
to connect with any other point in any other
system.
End of optional discussion 1.
Back to our definitions:
There are also more challenging
general, theoretical or philosophical
descriptions and comments.
The first example isn't too bad:
[A rhizome is] a map and not a
tracing...'open and connectable in all of its
dimensions (13) D
Incidentally, in the same bit there
is a reference to decalcomania – strangely taken
to be crucial in some commentaries, but just
another example for me. It refers to a technique
to add decoration to pottery as a kind of
applique. I don't know enough about it to see what
exactly is rhizomatic about this technique – maybe
it has to respond to minute changes in the surface
texture of the pot as well as to the artistic
intentions of the potter?
More abstractly:
The rhizome has no beginning and
end. It is a matter of alliance rather than
filiation. It proceeds by the conjunction
'and…and…and'...American literature and some
English literature shows this 'rhizomatic
direction' (28), following a 'logic of the AND'
(27). In other words, such works do not follow
conventional narratives but move from one
episode to the next. No examples are specified
here – I thought of James Joyce and Ulysses but
he is neither American nor English
More obscurely:
The multiple must be made, not by
always adding a higher dimension but ...with the
number of dimensions one already has available
-- always n-1 (the only way the one belongs to
the multiple: always subtracted). Subtract the
unique from the multiplicity to be constructed:
write at n-1 dimensions...A system of this kind
would be called a rhizome' (7).
[The rhizome] is composed of
dimensions or 'directions in motion'. It has no
beginning or end, only 'a middle (milieu) from
which it grows and over spills' [I often wonder
if translating milieu as 'middle' rather than
'context' is helpful here]. It constructs linear
multiplicities with N dimensions. It has no
subject or object. It moves on a plane of
consistency 'from which the One [capital O] is
always subtracted (N-1) (24)
Even
the
simple example we started with gets a bit more
complicated as we read on: plants connect the
rhizomes of their roots, with other things, like
the wind or animals or human beings. The whole
thing is now described as a rhizome.
In
human
life, we are told a rhizome ceaselessly
establishes connections between semiotic chains,
organizations of power, and circumstances
relative to the arts, sciences, and social
struggles (8) We are urged always to trace
connections like this, always follow rhizomes
until we get to the most abstract and tortuous
connections. These lines of flight away from the
specific examples will eventually lead us to a
completel;y abstract or 'pure' mechanism or
machine operating on the mysterious plane of
consistency (12). It is that pure mechanism,
with no specific empirical bits at all that is
being referred to in the obscure stuff just now,
referring to multiplicities and N dimensions
It is very tempting to ignore
these complications and go with what you know
already – the rhizome as an underground root.
Some people have used this simple metaphor to
find some immediate 'applications' to humans and
to social life as we saw – the way in which some
people learn, for example, trailing from one
task to another, wandering along directed by
their interests and personal motives which
operate beneath the surface of their
consciousness. This is only a metaphorical
connection, though - -and Deleuze actually
doesn't like metaphors which he sees as the
result of lazy thinking, not going into the
issues the actual similarities between plants
and animals which we discuss in a minute.:
Insert caption: the metaphor is
redundant, since it implies some true primary
meaning, whereas ‘all meaning and identification
derive rather from the unstable interplay of
figures, from configurations of sense’.
Deleuze 1995.:188
My suggestion is we do something
a bit more ambitious here, to try to work in all
the examples, and then try to see as a first
stage how the more general and obscure bits fit
in. We should and we can tangle a little bit at
least with the philosophy, using our own common
forms of thinking. I should say that Deleuze has
serious objections to the ways in which ordinary
thought processes work, and we'll mention a
couple more as we go along.
Optional discussion 2
One way to start might be to
return to the issue of what all the examples
might have in common. It seems that Deleuze and
Guattari see something in common between human
activities and the activities of animals like
ants and rats or even trickles of oil. We could
think in terms used in classical philosophy and
ask if there is some underlying essential
quality here – do we share having been created
by God as an earlier way of thinking about
essences would suggest? Theologians have amused
themselves for centuries with this sort of
inquiry and its implications – does God create
everything and if he doesn't who does? Does he
create each individual ant or just the species?
Is he there in each patch of oil?
A currently fashionable view
would take another option and say the links
occur because there is some cosmic consciousness
that connects us all to the natural world, that
even plants have some kind of consciousness of
their surroundings. But do trickles of oil? The
actual emphasis is possibly the other way around
though. Plant rhizomes develop by responding to
local differences in their environment
concerning moisture, temperature, nutrient
contents and so on. Rats and ants might respond
to chemical or physical differences in their
environments – texture of the surface, gradient
and so on. Trickles of oil also respond to local
gradients and the general effects of gravity.
