Notes on: Fox, N & Alldred, P.
(2023). Applied Research, Diffractive
Methodology, and the Research – Assemblage:
Challenges and Opportunities. Sociological
Research Online 28 (1): 93 – 109. DOI:
10.1177/1360780421102997
Dave Harris
[This distinguishes between diffractive analysis
of texts, and that which approaches data analysis.
That involves reading empirical research with
other materials 'including researchers
perspectives, memories, experiences and emotions —
to provide novel insights and events'. It seems to
be based on Barad and Bohr on the necessary
implication of the observer with the experiment,
the 'agential cut and more loosely, 'the
situatedness of all research data'. They want to
understand it through D and G and the research as
assemblage to get a better understanding of the
entanglements between research and its subject
matter.It is a classic example of forgetting
Barad on quantum theory altogether and seeing
'diffraction' as any interaction between
researchers and data]
They want to focus on evidence to inform practice
or policy. They recognise a tension in
sociological research, including questioning
whether social enquiry can adequately represent or
reflect the social world it studies. Some have
recommended a minor science perspective instead,
involving flows and becomings, a world in flux.
The problem is that the evidence so generated does
not always productively informed practice policy
or activism. Diffractive methodology (DM) might
need modification.
The approach was developed by Haraway and Barad
and has been adopted by various others. It intends
to show where the effects of difference appear,
and to explore engagements and interferences
between world and social researcher. Barad drew
her insights from Foucault, Butler [?] and Bohr.
DM makes explicit entanglements and differences by
reading data through 'other texts , personal
experiences, or other data'. This leads to context
specificity, but this only reassures us that
research findings are relevant and applicable.
However, there is a potential to generate 'a near
infinite multiplicity contingent — and different —
conclusions from research data' (95). They propose
a new materialist framework offering a more
nuanced assessment, looking at how exactly and to
what extent observations affect data.
Ethicoontoepistemology (EOE) entangles [!]
researchers with their responsibilities for
research, ethical responsibility and the apparatus
with its epistemological implications.
Socio-material processes interact and diffraction
when studied makes this evident, including
'"changing and contingent ontology of the world,
including the ontology of knowing"' (citing Barad
2007, 73). Data produced by research is
'unavoidably[!] a diffraction' rather than
representation or reflection of the world.
DM may explore diffraction phenomena, 'the ways in
which social processes diffract the world as they
intra-act', and the way in which data analysis may
be 'tuned' the better to understand phenomena.
Neither of these offers a strict methodology for
research design: the first is a focus on
diffractions and interferences, and the second is
a data analytic method.
One root is in quantum mechanics, especially the
diffraction patterns produced by the two slit
experiments. Bohr referred apparently to
'"phenomena"' to refer to 'specific instances of
entanglements between quanta [yes -- materia
phenomena] and observers/measurement
devices/theories' (96) [citing Barad 1996) [not
just the modern sense then]. Barad extends these
findings to the social world leading to agential
realism acknowledging the entanglement of research
and research apparatus and leading to a focus on
'"things in phenomena"' [citing 1996]. The
particular point of view established by research
designs method for theories become '"agential
cuts"'.
IN social enquiry, we must attend to entanglements
and read insights through one another while paying
attention to patterns of difference. Science has
not been successful because of its observer
independent knowledge, but rather because it has
produced data via human engagements relevant to
the human enterprise [1996 again], producing a
particular '"cut"'. [I must chcek this]
Secondary literature also follows the distinction
between entanglements on diffractions in social
processes and the data analytic method to read
texts. For the former, the emphasis is being on a
way to '"question the nature of space, time,
number and life"' [citing de Freitas 2017], or to
examine the entanglements of bodies texts, data
language and theory {Mazzei 2013]. Barad on
Hiroshima [unrefd --do they mean Hayashi?] So is
'the interferences and diffractions between
nuclear physics, culture geopolitics and life'(97
)Pienaar et al (2017) apparently explored how
dualism in stereotypes and biomedical discourses
produced 'differing agenda shortcuts and social
perspectives upon drug use'. Dixon-Romain (2016)
investigated the effects of quantification and
also rehabilitated quantitative methods.
Most studies however have focused on reading data
texts together. Mazzei generated multiple
diffractive reading is by reading data from
different theoretical perspectives. Renold and
Ringrose (2017) drew data from two disparate case
studies to study gender and power. Lenz Taguchi
and Palmer (2013) applied specific agenda
shortcuts in their reading of data [the bullshit
about how they brainstormed the project]. At least
they realised that researchers are responsible for
the 'choice of agential cuts' and that their own
identities might have affected this choice.
