Notes on: Barad, K. (1998) Getting Real:Technoscientific Practices and the Materializatrion of Reality. Differences: A journal of Feminist Cultural Studies  10(2) 87--128

Dave Harris

[Obviously the forerunner of the piece in Barad 2007, esp chs 4 & 5 -- better developed ]

We start with Foucault and the power relations involved in the body, to get it to carry out tasks and emit signs. A body reacts to forces and can transmit local signals or signs. This makes it 'the effect and instrument of visualising technologies'. We see this with the Pizeo Electric crystal [PEC]. Pressure produces an electric signal, electric fields deform the crystals so that if we apply an electric signal we get expansion or contraction, or vibration and the production of ultrasonic waves, transmission. This capacity to act as both transmitter and receiver is very useful in ultrasonography.

We can see it as a material instrument, and observing apparatus which operates with not only signals but discourses in the Foucault sense [presumably confining it to linguistic, and not visible results in practices?]. It can then serve to examine the relation between the material and the discursive more generally. This relationship has been explored in her 'feminist framework' (89) agential realism, inspired by Böhr in quantum physics.

Böhr challenged several foundational assumptions in Western epistemology, the subject/object distinction and the representational status of language [so I wonder if it is his term]. Agential realism extends his insights to discuss materiality, the relation between the material and discursive, the whole meaning of nature and culture and their relationship, and the issue of agency including effects of boundary such as exclusions. It helps explain the role of human and nonhuman factors in the production of knowledge, moving beyond realism versus social constructivism debates. With this 'more robust understanding of materiality' (87) feminists and other liberators can see how matter comes to matter, material constraints work, and how matter comes to be mediated in various 'poststructuralist and Marxist insights'. She's going to read Butler on performativity first, reading it through and with agential realism to get a 'richer ' account of materiality and agency.

Butler's book Bodies That Matter sees discourse and power as constituting subjects. The human body is seen as material in a way which is not at all 'foundational or self-evident'. Gender performativity links these arguments. She begins by criticizing social constructionism and urges a return to matter as process, especially on the materiality of sex and how it is produced. Matter is a process of materialisation that can stabilise, producing boundaries and surfaces. Her conception is limited, however.

She still retains a 'passive/active dualism', by arguing that it is only discourse that comes to matter, not matter itself, and not other material constraints and exclusions. It is not that she is guilty of idealism nor linguistic monism as critics have asserted, nor has she collapsed materiality to discourse, or stressed re-significations as the source of liberating politics. She does analyse the discursive dimensions — but this leaves out other components. Of course these are exclusions which are inevitable, even necessary, and they can be re-articulated. The point is whether or not we can add new dimensions of materiality 'enact a productive appropriation and elaboration of her theory' (91) without renouncing the whole theory.

Thinking about material constraints raises problems. Materiality itself might be seen best as the 'dissimulated effect of power'. We seem to require a fixed notion of materiality in order to explain how it constrains processes, and the whole thing threatens to revert to more conventional ontology. We turn to a quote from Butler on 'medical interpellation' (92) performed by a sonogram which turns an embryo into a he or a she, a process of '"girling"'. That initial interpellation is then reiterated by various authorities producing a 'naturalised effect' — it both defines a boundary and inculcates a norm.

Barad thinks that this particular kind of interpellation is remarkable and significant and should be analysed further. Butler dismisses this offhand. Can we just add appropriate material constraints, or do we need to revise the notion of discursive constraints as well?

Ultrasound technology has been discussed by feminists — Adams for example says that representations of mother fetus relationships in medical texts provide economic informational and ideological material. There are important issues of different access and different impact. Someone called Farquhar suggest that the machinery is part of a general campaign 'to hold pregnant women liable for causing prenatal harm' and to regulate the behaviour of pregnant women (93) . This reduces women into 'a mere maternal environment' and gives the fetus rights. This particularly impacts on 'poor, relatively disenfranchised pregnant women of colour who are drug abusers', and displaces the real importance of racialised poverty.

