Notes on : Denzin, N. (1997).
Commentary and Debate: Whose Sociology Is It?
Comment on Huber. American Journal of
Sociology, 102 (5): 1416 – 23. DOI:
10.1086/231088.
https://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1086/231088
Dave Harris
Huber had apparently
identified problems with sociology as a
discipline, in an article in AJS 101, and
isolated 'certain self-destructive
characteristics' including 'some "affinity for
anti-rationalist ideas"' (1416). They should not
be tolerated any more and we should develop a
central core of knowledge and solid facts about
society that will make us useful, to show that
sociology is useful. [Note 3 says that Huber
wrongly identifies irrationalist ideas as
post-modern ones, but this conflates the meaning
of post-modernism, and ignores earlier
constructionist and interpretive approaches].
She particularly says that people like
constructionists offer '"aggressive efforts to
undermine everyone else"' (1417), and alleges that
these people have no '"standards of rationality
objectivity or truth"'. This is caricature. No one
is named inthis position because 'no one holds
it'. A comparison is then made with another
sociological group who support the idea of
sociology as science and think there is a
disciplinary core — 'demography, social
organisation, and stratification'. They produce
replicable data and supply knowledge needed to run
welfare states, especially if they include
statistics. Critics should not be tolerated if
they challenge the idea of disinterested
observers.
Methodological controversies about positivism were
ignored in 1980s mainstream American sociology,
and were found best developed in anthropology and
economics. There were challenges to the notion of
objective social science and traditional forms of
authority including reliability and validity.
There was much criticism of ontological and
epistemological and methodological
presuppositions. Guba and Lincoln (1994) can be
cited as developing 'a more relative,
constructionist position' (1418). However there
were still complex criteria for evaluating
interpretive work, including 'credibility,
plausibility, context embeddedness, dependability,
confirm ability, authenticity, dialogue, narrative
truth, emotional verisimilitude and so on' (1419)
— but all this is rejected as relativistic [and so
internally contradictory as tobe meaningless].
Huber does not even address methodological biases
in positivism, especially 'who is to police those
who claim they have the correct view of knowledge,
truth, or science, and knowledge for whom?' [Old
very general challenge that crops up even in the
later work — exaggerated term like policing, and
an assumption that there can be no one who has
anything other than their own interests at heart.
Equally applicable to his judgements,of course].
Huber does not suggest how we determine objective
truth. Her methods 'carries political and social
biases, and she has no strategy, other than
rhetoric, for guarding against them'.
Democracy is not the same as value freedom. Her
model is ecological, with 'Darwinian overtones',
where administrators have the right to choose the
strongest options. Those who advocate intellectual
relativism 'and the inclusion of students on
administrative committees' have only brought
unclear standards and inappropriate participation.
They have given sociology a partisan image.
They are actually asking for a pluralistic field
beyond the core subjects. They suggest that
science is a social institution with values and
these are often exclusionary and distorting. They
suggest that science must reflect 'multiple,
interpretive perspectives, even, perhaps, a
successor feminist science [referring to Harding]
or a science that embodies the interpretive and
epistemological standpoints of different racial
and ethnic groups'. These would be democratic
communities. They are calling for more ASA
sections to reflect standpoint interests and
suggest that graduate students should contribute
to departmental politics. These are partisan
values and they may have made the field vulnerable
to attack by administrators. 'But when have we
ever been value free?' (1420). How can we
encourage new people? [edbiz?] Is Huber proposing
some test for admission? [Heaven forbid!] She
wants to go back to some orthodoxy with one view
of sociology and its interests. 'This is
nostalgia, for when did this state ever exist?'.
She still needs to show how she would address core
problems of the kind she identifies, how to
develop consistent standards of teaching and
research, norms of civility, rigour. Not everyone
agrees these are problems in the discipline —
Stinchcombe advocates a disintegrated discipline
in order to advance knowledge and expand students
minds. Pluralism is nothing new, and has
characterised fruitful moments in the 50s and 60s.
Even within Huber's core, there has been
pluralism, for example trying to connect Weber's
methodology with Marx's reflexivity [an example
she mentions]. It is the narrowness and
traditionalism that is new.
This orthodoxy 'got us into this mess in the first
place' (1421), when good old 'mainstream empirical
middle range sociology held sway '. The discipline
fragmented into subspecialisms, and it's that that
drew negative attention. It is 'scapegoating' that
leads to blaming constructionists. Even her own
examples of trivial research are mainstream. In
her orthodox period, departments and disciplines
were oriented to either specific missions or
something more generalist, which somehow involved
'the needs of society'. Over time, the orientation
shifted towards domains, [professionalisation and
scholasticisation of the discipline in my view]
and this is also partly because societies are more
complex, so that the single discipline approach
was no longer adequate. Diverse interests and
interdisciplinary programs arose as a result.