At least the approach rejects essentialism and
nature/culture dualism. Instead material factors
are not fixed and stable but emergent, with
context specific properties. 'Intra-action'
emphasises this — 'there is nothing "beyond" with
which to interact' (98) [crazy!!]. They also want
to congratulate Barad for supporting, of all
things constructionism, retaining much of the
language and concerns around performative of the
and ethical responsibility in feminism and
'smoothing the ontological shift' towards a
're-immersion in materiality'
Criticism includes extending findings from quantum
theory to the macro world, while ignoring other
explanations, such as Bohm. Pinch suggests that
the whole messy history has been ignored. Perhaps
Bohr, and therefore Barad is only one agential
shortcut among many, and it might be threatened
still alternatives be accepted.
Another problem is that most DM studies have
ignored practical findings and how they are
affected by research design, in favour of data
analysis and reporting. There is clear influence
in the analytic cuts pursued by the researchers
'history experience or perspective' as
acknowledged by Lenz Taguchi and Palmer. This
increases context dependency, and rules out
combinations with other less context -dependent
methods such as quantitative analysis. This
further limits transferability.
They argue that key specific issues are not
addressed — how observers affect events, how data
are affected by the actual process, and how some
kinds of observation affect data more than others
(99). There is no way to gauge whether effects are
minimal or massive, or exactly how observation
affects events, such as hawthorn effects, or
asking leading questions. There is no clear
guidance about observer interactions.
Deleuze's materialist methodology offers
improvements Deleuze is a 'monist' [a process
ontologist], advocating minor science that follows
flows of events, with the Observer part of the
phenomenon under investigation, rejecting
researchers representation. However, minor science
'should run alongside representational "major"
science, rather than entirely substituting for it'
[citing TP 367]. So we are going to refine both
Barad and Deleuze through a diffractive approach.
Deleuze has a Spinozist ontology [citing the
little book on Spinoza], where materiality is not
defined by form substance or 'subjectivity' but by
emergent capacities to affect or to be affected
[the bit everyone gets] Effective
arrangements of bodies and things are
'assemblages… Constellations of matter', (100)
unstable yet productive. They display affective
interactions or affect economies and these
determine what a body can do. Assemblages replace
individuals or bodies, and analysis is to disclose
affect economies in assemblages and the capacities
produced. Event assemblages produce micropolitical
moments of power and resistance. Research is also
an assemblage, say various deleuzians, assembling
from research tools, analytic technologies and
machinery, and findings of earlier studies the
data generated and ethical principles, and
everything else to generate outputs from multiple
affects. It's not just a matter of the agency of
the researchers. This is like Barad on research
apparatuses as open-ended material discursive
phenomena that themselves reconfigure space and
time. [Although Deleuze emphasises better?] 'The
micropolitical processes that produce "research
knowledge"' (101).
The interference between apparatus and assemblage
leads to explorations of entanglements between
events and research [ordinary understanding of
entanglements]. Research assemblages need to be
affected by events if their information is to be
relevant. Affects in research assemblages must not
overwhelm those in event assemblages, though for
fear of producing unintended effects like bias
[and here they equate Bohr to the Hawthorne
effect]. We can investigate this in more detail.
Qualitative interview assemblages, for example
privilege human accounts and then researcher
interpretations, while randomised trials establish
controlled environments and statistical
techniques, privileging the model over real-life
conditions. Each research assemblage has a series
of 'simpler research machines' each of which
performs specific tasks like data collection or
ethical review, each with a 'specific affect
economy' (102). We can do micropolitical analysis
on these machines to gain greater precision on
their transformative effects, for example how data
is coded. In general, the perspectives of
researchers over the researched are nearly always
privileged; data is nearly always aggregated 'to
produce uniformity and underplay real world
changes' and sometimes to alter events; however
something of the event finds its way through, if
only as traces. In general any specific research
technique 'transforms ("diffracts") the event it
is studying' (103) [so any transformation is a
diffraction]. Research methods lacking an impact
on the social world is just the same as Bohr
arguing that macro scales physical systems are not
affected by apparatuses [?]. [They also use the
term 'interference pattern' to describe the
'differing ontologieis of research apparatus and
research assemblage' — these are really
differences of scale and intention?]
Diffractive readings produce analytic cuts. This
happens because data are read in relation to
another source of affect, for example the
analyst's own experiences including emotional
responses, as in Lenz Taguchi and Palmer [but this
is crap]. This shows their 'entanglement with the
event they studied' and how it was powerfully
affected by their own 'affect economy', in effect
privileging their perspective: Fox and Aldred call
this a '"re-diffraction"'.