The machine itself therefore does not just map the body, but 'geopolitical, economic, and historical factors as well' [which assumes its interpellative property]. Another feminist, Ebert, argues that gender interpolation connects to relations of production, for example when girled foetuses are immediately aborted in non-Western countries, because 'families cannot afford to keep them'. These are examples of material as well as discursive factors. Butler would not deny this, but she does not show us how to take account of these constraints with their material dimensions. As a result, she cannot see what is specific to ultrasound technology and the way it works before conventional girling takes place at birth.

All this is rooted in 'representationalism and Newtonian physics' of the 17th century (94). Language was seen as something transparent that can transmit a picture of reality to the knowing mind. The parallel is the idea of a scientific theory that sees observation as a matter of discovery, passively gazing at the world, revealing 'an observation – independent reality'. Both of these have been questioned.

Böhr for example challenge these assumptions and came to investigate 'the connections between descriptive concepts and material apparatuses… The inseparability of the "objects of observation" and the "agencies of observation"', the ways in which agencies an observation and particular epistemic practices code constitute the objects of observation, the ways in which constraints and exclusions are interdependent, the material conditions for objective knowledge, re-formulating causality. We can also read it 'through a feminist lens'.

Böhr concluded that two central assumptions were flawed: that objects are independent of observation with well-defined intrinsic properties of their own which can be represented as universal concepts; measurement interactions between objects and observers are continuous and determinable, and depend on the objects. Instead, Böhr argued that theoretical concepts are defined by particular circumstances required for their measurement. It follows that the emerging discontinuity in measurement interactions suggested that there was no unambiguous way to distinguish objects and agencies of observation, so measured values cannot be attributed to observation independent objects alone — indeed there are no such 'well-defined inherent properties of these objects'(95).

Quantum wholeness provides a new framework based on not distinguishing objects and observers. Böhr's term is phenomenon — 'particular instances of wholeness'. In particular interactions between object and apparatus cannot be neglected or compensated for but are inseparable in the phenomenon, so all the '"relevant features of the experimental arrangement"' must be accounted for and described [quoting Böhr himself] [but relevant is a real weasel]. The physical [and conceptual, she adds?] apparatus is 'a non-dualistic whole', and concepts always refer to particular physical apparatuses. There is a 'constructed 'cut between object and agencies of observation — so that instruments with fixed parts are required so that we can understand the concept 'position'. Each apparatus excludes other concepts, such as 'momentum', which requires instruments with movable parts [and then, by entailment?] 'Physical and conceptual constraints and exclusions are co-constitutive' [assumes that we can cover all the important dimensions — position and momentum in this case].

What follows for the idea of observation? For Böhr, there are ideal experiments which help us understand events in an unambiguous way, especially to '"state the conditions necessary for the reproduction of the phenomena"'. This implies that there is a cut between an object and the agencies of observation, but this is constructed, not inherent. Every measurement in fact involves a choice of apparatus which provide the conditions necessary to define the variables and exclude others. The ambiguity is only resolved in particular contexts. Resolution arises from the wholeness of the phenomenon.

Nevertheless Böhr insists that quantum measurements are still objective. This obviously does not mean that there are inherent properties of independent objects. Instead it becomes a matter of permanent marks like those left on the apparatus. There is a necessary reference between objectivity and bodies which register these marks [which seems to smuggle in observer independence again?] However the property in question can't be assigned to an object or a measuring instrument — they are neither observation independent nor are they 'purely artifactual' created by measurement. Instead the properties refer to phenomena — 'physical – conceptual "intra actions"' (96). She introduces this neologism 'to signifie the inseparability of "objects" and "agencies of observation" (in contrast to "interaction," which reinscribes the contested dichotomy) [at the level of scientific observations, but there is no dichotomy at the social level, I insist].

Newtonian physics operates with strict determinacy and is therefore able to predict physical states. Böhr revises this idea and its implicit understanding of causality [more quotes from him]. However, he is not presuming 'overarching disorder, lawlessness, or an outright rejection of the cause and effect relationship' (97). But the traditional notion of causality is too closely connected to human '"feeling of volition"', and both are indispensable in the conventional understanding of the subject object relations. Both poles have to be rejected, neither freedom nor determinism but a third possibility.

