html
Notes on: Latour B. On actor –
network theory. A few clarifications (1996) Soziale
Welt 47, H. 4:
369 – 81. HTTPS: //www.JSTOR.org/stable/40878163
Dave
Harris
The
theory has been misunderstood. It has been given
a technical meaning
in the sense of a train or subway network,
related but distant
elements with compulsory circulation between the
nodes through paths
that give some nodes strategic importance.
Computer networks are the
best examples of a final and stabilised state of
an actor network.
But networks here may be local, with 'no
compulsory paths no strategically
positioned nodes'(369). It is a network of
power.
Nor
are the networks really social networks but
instead are about 'the
social relations of individual human actors'
rather than
'institutions or organisations states or
nations', which are less
realistic and too large, all-encompassing.
However nonhuman and
non-individual entities also included. Social
theory is to be rebuilt
out of networks, as 'an ontology or a
metaphysics' as much as a
sociology. Social networks are included but they
are not privileged.
The network concerned actually comes from
Diderot and was
intended to avoid a divide between matter and
spirit. It avoids the
notion of essences and replaces that with
filaments or rhizomes in
D&G. There are, however many dimensions, as
many as there are
connections, giving a 'fibrous, threadlike,
wiry, stringy, ropy,
capillary character to modern societies' (370)
rather than a matter
of levels or layers or systems. It's been
developed in studies of
science and technology and the facts produced by
sciences and
artefacts are essential to understand what holds
society together.
In
some ways it is 'a simple material resistance
argument'' stressing
the 'dissemination, heterogeneity and plaiting
of weak ties' as the
source of social strength, what Foucault refers
to as micro-powers,
it proceeds by taking local contingencies,
unconnected localities
which then turn into sometimes 'provisionally
commensurable
connections'. There are affinities with notions
of disorder or chaos
philosophy and 'many practical links with
ethnomethodology'.
Universality and order are exceptions. Local
contingencies or clusters
are best seen as archipelagoes on a sea. There
is no attempt to fill
in what is between these local pockets of order
— 'literally there
is nothing but networks'. This makes ANT
reductionist and relativist,
but it will end in 'an irreductionist and
relationist ontology'
The
properties of nets are added to the notion of
actor that does some
work. The first property of networks is
that it avoids the tyranny of
distance or proximity, so that elements can be
close when connected
even though they may be infinitely remote or
distant, as in telephone
connections, or adjacent animals cut off by a
pipeline, or neighbours separated by cultural
differences. Geography is prevalent and stops
us defining all associations in terms of
networks. Geographers are to
blame in defining proximity and distance as
special, and or ignoring
proximity or distance not defined, say on maps,
there is a 'tyranny
of geographers in defining space' (371). The
notion of scale is also
changed, especially the macro micro
distinction, and is replaced by
'a metaphor of connections' — networks are
simply longer or more
intensely connected rather than bigger we can
thus avoid notions of
order that go from top to bottom and the
difficulties of tracing
links between the scales. In ANT there is no 'a
priority order
relation' and so it avoids questions of top and
bottom and
transformations, and indeed can follow changes
in scales — 'the
scale, that is, the type, number and topography
of connections, is
left to the actors themselves.' We thus regain
more manoeuvre between
the ingredients of social life, vertical space,
hierarchy, layers,
wholeness and we can see how these features are
achieved. We can
think of global and local entities, and can see
how elements become
strategic [that is important to wider
connections]
The
third property that is avoided is the
notion of inside/outside 'a
network is a boundary without inside and
outside' (372). As in
Deleuze [?], a network creates the background
and the foreground. There
is no need to fill in the space between the
connections — networks
have no negativity to be understood, no shadow.
These
properties have made the study of society and
nature difficult, and
ANT does not have to qualify matters as either
social or natural.
There are things that are macro social or
outside nature but these
are best seen as the 'effects of distance,
proximity, hierarchies,
connectedness, out sidedness and surfaces' and
we have to study these
through a great deal of work. The topological
notion of network
itself is insufficient and we need to add a
foreign notion — 'that of
actor', moving away from mathematical properties
to introduce dynamic
ones.