So Barad shows us the way to acknowledge Data produced
by research is 'unavoidably[!] a diffraction'
rather than representation or reflection of the
world.
or assemblages [does she bollopx]. The
inevitability of entanglement leads to a
diffractive approach rather than a representation,
a multiplicity of possible knowledges. However
there are problems if you are interested in policy
or practice. The questions asked earlier can now
be addressed.
It all depends on the ability now to do
micro-politics and analysis of the way in which
research designs methods and techniques are
actually entangled with the events, and how these
entanglements affect [further specified as
'"diffract", 'interfere with" the data] (104),
which adds an additional toolkit, especially
because we can now reveal the different extent to
which this takes place and assess the effects. We
do 'meticulous micropolitical analysis'. We can
use any specific research method or technique as
long as we calibrate it according to the
'requirements of the particular research study or
its sponsors', and proceed strategically, to
produce findings but which also acknowledge the
effects that research has and offer an assessment
of them in the form of '"health warnings"', a
pragmatic resolution.
[Page 105 offers a table spelling out these
techniques in more detail — pretty banal]
Barad seems to offer the total rejection of major
science, unlike Deleuze and Guattari, and unlike
Braidotti in her critical
posthumanities piece. DeLanda also argues
against We need to remain 'methodologically
open inclusive' (106) rather than opting for one
or the other, using 'representational
approximation and theoretical elaboration'
cautiously if necessary, while acknowledging
inevitable entanglements and seeing what effects
they have. Approaches should be chosen that are
best suited to research aims, and these may
include diffraction, but a plurality of methods
and techniques are at our disposal. However we
should 'always [be] fully aware of how these
research assemblages diffract the data they
produce' (106).
NB Real
Barad “wrongly attribute agency to reified
notions called Culture, Power, Discourse, et
cetera”. Ideas are not just in her head— “they
are specific ongoing reconfigurings of the world
in its iterative intraactivity… threaded through
‘me’ and ‘me’ through them” (Jeuleskjaer and
Schwennesen 2012, 23). Specifically, it would be
wrong to see her own work as a narrative
produced by a conventional subject “since this
position is counter to diffracting. There is no
I that exists outside the diffraction pattern,
observing it, telling its story. In an important
sense, this story in its ongoing (re)patterning
is (re)(con)figuring me” (2014, 181). More
generally, “all ‘selves’ are not themselves but
rather the iterative intraactivity of all matter
of time-beings… dispersed/diffracted through
being and time” (Barad 2017, 80). For that
matter, human memory is not a feature of human
consciousness but is materialised, embedded or
sedimented in objects such as landscapes.
“the shockingly
anthropocentric hypothesis that human
consciousness collapses the superposition
Barad (2008b)
Empirical and
political commitments are necessary to prevent
arguments looking like idealistic moralising or
as another abstract scholastic intervention in
philosophy. Nevertheless, making the arguments
materially relevant requires an examination of
the social world to avoid mere idealism, as Marx
showed with historical materialism. The problem
arises in Barad herself in the various
discussions about material limits to various
processes. The most obvious issue is whether
apparatuses have an outer limit. If they do not,
then possibilities are endless with nothing to
limit them, and, correspondingly, no constraint
on, and no possibility of testing for, creative
thought. We could grasp the possibilities
entirely within thought and consciousness itself
as in classic idealism. Barad notes the problem
and offers a partial solution in offering
Foucault and discourse as an outer limit for
apparatuses. She also mentions materiality as a
constraint, but her actual position over the
possibility of empirical falsifiability, for
example, seems unclear as we saw.
Barad’s phrase is that
responsibility is “an incarnate relation that
precedes the intentionality of
consciousness.” Barad (2007) has this
phrase in a section close to the end entitled
“Towards an Ethics of Mattering”, which begins
with citing Levinas, or rather a reading of
Levinas by Ziarek. This is further described as
a “materialist” reading in later work (Barad
2010), and the context there is the familiar one
of having to materialise accounts to remedy any
humanism before any diffraction can be pursued.
an embodied
sensibility which responds to its proximal
relationship to the other through a mode of
wonderment that is antecedent to consciousness”
(Barad 2007, 391).
Ziarek (2001b) says
that ethical responsibility for Levinas is
located not in consciousness but specifically in
“incarnation”... Levinas suggests instead that
there is a responsibility “prior to the will and
intentionality of consciousness” before any
notion of the subject or the ego....
Consciousness for and of itself is not the
defining feature of the human subject: something
else persists— “the
embodied ego, or what Levinas
calls ipseity”
|
|