The wave particle duality paradox produced further revisions. The duality is only a paradox to classical realism which sees the duality as a problem for the 'true ontological nature of light'. For Böhr, both wave and particle are descriptive concepts, relating not to independent physical objects but to 'mutually exclusive phenomena' — we are not recording an observation independent object but a phenomenon. This alone provides for objective knowledge — there are no observation independent objects to try to describe.

Back to Foucault where discipline makes individuals, sometimes through an observational apparatus — there we can see the effects of power as '"clearly visible"'. For Böhr, apparatuses are also productive of phenomena, but he is not clear where the apparatus actually ends — he has not established an outside boundary. So if we use a computer connected to an instrument does the computer become part of the apparatus — or the printer, or the paper and so on? He does focus on unambiguous communication as the key to objectivity which refers to bodies defining the experimental conditions which embody concepts to the exclusion of others. So this is an acknowledgement of the social nature of scientific practices, 'the interrelationship of complex discursive and material practices'. The definition of apparatus should acknowledge this complexity (98).

Foucault also examines conditions for intelligibility and the productive and constraining nature of practices embodied in apparatuses. If we read him and Böhr 'through one another' (99) we get a richer overall account. We extend Böhr from the physical conceptual to the material discursive more generally, and extend Foucault to include the natural sciences and nonhumans. We can also be more explicit about the relation between the apparatus the objects and the subjects of knowledge practices.

In Discipline, apparatuses of observation, production and discipline appear in 18th-century new technologies, especially the panopticon. It produces disciplined bodies, employing new political technology and power at a new micro level, operating through individual bodies. For Foucault this technologies diffuse, not easily grasped in systematic discourse, usually only a '"multiform instrumentation"', working through various apparatuses. However, he has not discussed 'the dynamics of intra-action and the inseparability of observing apparatus and observed'. He is right to say that the objects of knowledge, human subjects, do not preexist but emerge, but fails to see that these are also inseparable from the apparatuses. He does not have anything analogous to the phenomenon [bizarre critique — Foucault is not Böhr].

What if we consider Böhr? The panopticon might be the best kind of observing technology for the 18th-century, but we can consider ultrasound technology as a more contemporary apparatus. In that apparatus the transducer both makes and bridges boundaries. We can use it 'as the interface for the reading of Böhr's and Foucault's insights through one another' (100). Ultrasonics developed in Sonar technology first and was then applied to medicine, first abstractly and then more widely.

Fetal ultrasound images are now widespread, but interpreting them requires specialised forms of knowledge, and misdiagnosis is frequent. The transducer both sends and receives ultrasound waves, acting as 'the machine interface to the body' (101 the electrical signals become an image on the screen, but there are a number of influences — different sorts of tissues have different acoustic resistances, the interface geometry varies the beam, beam resolution itself can require different transducers, since the one has a natural resonant frequency. Producing and then reading ultrasound images is not simple. [The machine on its own is not very productive at all really, without the human interpreters etc]

In other words, we are not looking innocently at a fetus, nor are we simply constrained by the apparatus. It both produces images and is part of the body being imaged [I don't see how]. We can see the sonogram images as a phenomenon, co-constituted by intra-action between the apparatus and the object. The referent is not itself the object. Whether or not the fetus is seen as the referent depends on various political and scientific reasons, 'epistemology as well as ontology' [so they have not collapsed here -- but see notes below ]. Taking the object of observation as the referent can involve political advantages with consequences for the ways in which scientific practices are reiterated.

To fully understand the complexity we need to investigate the apparatuses. It is not just a transducer, with fixed properties ready for use the. The apparatus has to be constituted through particular practices, a creative and difficult matter of doing science, getting instruments to work. There is always intra-action with other apparatuses. Phenomena can be enfolded with implications for the way in which they materialise. The apparatus can undergo important shifts as a result. 'Which shifts actually occur matter for epistemological as well as ontological reasons' [still separate at this stage] (102). This means we are responsible for the actual ways in which particular practices that we can shape are sedimented out. Apparatuses materialise over time, and so they are themselves 'material discursive phenomena', only materialising after intra-action with other apparatuses. [not suprising that they produce material and discursive effects really -- they must do so if they are defined like this in the first place?]