'An
actor – network is an entity that does the
tracing and the
inscribing'. It's not a piece of inert matter in
the hands of human
planners, and it should not be understood as
involving human
intentional individual actors, especially not
people, usually males
who want to grab power through a network of
allies, doing networking.
In ANT, an actor 'is a semiotic definition — an
actant-- that is
something that acts or to which activity is
granted by others. It
implies no special motivation of human
individual actors, nor of
humans in general. An actant can literally
be anything provided it is
granted to be the source of an action'
(373) this is difficult to
understand because 'anthropocentrism and
socio-centrism are so strong
in social sciences'. Actually, ANT is completely
indifferent to
models of human competence, 'the human, the self
and the social actor
of traditional social theory is not on its
agenda'.
Instead
it studies the attribution of 'human, unhuman,
nonhuman, in human
characteristics' and how they are distributed
among entities,
connected together, circulated and distributed.
These must be grasped
in an integrated practice of study. Semiotics is
a necessary step
following from 'when you bracket out the
question of reference and
that of the social conditions of production is —
that is nature
"out there" and society "up there". What is left
is a first approximation — 'meaning production,
or discourse, or
text' as in the linguistic turn, where
discourses became mediators,
rich and complex. ANT draws from this work what
is useful 'to
understand the construction of entities — that's
'every entity,
including the self, society, nature, every
relation, every action,
can be understood as a "choice" or a "selection"
of finer and finer and branch moments going from
abstract structure —
actant's — to concrete ones — actors'. We
retrace this generative
path. [Better than Hjemslev
on universal 'expression'?]
'...the granting of humanity to an
individual actor or of collectivity..., or
anonymity, ... zoomorphic
appearance..., amorphousness...materiality'
involves the 'same
semiotic price', although the effects are be
different. The work of
attributing and imputing is the same. We have to
think of all these
actors as 'flows, as circulating objects
undergoing trials', made
stable, continuous as a result of 'other actions
and other trials'. Various texts and discourses
retain their ability to define their
context, authors and readers, 'even their own
demarcation and
metalanguage'. The "text itself' remains as
central to analysis,
just as the slogans about nothing outside the
text argued, but the
ontological consequences are avoided, 'by
extending the semiotic turn
to this famous nature and this famous context it
has bracketed out in
the first place' (374). [cf Kirby's
attempt to do this with Derrida]
We
saw the problems when the slogans were applied
to scientific and
technical discourse, and scientific texts.
Scholars did not treat
fictions or myths seriously anyway and so their
distance and
scepticism was easy to achieve, but the real
test was hard scientific
text. ANT semiotics extended to include 'a
completely empty frame
that enabled to follow any assemblage of
heterogeneous entities —
including now the "natural" entities of science
and the
"material" entities of technology'. But as a
method to
describe generative paths 'of any narration,
analysing 'what the
recording device should be that would allow
entities to be described
in all their details… The burden of theory [is]
on the recording,
not on the specific shape that is recorded'.
Actors may be human or
unhuman, pliable, cross scales, ordered or not
and this 'does not
qualify any real observed actor' but specifies
the 'necessary
condition for the observation and the recording
of actors to be
possible', not 'constantly predicting how an
actor should behave and
which associations are allowed a priori'. It is
not a theory of
action but 'qualifies what the observer should
suppose' if they are
to record the shapes they seek, and 'any shape
is possible provided
it is obsessively coded', rigidly or
heterogeneously.
We
are talking of 'infra language' rather than
'metalanguage' (375). ANT
is not a descriptive vocabulary but is concerned
with 'the
possibility of describing irredeductions', [ie
weproceed until we achieve irreducibility?]
against all a priori
reductions. Nor is it merely empiricist, since
theoretical
commitments are required in order to define
'such an irreducible
space', and so is polemic. Indeed ANT is often
accused of being
dogmatic or simply descriptive, or blandly
claiming that actors are
really infinitely pliable or free.
It
should be accepted that bracketing out social
context and reference
does not solve the problem of meaning, despite
the claims of the
enthusiasts, nor does sketching the shape of
associations offer any
actual explanation. We need a third strand,
which is particularly
devious, although it makes AMT look really
commonsensical.