This is not really consciousness, but more a
basic detection of different sorts of intensity
– of chemicals or gravitational forces.
And it is often the case that
these differences drive human actions too. We
are not conscious of all of them. We are
affected by physical aspects of our environment.
Our environment produces affects. Now the term
'affect' has been colonised by recent psychology
to mean just emotions, but Deleuze sees an
affect in an earlier 17th Century way
to mean anything that affects us, usually
registered at the bodily level. That produces
things in our minds like emotions and feelings.
We respond to chemicals in our bodies and in our
environment. We respond to external forces like
gravity by feeling happy if we lose weight, sad
if we put it on and feel gravity tugging us
down. We are nervous thinking of the effects of
falling from height, elated at feeling g forces
on an accelerating motorcycle – and so on. The
best place to find this view of affects and how
they work on bodies is Deleuze's book on Spinoza
(Deleuze 1988) or the online lectures on Spinoza (Deleuze 2007).
This could be what they mean by
the section on page 9 of ATP:
'Puppetstrings,
as a rhizome or multiplicity, are tied not to
the supposed will of an artist or puppeteer
but to a multiplicity of nerve fibers, which
form another puppet...[let's call them] the
weave. It might be objected that its
multiplicity resides in the person of the
actor who projects it into the text. Granted:
but the actor's nerve fibers in turn form a
weave' (9)
So human rhizomes are like plant
rhizomes not because we share some essential
consciousness, but because both are affected by
intensities of forces in their environments.
End of optional discussion 2
Let us try another normal
technique of thinking, found in the social
sciences this time. We could ask: do the
examples share common observable properties?.
Vigorous couch grass roots, ants on the march,
rats building burrows, tourists wandering around
Amsterdam, and guerillas operating in enemy
territory do not follow simple binary choices or
directions laid out in suggested routes. The
claim is that you couldn't fit them into a
logical pattern like an algorithm (to use the
modern term) or a 'decision tree' or 'command
tree' (to use older ones). This explains the
contrast between rhizomes and trees appearing at
time in the book.
We can connect this to one of the
comments earlier:
[A rhizome is] a map and not a
tracing...'open and connectable in all of its
dimensions (13)
Guerilla
fighters
and tourists use maps, on paper or in their
heads, but they do not always stick to the
prescribed routes or tracings, and, with a bit
of poetic licence you could see ants on the
march and even the other examples as showing the
same qualities, responding to local and
immediate bits of environment wherever they
lead, as we saw. The rhizome as a map offers
more possible routes than the usual specific
ones that we follow from inertia or habit or
because we have been told to do so.
Note
that
we are developing a more general
or theoretical structure.
We could use the
term 'abstract structure' for now, although Deleuze
does
not like that specific term either.
The easiest
reason for
that ,incidentally, is
that
'abstract' or 'theoretical'
imply
that the structure that results is not real,
that it exists only in our heads, that
the
qualities we have in mind are derived only
from thought, from our
imagination, and that we have
had to ignore or explain away other aspects that
do not fit
our
theoretical model.
By contrast, Deleuze makes the extraordinary
claim that these structures are real, that they
exist in reality – but in
another dimension of reality. He
calls this the virtual dimension, where
we
find purified objects, with no empirical
components. This is
not to be confused with the
current usage of the term to refer to realistic
computer-generated images.
Optional discussion 3
Deleuze
doesn't
like the more usual
philosophical argument
that this is a transcendental level of reality.
He is criticising Kant Hegel
or Husserl here, but you might
know of a popular transcendental approach in
modern 'critical realism' associated with Roy Bhaskar ( eg Bhaskar ,
1980)
and others. If you don't know
this stuff, don't worry, of course.
Optional
discussion
3 ends
Another
extraordinary
claim is that the operations at the virtual
level explain all
the empirical examples and their characteristics
- -we'll come to this argument when we consider
the haecceity in another presentation.
All the examples are tracings to
be put back on underlying maps.
So
even the normal notion of a map
will not do. Rhizomes at
this level of reality, the
virtual, are
maps 'open and connectable in all dimensions',
always capable of extending themselves into ever
larger maps, and operating not in two dimensions
like normal maps but three (or more).
Nor
are
virtual rhizomes
limited to just joining
up with things that they have already connected
or established.
They have no definite end. They
are very flexible and can join themselves on to
almost anything, any activity,
any environment or context. They just cheerfully
add on these additional dimensions, in a series
connected just by 'and', following alliance
rather
than filiation
(in other words, they don't have
to be in the same family as the things they
connect with): power
systems ally themselves to linguistic systems so
we are constrained by both direct force AND a
set of psychological mechanisms, that make us
feel guilty if we disobey AND a linguistic
system that seems to offer us unconstrained,
creative 'free speech' but
within limits.