For example transducers materialise and are re-materialised in interaction with several practices — those based on medical needs, design constraints, various legal and engineering constraints, market factors, political issues, R&D projects, the educational background of the designers, the workplace environment, how receptive the medical community and patients are to it, various legal cultural and political constraints, how patients are positioned, how technicians are trained [but why stop there?]. We can see these as showing the effects of disciplinary practices in Foucault's sense — legal educational medical architectural and so on. Physicians, engineers and scientists are subject to surveillance as well as the fetus — the apparatus both objectifies the fetus and subjectivates the technician or engineer.

Other material configurations and discursive formations are clearly involved as well. With Foucault, we need to remember that observation can involve discourses as practices forming objects. We can now use this to further articulate Böhr. However, Foucault also needs to be developed, because he sees nonhuman bodies as 'naturally given objects' (103) whereas they are really material in an equal way with human bodies. The division between human and nonhuman is a boundary constituted by practices. Foucault talks about materialisation operating through 'the soul', which then becomes ;a certain technology of power over the body'. A more general account is needed.

We must continue to talk about what is real, and avoid the 'anti-metaphysics legacy of positivism'. Developing ontology is risky because 'making metaphysical assumptions explicitly exposes the exclusion upon which any given concepts in of reality is based' as a result we have to recognise the inevitability of exclusions and also account for them responsibly. All these are present in her 'agential reality' (104).

Petersen quotes Böhr on language and reality to admit that we are always suspended in language and that 'reality' is only a word as well. However, he does not explain how he thinks this word should be used. To be consistent, he should agree that phenomena are constitutive of reality, a non-dualistic whole with no independent things causing them.

Classic realists assume that there is being prior to significations, Kantians say that being is inaccessible to language, while linguistic monists say that languages all. Agential reality, connects the material in the discursive — it is 'not a fixed ontology that is independent of human practices, but is continually reconstituted through our material – discursive intra-actions' (104) [which gets close to classic phenomenology]. This helps us formulate notions of realism and truth that is not based on representational knowledge, but rather to 'material instantiation in particular practices' (105). Theories describe not nature but 'our participation within nature'. Realism means 'providing accurate descriptions of agential reality' rather than some independent reality. Agential realism covers both this new realism and the larger 'epistemological and ontological framework'.

Certain practices sedimented reality and make it intelligible, so we are responsible not only for knowledge but 'in part, for what exists'[the bits we sedimented?]. Phenomena are produced through intra-actions by various apparatuses, but these apparatuse are 'themselves phenomena made up of specific intra-actions of humans and nonhumans'. However, the notion of human 'itself designates a particular phenomenon' and what gets defined as subject or object, and the definition of an apparatus is also 'intra actively constituted within specific practices' [so it's phenomenology all the way down].

We can understand this in a performative sense. [Lots of rhetorical questions here]. We are interested in the materialisation of bodies, which implies that not only material constraints, but the 'material dimension of regulatory practices' are important. Performativity becomes a matter of 'how matter comes to matter', not focused on discourse alone.

If we think of Butler, her notion of materialisation is not robust enough to extend beyond humans. It may not even be robust enough to describe things like the sexual materialisation of human bodies. If we turn to science and science studies we might gain more insight, developing 'a physicist's understanding of matter and scientific practices' (106) to extend feminist theories. This would help us see how 'the very atoms that make up the biological body come to matter' and in general 'how matter makes itself felt'. This might take full account of materiality without reinstating it as some 'natural uncontested ground' [so she wants to take on the usual definitions of nature in order to rescue the flexibility and non-naturalism of feminism?]

If we read 'agential realism and Butler's theory of performativity through one another' we are not assuming a symmetry between subject and object or physics and social science, but rather aiming at 'the production of mutually informative insights that might be useful in producing an enriched understanding'. We can do this by moving from citationality to intra-activity.

