Notes on: Bourdieu, P (1987) What Makes a Social class? On The Theoretical and Practical Existence Of Groups. Berkeley Journal of Sociology.32: 1--17. https://www.jstor.org/stable/41035356

Dave Harris

[Very useful condensed account of his position]

[A paper at a symposium]. One obstacle to scientific sociology arises from common oppositions, concepts or 'what Bachelard calls "epistemological couples"' which are constructed by social reality and are unthinkingly used to construct social reality. One is the opposition between objectivism and subjectivism, or structuralism and constructivism. Social agents can be treated as things, classified like objects and this is a break with naïve subjective classifications which are seen instead as '"pre-notions" or "ideologies"' (1). From this objectivist point of view agents construct social reality which is an aggregation of these individual acts of construction, so there's no need to break with primary social experience, but instead to give an '"account of accounts"'. However, this is a false opposition because agents are both classified and classifiers although they classify according to their position within classifications. We see this if we analyse the notion of 'point of view… a perspective, a partial subjective vision (subjectivist moment); but it is at the same time, a perspective, taken from a point, from a determinate position in an objective social space (objectivist moment)' (2). We can develop both moments as they apply to the analysis of class.

So are classes a scientific construct, or do they exist in reality, which is also a political question, one of the major principles of division in current politics. Political choices will be involved as well as stances on the mode of knowledge. Those who assert the existence of classes tend to take a 'realist stand' and often attempt to determine empirically properties and boundaries of the various classes, sometimes their individual members. Others will argue that classes are 'nothing but constructs of the scientist', with no foundation whatsoever in reality and that it is impossible to find 'clear-cut discontinuities'. Instead we find continuous distributions such as with income, between classes and between men and women, as in the 'embourgeoisment of the working class' (3). This involves accepting a 'substantialist philosophy, which 'recognises no other reality than that which is directly given to the intuition of ordinary experience'.

It might still be possible to accept that there are differences based on economic and social processes and to adopt 'relational or structural modes of thinking characteristic of modern mathematics and physics' which stress relationships rather than substances. We can thus talk of social reality in Marx and Durkheim in terms of invisible relationships constituting a space of positions defined by the relative distance to each other, where reality 'is nothing other than the structure as a set of constant relationships which are often invisible' obscured by ordinary sense experience. Substantiality is not denied, and a social space is seen as offering 'reciprocal externality of the objects it encloses'.

Science constructs the space 'which allows us to explain and to predict the largest possible number of differences observed between individuals… The main principles are differentiation necessary or sufficient to explain or predict the totality of the characteristics observed'. The social world is 'a multi dimensional space that can be constructed empirically by discovering the main factors of differentiation'. We can consider these as 'the powers or forms of capital which are or can become efficient… aces in a game of cards… for the appropriation of scarce goods of which this universe is the site' (4). The distribution of the various forms of capital provides the structure of the space, that is the distribution of active properties within the universe under study, those which confer 'strength, power and consequently profit on their holder'.

In French society, 'and no doubt in the American society of today', these fundamental social powers are, 'according to my empirical investigations, firstly economic capital in its various kinds; secondly cultural capital or better, informational capital, again in its different kinds; and thirdly forms of capital that are very strongly correlated, social capital which consists of resources based on connections and group membership, and symbolic capital which is the form the different capitals take once they are perceived and recognised as a legitimate'. Agents are distributed according to the global volume of capital, next according to the composition of the capital, the relative weight of the various forms, and thirdly according to their trajectory in social space, the 'evolution in time of the volume and composition of their capital'. Agents in sets of them are assigned a position or location or a class of neighbouring positions, a particular area within a space which is defined by their relative position 'in terms of a multi dimensional system of coordinates'. Occupation may be 'a good and economical indicator of position'.

There is a danger that this relational mode of thinking will be interpreted in a 'realist and "substantialist' way, whereas they are really logical analytic constructs theoretically dividing a theoretical space. The more accurate they get, the greater the chance that they will be seen as real groups. They are based on the principles of differentiation which are the most effective in reality, 'i.e. the most capable of providing the fullest explanation of the largest number of differences observed between agents… Well founded in reality' (5). If we have grouped people properly, the classes will be 'as distinct as possible from one another' and we will get 'the largest possible separation between classes of the greatest possible homogeneity'.