Once
we consider nonhuman entities and nature,
semiotics looks weak
because it appears that we can do without words
like discourse or
meaning altogether, since semiotics classically
studies texts rather
than things. They did 'scientistically' believe
in things in addition
to meaning, or even context, but saw a semiotic
of things as 'easy,
one simply has to drop the meaning bit from
semiotics'. If semiotics
now becomes path building or order making or the
creation of
directions, you can include objects as well as
language and unified
practices that were once seen as different. One
consequences to
elevate things to the dignity of texts or give
texts the ontological
status of things. Both are elevations not
reductions, and absolute
distinctions are lost 'between representation
and things'. '… This
is exactly what ANT wishes to redistribute
through what I have called
a counter Copernican revolution'
[So,
stap me! The bugger is arguing that human
exceptionalism can be
replaced not for ethical or political reasons,
but for analytic
ones!]
This
also leads us to a better understanding of
explanation, and therefore
to a methodology that deals with description.
Actor networks connect
and this will 'provide an explanation of
themselves, the only one
there is 'for ANT'. An explanation is 'the
attachment of a set of
practices that control or interfere in one
another' [cf Deleuze on
the Logic
of sense] and no explanation is stronger
in providing
connections among unrelated elements or showing
how one element holds
many others'. This is a property of networks,
not something distinct,
and explanations grow as networks grow. Networks
attract explanatory
resources as they grow. Explanations do not get
added from outside
'one simply extend the network further' (376)
and this extends frames
of references, frames, explanations. Each
account has to be
recalculated, just like in Lorentz
transformations. This does not
contradict science and its task of providing
explanation and
causality — science proceeds by extending the
network itself, even
though its goal is never been achieved.
'Explanation is ex–
plicated, that is unfolded'. [but seebelow -- no
heretical denunciatins etc]
This
is relativist, or rather 'one should prefer the
less loaded term
relation-ist' and it helps solve the other
problems historicity and
reflexivity
Pre-relativism,
there was a difference between providing an
explanation and just
documenting the historical circumstances, but
now there is no
difference. Critics have suggested that this
'"escapes
socio-historical contingencies"', but this only
means that
longer term factors have been more important,
like networks of power,
or networks of world economics, capitalism or
zeitgeist. Historians
don't like this because they don't like
ontology. [and prefer empirical accident,
contingency etc]
Historicism
is avoided because there is no definition of the
things themselves
involved. There used to be a clash between
historicism and explanation or
theory since there was thought to be a
distinction between the
history of people, of contingencies, of the
effects of time on the
one hand, and a theory or a science of something
timeless or eternal
or necessary on the other. ANT says there is the
science only of the
contingent, that becomes necessary as a local
achievement through the
growth of a network. The distinction between
things, descriptions and
explanations is dissolved and this is 'what an
explanation or
explication is and what has always been the case
in the so-called
hard sciences' (377) [values smuggled in then].
Reflexivity
is not the main goal but it is added since the
frames of reference
are accessible to the actors. The problems
usually arise with the
'epistemological myth' of an outside observer
providing a superior
explanation for the participants who can merely
describe, but now
there is no privilege, merely another frame of
reference, the
observer's, 'on a par with all the other frames
of reference'. To
move from one frame of reference to the next
requires work just as
with any other actor, 'to explain, to account,
to observe, to prove,
to argue, to dominate… To "network"'. In this
way
reflexivity is not a problem but an opportunity.
Privileged
metalanguage has to be abandoned [not easy --
and not done in this case, of course] but this
was usually only a resource
for 'small points limited to very specific
local[itieis] — campuses,
studios, corporate rooms'. Many frames of
reference means many
metalanguage strategies, but the only one
required is better
understood as an 'infra language' the equivalent
of a Lorentz
transformation, a 'translation' in ANT terms
this produces only a
'one-shot account exclusively tailored to the
problem at hand, and
Callon calls them "disposable explanations' as
networks expand.
This
is common sense. New accounts do not subtract
anything in ANT. The
selection principle is not whether there is some
fit between account
and reality but 'whether or not one travels from
a net to another'.