If apparatuses are produced and reproduced in interaction with other apparatuses as material – discursive phenomena, then agential reality takes on a certain temporality. 'Phenomena the effects of power – knowledge systems, boundary drawing projects'. practices constitute bodies such as subject and object. Phenomena are inseparable from apparatuses that produce them, so we can now see materialisation as something broader, related to the whole process of intra-activity. This might help Butler bring bodies to the fore again as an essential part of regulatory norms. We have to see bodies as material – discursive that materialise in interaction with other apparatuses, particular practices.

Butler's existing account is still limited. She sees the human body as 'perpetually vulnerable to the workings of social norms' (107) but does not adequately explain how norms materialise the body, that regulatory practices have a material nature, that discourse has a material effect. How is this materiality to be understood, and is it different in human affairs, and different from the way biological bodies materialise? Can agential realism help to explain why regulatory apparatuses can also be reworked, both through recently and new material arrangements?

Butler works with the surface of the human body, and this is important, as is the 'psychic dimension of regulatory practices' but we should extend it to nonhumans. Starting with the way in which the boundary between the nonhuman and the human is drawn. That is a practice that is 'always already implicated in particular materialisations'  (108) These practices applied to all bodies, except cyborg ones [which obviously gives  problems to conventional classifications]. The material dimension of regulatory apparatuses should be understood in terms of the general materiality of phenomena. There is no outside or independence. We can see regulatory practices as offering 'temporality', and 'causal (but nondeterministic) materialising effects' so materialisation becomes iteratively interactive, sedimenting out bodies through which phenomena become intelligible.

Speech acts become a special case. Language itself is materially instantiated in gestures or soundwaves, but their efficacy is not guaranteed — nor is any intra-action. Speaking does not make it so, nor does devising particular instruments in a lab. However it is all the same materiality, and this helps explain how language specifically affects the body. We require 'specific material discursive apparatuses' (109) [and what are these? Althusserian apparatuses?]. Materiality does not become effective just through discourse, but nor is it a fixed ground — there are 'material dimensions of constraints and exclusions'. We can now abandon any fixed difference between animate and inanimate matter. Materiality really refers to 'agential reality' and this is not just something outside culture, so we cannot 'reinstate materiality as natural' [the real issue for feminists, I suspect].

Agential realism helps us 'incorporate material constraints and exclusions', recognising them as processes in their own right. This will also help us understand 'the nature of abjection' [?]. The material and discursive are intertwined in apparatuses and their constraints 'operate through one another', so we need 'an analysis of both dimensions in their relationship to one another' [note dimensions].

Back to ultrasound. It's not just a physical instrument that views the fetus, but something which 'designates specific material – discursive practices' which limit what can be seen in produced. These limits are produced by its 'techno-scientific, medical, economic, political, biological, and cultural, et cetera development' [there is that et cetera clause again]. Particular usages in connections with other apparatuses have also developed it. Technological improvements helped the patient and practitioner 'to focus exclusively on the fetus'because its image becomes large and clear. Of course there are political discourses which facilitate and in part condition this focus [horrible weasel], especially if they stress the autonomy of the fetus. This then leads to [?] The exclusion of the subjectivity of the pregnant woman. This shows that constraints and exclusions are inseparable. [I think a conventional chronology would handle this]

We have some testimony from a pregnant woman being scanned, and how the team ignored her and focused on the baby. Then we have a piece by Haraway about the master slave dialectic related to objects of knowledge and knowers, and how agency becomes important in producing social theory. Without allowing for agency reproduce error in all sciences, we must acknowledge the agency of the world including its '"independent sense of humour"'. However, Casper argues that nonhuman agency can deflect attention from human accountability.

Back to Foucault. The subject is not determined by power relations because there is conflict and even resistance — but how are these possible? Butler says that Foucault needs to rethink causality and agency, but her own account can be extended.

For Foucault power is productive as well as constraining and it operates through the constitution of subjects, so what follows for determinism? For Butler, the very materialisation of the body invests it with power relations, that materiality is an effect of power, but she does not see this as just the effect of a discourse in a causal sense. Materialisation is not just '"a unilateral movement from cause to effect"'. Nor is the subject alone the agent, somehow outside a cultural field. Instead, agency is connected to performativity, and this is reiterative. This alone shows us that materialisation is never complete, nor is subjugation to norms. There are for example 'contradictory discursive demands on the subject', ambivalence. In other words norms are never finally embodied but are 'always part of a citational chain' (112).