However, the means used to display the social space 'tend to obscure it from view' . That's because those in close social classes share a number of common properties, while those most distant have few properties in common [I think the point is that those close together see no differences in society, while those far apart are ignorant of them]. The dispositions acquired 'involve an adjustment to this position, a 'sense of one's place', where common folk remain humbly in their place, keep their distance. This may be 'totally unconscious and take the form of what we commonly call timidity or arrogance'. The social distances 'are inscribed in the body'. Objective distances are reproduced in 'subjective experience of distance… Remoteness in space associated with the form of aversion or lack of understanding, while nearness is lived as a more or less unconscious form of complicity. This sense of one's place is at the same time a sense of the place of others'. This is reinforced by 'affinities of habitus experienced in the form of personal attraction or revulsion'. This lies at the root of 'all processes of co-optation, friendship, love, association et cetera' [including racial prejudice?].

So classes are analytic constructs founded in reality but the people located in them are affected in their social being, by 'a certain class of material conditions of existence, of primaeval experiences of the social world, et cetera' (6) and relationally in relation to other positions including those in the middle. They are homogenised and they have dispositions which 'favour the development of relationships formal or informal' which increase homogeneity, and thus develop resemblance and coming together.

We have arrived at 'all the requirements of the scientific taxonomy, at once predictive and descriptive'. We have categories obtained by 'cutting up sets characterised by the similarity of their occupational conditions within the three-dimensional space'. These have a high predictive capacity but 'a relatively small cognitive expense (that is relatively little information as necessary… three coordinates)'. These help us describe and classify agents and their practices. The project was expressed first by Halbwachs apparently, then  Centers on the psychology of social classes.

We can therefore suggest that theoretical classes are real classes, as Marx did, moved by the consciousness of the 'identity of their conditions and interests… Which simultaneously unites them and opposes them to other classes' (7). However Marx committed a 'theoreticist fallacy' like Hegel by equating constructed classes with real classes, 'the things of logic with the logic of things' by suggesting that theoretical classes somehow became automatically real classes. The argument was that the identity of conditions must inevitably assert itself with time, or that consciousness would awaken and the objective truth realised, or that the Party would provide a suitable vision to reconcile the two. All this would result in 'the analytical construct [being] made into a folk category'.

At best a theoretical class might be considered as a probable real class which could be mobilised on the basis of their similarities, that the social space could offer probabilities with draw individuals together or apart. The movement from probability to reality can never be given, and 'the principles of vision and division of the social world at work… Have to compete in reality with other principles, ethnic, racial or national, and more concretely still, with principles imposed by the ordinary experience of occupational, communal and local divisions and rivalries'. It might still be possible to argue that the perspective taken when constructing theoretical classes may be the most '"realistic"' in that 'it relies on the real underlying principles and practices' but this still will not impose itself on agents 'in a self-evident manner'. Agents will only follow 'the laws immanent in [their] universe through the mediation of their sense of place' (8).

Anything else dismisses the question of politics and of political work required 'to impose a principle of vision and division of the social world' even those that are well founded in reality. Classes that realise themselves through class struggle 'do not exist'. They only assent to a particular form after 'specific work, of which the specifically theoretical production of a representation of the divisions is a decisive element', and that only after political labour is armed with the theory 'well founded in reality', when it persuades people that what it argues is 'more present, in a potential state, in reality itself'. What we are talking about is a specific logic in order to produce classes in the form of objective institutions — 'symbolic production… political work of class making'. This is more likely to be effective when agents are already close to one another in social space and already belong 'to the same theoretical class'.

However there may be an occupational basis or a genealogical basis in precapitalist societies, but groups are 'always the product of a complex historical work of construction', as EP Thompson's book indicates [he also mentions Boltanski and the creation of the managerial class in France]. The English working class is a 'well-founded historical artefact', just as Durkheim saw religion as a well-founded illusion, the same with any other group like the elderly, or the family. When it appears in popular discourse, it is as 'one of those impeccably real social fictions produced and reproduced by the magic of social belief' (9).