No metalanguage helps here. Epistemology does
not lead to moral
relativism but rather to a 'stronger
deontological commitment: either
an account leads you to all the other accounts —
and is good — or
it constantly interrupts the movement, and
letting frames of
reference distant and foreign [sic] — and it is
bad' (378). More
mediating point are produced, good, or are
reduced, bad. Reductionism
or areductionism — 'that's the highest ethical
standard for AMT'
and more discriminating than searching for
epistemological purity,
foundations, or moral norms: 'demarcation is in
fact an enemy
of differentiation'.
So
ANT brackets out society and nature to consider
only meaning
production. Then it breaks with conventional
semiotics and grants
activity to semiotic actors turning them into
'new ontological
hybrids, world making entities'. It builds an
empty frame to describe
how entities build their worlds and it retains
from description only
a very few terms 'it's infra language — which
are just enough to
sail in between frames of reference and grants
back to the actors
themselves the ability to build precise accounts
of one another by
the very way they behave; the goal of building
an overarching
explanation… The search for x applications, that
is for the
deployment of as many elements as possible
accounted for through as
many metalanguages as possible'
ANT
is therefore 'about a network tracing activity
rather than traced
networks themselves. 'No net exists
independently of the very act of
tracing it, and now tracing is done by an actor
exterior to the net.
A network is not a thing but the recorded
movement of a thing'. There
is no need to distinguish what moves inside
networks, into, for
example pieces of information, words, or bodies
since nets existed
before such distinctions became important — what
is important is
like the circulating object in semiotic texts,
something defined 'by
the competencies [it is] endowed with, the
trials it undergoes, the
performances it is allowed to display, the
associations it is made to
bear upon, the sanctions it receives, the
background in which is is
circulating'. These and its persistence are 'the
results of the
decision taken through the narrative programs
and the narrative
paths'
Is
ANT limited to the world of text and discourse?
Is there a gap
between text and context? For ANT, this is 'no
more than a slight
bump along the net' caused by a previous divide
between nature and
society and discourse (379). Instead there is a
continuity, multiple
plugs between the circulating objects, the
claims outside the text in
the social and what the actants themselves
really do. The circulating
object goes on circulating, things like society
text and nature are
'arbitrary cutting point on a continuous tracing
of action'
themselves part of the obstacles, trials and
events leading to
attributions of textuality or sociology or
natural reality 'not part
of what makes the distribution'.
This
could be described as a 'generalised narrative
path'. All this would
be to imply that everything is a text. To call
it a force or energy
would imply that everything is naturalised, and
to call it a social
interest extends social action to nature and to
texts. ANT originally
played with 'generalised symmetry' and used
whichever words are
connoted in one realm to describe the others to
show the continuity
of network and the disregard for any gaps, but
this could lead to
misunderstanding and accusations of Social
Constructivism, naturalism,
or French belief in the textualisation of
everything. The point is
that all of the terminologies refer to the
filling in of what is
between the network, 'and which one is chosen or
rejected makes no
practical difference, since nets have now "in
between" to
be filled in'
What
circulates should be seen as both co-determined
and transformed',
what Serres has called a quasi-object. Material
objects are poor
examples because they are not transformed Quasi
objects
are moving actants that transform those who
do the moving and
the moving object. Stability is exceptional.
This males ANT
different from all other models of
communication, which are human-
or languaege-centred. or praxis-cemtred.
There are also
different kinds of morphism --
anthropomorphic but also zoo- and
physio-morphic,logo- or techno-
ideo-morphic. Again paths with
restricted access to humans or mechanisms
are exceptional.
So we
can destroy 'spheres and domains', reinstate
heterogeneity and
interobjectivity. Associations are not
differentiated though
(politics?). This needs to be done,to 'specify
the types of
trajectories that are obtained by highly
different mediations
Still
classically in terrain of natural science where
network indeed
expanded or transformed. Transformatiopns
according to accepted
mathematical procedures in the case of Lorenz or
Einstein. Others
debatable eg marxist accounts, even religious
ones. Not accepted are
attempts to destroy and replace the whole
network, condemn it as
heresy as harmful or oppressive. This is what
happens in soc sci
or phil, -- happens with p-humanism!
|