Let us now compare agential realism. Böhr has already revised causality because there are necessary exclusions to draw boundaries between subject and object first. Material discursive apparatuses constrain what can be produced, but they also produce exclusions — this makes them 'constraining but not determining'. Intra-actions also open 'space for material discursive forms of agency', even if apparatuses themselves are not contradictory in the implications. Agency means intra-acting, enactment, not some possession of subjects. It involves making 'iterative changes to particular practices'. Enfolding is also a mechanism [actually not very extensively discussed]. Agency means looking at possibilities, but also accountability, especially enjoying boundaries.

However there is also thge nonhuman, which 'may seem a bit queer'. We have to separate it from subjectivity and intentionality, and see as an enactment. This will allow for both nonhuman and cyborg forms. For example in science the subject matter is often nonhuman, but there is clearly 'a sense in which "the world kicks back"', just as social interactions intervene in the construction of scientific knowledge. Casper works within science studies and suggest that classical notions of nonhuman agency depends on an underlying ontological dichotomy — but human and nonhuman are already '"heterogeneous entities"' [sounds like Latour here] (113). There are political assumptions, very clear in her work on 'experimental fetal surgery'. Here the fetus is constructed as a patient, a potential person, and this is assisted by ultrasound images — even the physicians refer to foetuses as humans. This can render pregnant women invisible, except as 'techno-maternal environments'. Casper says she wants nonhuman people and animals to have agency, but not necessarily foetuses — and says that she admits she's taking sides and developing a politics and that she is prepared to be accountable [male heroics again].

Barad agrees with Casper, but worries about whether there is a universal boundary. She also implies that you're only accountable to someone who is already described as an agent. If we challenge these, we might reconsider fetal agency. There might be 'a need to strategically invoke fetal agency to counter the material effects of sexism rather forms of oppression' (114). Excluding their agency might come to support early abortion of female foetuses. We need to be extra vigilant in the face of 'global neocolonialism', and not foreclose agency in a way that disguises accountability. The attribution of agency 'is a political issue'.

It's not clear that fetal agency is a universal culprit. Some kind of feminist interventions, such as recommending midwifery not medical berthing might need to acknowledge the agency of the fetus. We might need to rethink 'the referent of the attribution' and thus the framing of agency. She would start by asking about the fetus itself. It has been constructed as a subject by both law and objectivism, where scientists are allowed to interpret the world. The pregnant woman herself is absent, and so are the background medical, scientific, and legal practices. It is these that have reduced the fetus as something less than a subject, not just the notion of fetal agency — general subjectivity rather than specific agency has played a crucial role in abortion debates. We should understand the fetus in relation to agential reality.

Viewed in this way, it is not just a pre-existing object of investigation, but a phenomenon, constituted and reconstituted out of intra-actions between material–discursive apparatuses. It includes those apparatuses — the pregnant woman is another. This issue is  boundary articulations between the fetus and those other apparatuses, and these are 'particular historically and culturally specific intra-actions of material discursive apparatuses'. They are connected to matters of race and class — the apparent epidemic of infertility affecting black women has been used 'as a justification for the expanded development of a range of new reproductive technologies for the production of white babies',(115)  and has deflected attention from environmental racism. These new reproductive technologies reproduce both the fetus and particular race relations. These are just as important as the specific focus on fetal agency in Casper.