Any occupational groups or classes are symbolic constructions shaped by specific interests and cognitive struggles between laymen and between various professionals who try to represent the social world. Sometimes social scientists attempted to set themselves up as referees between these rival constructions, but all are 'constitutive of the reality of the social world'. The criteria used in the construction of objective space are also 'instruments – I should say weapons – and stakes in the classification struggle'. The relative value of different kinds of capital, or among different kinds of capital is constantly being brought into question and reassessed. There are struggles aimed at inflating or deflating the value of one or the other type — economic titles or educational credentials, MBAs versus MA's, age or sex. There is no overall coherent or logical system because there is always a practical or convenient element, and constantly variable taxonomies. There are also different levels of aggregation and differentiation [specialists and connoisseurs have more categories]

There is no strict opposition between realist, objectivist and structuralist perspectives on the one hand and constructivist, objectivist, spontaneous divisions on the other. Any proper theory must include subjective representations and the contributions they make, and the symbolic work of fabrications of groups and their representations. There is always a struggle different distributions, and unequal resources. There is no 'universal core and universal sense' (11). Reality is relatively indeterminate and pluralistic, hence the diversity of viewpoints because of the diversity of positions. Reality can be strongly structured, but symbolic space can have variable visible distinctions and distinctive signs. Agents vary in terms of the extent to which they have relevant categories of perception, the extent to which signs of social positions are 'immediately discernible through their visible manifestations'. There are also 'bluffs or symbolic inversions (the intellectual's Volkswagen Beetle)'. Even statistical connections are not that constant and reliable.

There are particular problems in the intermediate zones of the space, characterised by indeterminacy and fuzziness and more room for 'symbolic strategies designed to jam this relationship' (12). Goffman has charted this particular region with his observation of many forms of the presentation of self. There are also many examples of how even the most reliable symbols of social position such as occupations and social origin can be manipulated displayed or concealed, played with, covered by simultaneous memberships. The same goes with political strategies — the intermediate groups are particularly difficult to win over by the various political parties. The boundaries are more like those of a cloud or forest, or a flame. Indeed the definition of boundaries is one of the major stakes in the struggle and can become a political force, one of the 'properly political collective struggles' such as those who can monopolise symbolic violence, impose a legitimate vision of the social world, 'power over words used to describe groups or institutions which represent them' (14), often by employing the services of professionals of representation who operate within a 'closed, relatively autonomous field, namely the field of politics'.

[And some strange philosophical stuff about whether something that is represented is 'nothing other than what represents it', or that an individual represents the group or embodies it 'in and through his very person… Makes it exist'. 'The signified, that is, the group, is identified with the signifier' [which relates to all sorts of interesting discussions that philosophers had]. The nub of it is that any 'otherwise elusive social collective exists, if and only if there exists one (or several) agent (s) who can assert with reasonable chance of being taken seriously… That they are the "class"' (15). In other words if there are agents who can impose themselves as somehow authorised to speak or act officially in the place of and in the name of, with full power, as members of the class, they can 'confer upon it the only form of existence a group can possess'. This is 'logic of existence by delegation', and it has a particular force if members of a class 'lack any individual means of action and expression' or 'equal opportunity of acceding to the various forms of collective existence… Diminished form of existence', some form of diminished existence, dispossession, sometimes by movements that are supposed to represent them [I think], but which take the actual form of a select club.

Everything will depend on the balance of power, the symbolic capital accumulated by those who try to impose the various visions and the extent to which they are grounded in reality, the extent to which dominated visions can be constituted. An action will succeed in transforming the social world 'when it is founded in reality'. The vision of the dominated is 'doubly distorted'. First their categories of perception are imposed on them by the objective structures of the world, which they tend to accept ('a form of doxic acceptance of its given order') (16). Second the dominant groups try to impose their own vision and representations in order to develop 'a "theodicy of their privilege"'. However, the dominated do have 'a practical mastery, a practical knowledge of the social world' which can result in 'nomination' — 'when it is well founded in reality, naming involves a truly creative power… Revelation'. They can invoke 'the mystery of ministery [sic]', and this can have 'a truly magical effect by giving power to truth: words can make things', and even the dominated can join in the 'objectivized symbolisation of the group they designate' and as a result they can 'if only for a time make exist as groups collectives which already existed, but only in a potential state' [very mysterious! Reminds me a bit of Badiou on the power of witness, somebody standing up and testifying, declaring that the king has no clothes?]