Where
is
all this leading? In a philosophical direction,
aiming to answer philosophical questions,
including the ultimate ones like 'what is
reality'. You might not want to follow the story
this far just yet, but that is where Deleuze and
Guattari are heading. Deleuze
and Guattari use specific examples to get to
more general philosophy.
Any practical implications follow
only after we have followed this trail into the
virtual, and left specific constraints and
limitations well behind us. And
when we return to the practical, we must expect
to meet reintroduced mixtures, impure
combinations, say of rhizomes and tree
structures.
Optional discussion 4
It
is
a strange story, and one that goes quite
a way from common sense. We have
seen that rhizomes offer quite different
specific characteristics in practice, but that
they might have some general properties that are
not so visible. They feature ceaseless
connections, and constant growth into other
areas. But this is not determined or controlled
by human beings or gods,
or some ultimate purpose – they have ' have no
subject
or object'. They seem to
proliferate all on their own. Once they take on
specific forms, we can intervene – block a couch
grass rhizome, redesign Amsterdam, evict rats
from their burrows etc. But at the general level
the philosophical figure of
the rhizome carries on about
its own business. It is driven by forces beyond
human control. It produces or
turns
into strange multiple objects
with lots of potential different specific forms
– multiplicities. These
exist at the virtual level. At
certain
times and in certain states, multiplicities
produce the more familiar rhizomes we see around
us, but there are other possibilities too, which
may never actually ever appear in physical form.
Philosophy tries to work out the strange
activities of these unobservable multiplicities.
This
is
not as strange as it sounds at first, and
earlier forms exist of this sort of argument. A
leading structuralist, Claude Levi-Strauss says
he was inspired by an understanding of geology
first. We can explain the surface features of
landscapes – hills and valleys, particular
directions of slopes and so on, once we know
about the geology of the area, the rocks that
lie underneath. Levi- Strauss went on to develop
a structural model of language a bit like this,
saying that all the rich varieties of myths in
certain preindustrial societies could be
explained as combinations of underlying options
to discuss important matters like the relation
of humans to nature. Deleuze's colleague M
Foucault also purposed what he called an
archaeological model to study discourses, where
you inspect the remains of buildings or
discourses that lie on the surface ,and
gradually establish an overall plan or CGI model
of what the building might have looked like
which explains the remains that you see –and
sketches in what has been destroyed.
Now
these earlier
approaches are discussed
critically by Deleuze on the way to establish
his own underlying structures. Structure is the
wrong word here, for him, as
we
saw, and it also implies some
fixed set of options, and Deleuze wants to argue
instead for flux, flow and dynamic combinations
of forces, which themselves change and develop.
This bit explains why he is
sometimes called a 'post-structuralist',
although he does far more than just criticise
structuralism.
All this is
carefully if sometimes bafflingly argued in
Deleuze's book Difference and
Repetition ( Deleuze,
2004) ,
but there is a much shorter summary in Deleuze
and Parnet (1987),
right at the end.
To
take
one more example, the
commentary by DeLanda (2002) is very useful.
Again we might not be using
specifically Deleuzian arguments but we can get
a long way before we might have to correct them.
DeLanda says that modern physics thinks in terms
of unobservable forces swirling around in a
complex or chaotic way, combining with each
other to produce vectors. There also exist
various attractors that draw these forces
together to form particular shapes or
figures. Some,
but
only some, can be chaotic attractors, and this
provides the popular name for this approach –
chaos theory. As these forces
stabilise they cool down and condense into
matter of the kind we can detect. The
swirling hot forces of the cosmos just after the
Big Bang eventually cooled enough to start
combing protons, neutrons and electron together
to make atoms, then atoms into molecules of the
elements, molecules into compounds, compounds
into larger compounds under the force of gravity
– and so on. Combinations often
have different possible states which produces
matter of different kinds – gasses, solids and
liquids, for example. Ice,
liquid water, and steam look and feel quite
different to our senses, as indeed do the gases
hydrogen and oxygen, but they are all states of
one system
End
of
optional discussion 4
So
we have moved from the
specifics of couch grass to the
generalities of chaos or
complexity theory,from empirical
examples to purified ones.
Was it worth it? If you are a
philosopher, yes, since
it
gives us a fresh take on all sorts of earlier
philosophical approaches.
What if you are not a
philosopher?
At
the very least the
approach helps
us see that there is much more
at stake in analysis than
just using a nice metaphor. You
might
not wish to delve into the complexities of
Deleuzian philosophy, but it would be wise to
recognise that they are attached to the concept.