Agency is a matter of specific practices, and apparatuses are phenomena which can include intra-actions of humans and nonhuman is. These apparatuses of bodily production can be re-figured after exploiting various 'possibilities and accountability'. It is not a matter of attributing full subjectivity to a fetus even if it can '"kick back"' (116). Nor is it a simple object separate from the other apparatuses interacting with it, including its mother. For that matter, nor should we isolate the mother as something with full responsibility for fetal well-being. The real questions include how fetal subjectivity is a construction arising from particular material discursive practices, and how accountability is deflected from healthcare and nutrition apparatuses, themselves the 'consequences of global neocolonialism'. [Again this is convenient political exploration of connections and nestings, and global neocolonialism does seem to be the external boundary]

We can rework these apparatuses, in ways which include 'subversion, resistance, opposition, and revolution'. These in turn depend upon forms of agency of all kinds. It would be irresponsible to think that we are the only active beings — 'though this is never justification for deflecting that responsibility onto other entities'. Human accountability is not lessened but extended to 'existing power asymmetries'(117) [infinitely extended].

For example, we can resist by changing our practice after 'enfolding the material instantiation of subversive re- significations' (117) [unfortunate relapse into bullshit — we can explore subversive possibilities once we start?]. Or we can directly change material conditions of people's lives. E Sourbut argues that the new reproductive technologies might be subversive, for example in leading to 'gynogenesis'[embryos without males], and suggest that the so-called naturalism of sex has already been challenged by test-tube conceptions. The technique has also brought attention to gene imprinting, another 'form of nonhuman agency'. Again these are to be understood performativity, not as mere descriptions. There may be further 'techno-scientific intra-actions' if we can understand this form and how it changes with other agential shifts in bodily production. We have to intra act responsibly of course and this means 'thinking critically about the boundaries, constraints, and exclusions that operate through particular material – discursive apparatuses interacting with other important apparatuses' [ad infinitum].

New reproductive technologies have already been used in ways for which they were not intended — implanting lesbians with embryos originally created in the partners for example. These subversive acts depend on 'the instability of hegemonic apparatuses', and are a combination of reinforcing and destabilising elements — for example challenges to patriarchy 'are accompanied by the reinforcement of class asymmetries' and the 'cultural overvaluation of raising children that are genetic offsprings' (118)

The PEC is developing into a new techno-scientific practice — 3-D ultrasonography [MRI scanning?]. This development depends on suitable computer technology, which explains its recent materialisation. The implications are increased as well, and there seem to be 'epistemic earnings potential of this virtual reality tour of the body'. Images are lifelike, making the representation of the object seem 'isomorphic with the object itself', although it's even better than natural vision because it can zoom or rotate images, or slice them. It replaces the x-ray look of the ultrasound scan. — 'It has no respect for surfaces'(119) the computer integrates two-dimensional images and this restores opacity — the surface is constructed from the information about the volume. This makes the new technology 'a particularly poignant instrument and vector of power'.

There are intra-action with other practices, including debates about abortion, and many other non-obstetrical uses. It will help us understand human biology and change surgery. It will lead to a more complex understanding of bodies — it will no longer do just to operate at the surface. It might produce insights into the whole relations between surface and volume, and there might be other consequences of different mappings, different boundaries. Feminist theory might provide insights here, as in the worries about the referent and the seductiveness of visual representations in epistemology and ontology. There will be issues raised for patients subjectivity and feminists need to get involved — hence 'they need to understand the laws of nature as well as the law of the father' (120), but must also intra- act instead of studying this topic in isolation.

Notes are gripping as well. Note  1 (120)  suggests that epistemology and ontology ought to collapse because being and knowing are inseparable, as in her forthcoming work. Note 2 says that she is interested in Böhr's epistemology not his particular view of quantum theory. She says that the Böhr did not originally see that his epistemology was necessarily applicable only to the microscopic realm, because they were 'circumscribed by Planck's constant'. He did say that if that constant been larger we would have seen obvious effects to challenge representationalism. Barad says she is not just pursuing analogies between micro and macro, but elaborating Böhr's insights into matters like conditions for objectivity, the cultural factors in scientific knowledge production and the efficacy of science in the face of continuing demonstrations of its contingency. Note 6 says that wholeness needs to be re-conceptualised to clarify issues for feminists. It does not mean that all boundaries are dissolved, but rather that concepts apply only in the context 'as specified by constructing boundaries' it also implies the material and the discursive are inseparable. But the whole always requires 'differentness', against the utopian dream of ending all boundaries' (121). Note 8 points out that Foucault's real limitations to confine his attention to human bodies, and Rouse had already argued it should be extended more to natural sciences. Note 9 refers to a technological threshold in the development of disciplinary apparatuses so that any mechanism of objectification could be used [Foucault]. Note 10 says that she does use Foucault's account to try and articulate an outside boundary, [a discourse?]  but Böhr will redirect us to the inside boundaries which will provide 'significant corrective to Foucault's account'. Note 12 says that in intra-activity phenomena that are materialising are already implicated in other practices that are also materialising. This means we need to rethink causality, but not abandon it — 'materialisation is an open (but nonarbitrary) process. Note 13 says she has flirted with scientific literacy projects. Note 15 says that PEC's are used in non-medical applications as well including the design of smart skis and smart aircraft. Note 17 says that Böhr saw the constitutive outside as a matter of material discursive exclusions as well, making intelligibility and material exclusions 'indissociable' [sic--cannot be dissociated?]. Note 18 sites a particular dispute with Butler about what Foucault's Discipline is arguing: Butler says that he is theorising the materialisation of the prison as well as the prisoner, but Barad reads that is insisting on the material arrangements that constitute the prison and sustain discourses which is not the same thing as saying that the materiality of the prison is constituted by power relations. She also thinks's remark about materialisation through the soul is inadequate. She repeats that but there needs a better account of materialisation and materiality, and the way in which is implicated in boundaries between the human and the nonhuman. Note 19 compares Böhr and Butler in their critiques of representationalism [notes 'parallels']. Butler says that the body is always seen as prior to the sign, so that significations produces the body that it claims to discover. It follows that language is not representational or mimetic but productive, performative [but Butler did not follow this through?]. Note 20 says that she is not presuming the universal applicability of agential realism, but she is suspicious about anti-realism, often assumed in scientists saying that they are just making something work, working for fun rather than searching for truth. This has dominated post-war culture in physics, 'especially in the classroom' which leads her to suspect that this anti-realism is 'yet another symptom of late capitalism and the accompanying epidemic of abnegation of responsibility and accountability' (123), linked to consumer cultures pleasure in the plasticity of bodies or morphing. Restoring realism 'can provide a balanced against current tendencies that confuse theorising with unconstrained play' (124).
 
Note 22 refers to reading one text through another as 'particularly appropriate' to agential realism, while reading one text against another 'involves reifiying or fixing of the text against which the other is viewed' [I think the risks are the same]. This is like agential realism and intra-action as a 'nondeterministic alternative dynamics' as opposed to notions like influence impact or embedding — these can sometimes 'wrongly attribute agency to reified notions called Culture, Power, Discourse, et cetera'. Note 24 says it is Butler's notion of abjection she is discussing, referring to ways in which the human is 'differentially constituted' — this account 'privileges human bodies from the start'. Note 26 says that Butler's argument about different kinds of materiality, signified by different academic disciplines is a sign of limitation — Barad prefers to say that it is 'the intra-action of these different disciplinary apparatuses [that] contributes to the materialisation of the body [so rejecting multidisciplinary approaches and dimensions?] Note 27 says that Casper criticises ANT for wrongly recognising the fetus as a subject. Barad says agential realism avoids this issue because what constitutes the subject is that if you, and agency is not aligned with subjectivity.

Note 30 says that STS can address material agency in a limited way because it conflates material with nature or nonhuman and this saves what is human for the purely cultural domain. This note also insist that we still talk about cyborgian agency — not discussed as far as I know in any subsequent work. Other accounts include AMT and Haraway, and one exponent, Pickering, sees the tangle between the human and the nonhuman as post-humanist — although he still retains humanism to explain scientific choice. Note 31 refers to other debates involving ANT. Note 32 denies that the term apparatus means mere instrument or technology. Instead they are phenomena made up of specific interactions of both human and nonhuman — what defines some phenomena as a subject or object, while others are defined as an apparatus 'is interactively constituted through specific practices' [very abstract and general again].

Note 37 says that MRI scanning can obscure the patient's subjectivity, because the body can continue to be scanned after the patient has left, or even remotely This carries an obvious danger of removing people from decisions about them.

back to Barad page