It is obviously controversial to grab the
metaphor and then bolt it on to some other
philosophical approach like social constructivism
or humanism, at least without acknowledging the
problems.
More
practically,
maybe
a Deleuzian approach shows that the
specific rhizomes
that exist here and now are not the only
possible ones, and should not make claim to be
the only possible ones, although
they
often do. That is not an issue
with couch grass, although
gardeners
are usually thwarted if they try to pull out
bits of it only to find the thing starting up
again somewhere
else.
It is an
important issue if if
we
start to see modern organizations as
stabilised,
limited or blocked rhizomes.
We can see a space for politics,
for social change that
points to other possibilities emerging
equally
plausibly from the same underlying
multiplicity, even
ones that have not been realized
yet. This would be a
pretty radical politics, not just operating with
choices provided by existing systems but
realizing new possibilities.
This is why we
need a general account of possibilities, to
break out of existing constraints, in
politics and practice as well as in thought.
We
also
might begin to see that human activity can
operate only against a background of what is
already being made into reality by non-human
forces –which limits the space for politics and
social change. Not everything or anything is
possible. I am afraid this alternation between
political optimism and pessimism is something
that runs throughout ATP at least, and is a
major issue with D&G.
Finally,
I
am aware that a couple of things
haven't been discussed yet
– a
rhizome grows in the middle without beginning or
end. That is fairly simple in arguing that we
should not worry about rying
to trace everything back to a single origin, a
capital O One – like the
medieval philosophers did when they tried to
explain everything as emanating from the will or
characteristics of God. Nor should we try to
establish foundational concepts that always
explain everything – the mode of production for
marxists, or the Oedipus complex for Freudians,
or humanist qualities of creativity and freedom,
for that matter. It follows that there is no
ultimate end we should be thinking of either, no
glorious future of freedom and
self-understanding, no state of final
equilibrium in the universe, no peak of
biological evolution.
A
rhizome occupies N dimensions –
that is not just the usual 3 dimensions, but
any number. Note also that Deleuze
sometimes uses the term 'dimension' as some
mathematicians do – as a line joining points.
The bit about operating with N-1 is a puzzle – I
think DeLanda explains it best as referring to
abstract geometry. For now, we can read it as
advice not to work with specific and
unique things but to subtract
them
or abstract from them, and
think
of the forces behind them so to speak. We should
also take out
any original One that is supposed to spark it
all off, as
above.
There
is
one last mysterious term in the
definitions of the rhizome –
A rhizome
moves on a 'plane
of
consistency' That will have to wait
for another session. For now a plane or plan is
a way Deleuze has of
thinking of connections between rhizomes or
multiplicities (in this case): roughly, for now,
we have to analyse each separate rhizome in a
way which is consistent with what we know about
the others. It is partly a
matter of doing philosophical work, since we can
ever observe or measure multiplicities at the
virtual level – but it is not just philosophical
speculation, more like discovering by coherent
philosophical argument, carefully
developed, the underlying virtual
reality that can explain all the specific cases.
This
is
enough for one session. I'll leave you with some
references to books I have mentioned and to my
notes on them.
References
Bhaskar,
R. (1980)
'Scientific Explanations and
Emancipation'. Radical
Philosophy 26, Autumn 1980.
(my
notes
– http://www.arasite.org/bhaskar.html)
Delanda, M. (2002) Intensive
Science and Virtual Philosophy, London:
Continuum (my notes –
http://www.arasite.org/delandaintensv.html)
Deleuze,
G
(2007) Lectures on Spinoza.
http://deleuzelectures.blogspot.co.uk/2007/02/on-spinoza.html
Deleuze, G (2004)
[1968] Difference and Repetition, Trans Paul
Patton, London: Continuum Publishing Group (my
notes --http://www.arasite.org/diffandrep.html)
Deleuze, G. (1988) Spinoza
Practical Philosophy, trans. Robert
Hurley. San Francisco: City Lights Books (my
notes – http://www.arasite.org/delspin1.html)
Deleuze
G
and Guattari F (1984) Anti-Oedipus.
Capitalism and Schizophrenia, London: The
Athlone Press. (My notes –
http://www.arasite.org/antioedipus.html)
Deleuze
G
and Guattari F (2004) A Thousand Plateaus,
London: Continuum. (my [extensive] notes on
http://www.arasite.org/dandgthouplat.html)
Deleuze,
G.
and Parnet, C. (1987) Dialogues, trans H
Tomlinson and B Habberjam, London: The Athlone
Press. (my notes –
http://www.arasite.org/dialogues.html)
|