This development in turn provides diverse
materials and requires no longer a single
discipline or a single paradigms. Instead we need
'social problems–based, interdisciplinary
research' and this has been accepted in mainstream
sociology as better describing the field [quoting
Stinchcombe again]. Dichotomous and stereotypical
thinking will not solve sociology's problems. The
demands of radical democracy are long established
and cannot 'be quieted. There is too much at
stake' (1422).
We should focus again on the sociological
imagination in order to preserve the entire
discipline rather than getting bogged down into
disputes. Consider shutting down conversations we
should develop 'a common ground for reasoned,
civil discourse'
Huber, J. & Mirowsky, J.
Of Facts and Fables: Reply to Denzin [as above]:
1424 -- 8
Denzin apparently thinks that 'fables are superior
to facts because appropriate interpretation
enables one to make anything of the facts that one
chooses'. This is what drives anti-rational
thought and threatens lots of sciences. The ASA's
task group originally raised it as a problem [and
apparently their report led to her article].
There are fallacies in his argument. His
'narrative strategy (1423) has implications. His
own dictum is 'if you want to change how things
are, change how they are seen' [citing Denzin 1992
— the article on Cornerville]. He has mastered
'post-modern methods', via 'specious innuendo…
Derogatory implications… Patently false' (1424).
He suggests that quantitative mainstream methods
'are an exercise in immoral repression of free
thought'. People who reject measurement or
reproducible methods are 'moral heroes' while
those who practice it are 'repressive villains'.
This ignores the 'deep moral commitment' of
sociologists who do science, such as demographers
worried about population growth, stratification
researchers who 'feel anguish at the thought of
racism, sexism and poverty'. These people have
spent decades acquiring the relevant skills and
knowledge, and are often driven by moral concern.
The difference is that their method is based on
'the assumption that their personal beliefs may be
false and must be tested'. It is a strange
morality to demand the right that ideas are
accepted as valid 'regardless of how vague,
contradictory, or unsupportable they may be'. The
only people who benefit are 'ideologues, spin
doctors, charlatans, and the cognitively diffuse…
who fail when their ideas are put to the test'.
Denzin sees quantitative mainstream methods as
'thoughtless traditions'. In fact they have been
produced by at least a century of thought and
experimentation. The whole point was to aggregate
insights and discoveries. Quantitative research
was a solution to the weakness of earlier forms
that could not be reproduced or compared, and this
led to representative sampling. Those who really
dodged methodological criticism are those who
claim their cases are special and their insights
unique. 'It is arrogance to see one's own
impromptu methods as more thoughtful than standard
methods' (1425).
Positivist do not ignore methodological criticism.
Anti-positivists need to hear more. Denzin's
complex criteria for evaluation only 'treat an
artful fiction as if it were true. They define an
effective gloss'.
Objective and value free social science is not
'undemocratic or antidemocratic'. Denzin seems to
think that everyone has a right to think and do
anything they choose, including graduate students
who can 'come to any conclusion that suits them
without fear of being treated as lost or
incorrect'. Objective social science has a role in
a democratic society and is 'essential to
effective democracy' because it stops people
asserting anything at all about what the public
does, believes or wants, 'and fear no test of
truth'.
Where is the public to get information to make
informed decisions, cutting out 'interpretive
handlers'? People need information that they
cannot produce themselves and our job is to
provide it. Therefore we must 'strive for
relevance, clarity, honesty, and balance. It is
not our job to displace their preferences or
attitudes with our own'. In particular if ideas
find 'little or no confirmation in empirical fact,
we are obliged to say so'. We have to be polite
but we must be candid. We will not be trusted by
the public if our information is not worthy, and
if we are 'nothing more than manipulative
partisans of various causes'. [Dead relevant to
the UK crisis post-Brexit where unis were almost
entirely pro-Remain]
Denzin thinks that standard research undermines
the interests of minorities, women and the poor,
and that quantitative skill oppresses those who
identify with the abused and downtrodden. 'This is
the sorriest falsehood of all'. Interpretive
communities may speak of racism sexism or
inequality, but lack 'the effectiveness and power
of facts'. There is also the danger of 'elective
incapacity' on the part of those students who
struggled against a disadvantaged background. So
'nothing is more unscrupulous than a professor who
works students' insecurities, beguiling them into
the trap', as do Denzin and others like him
who fight against any attack on the falseness of
their product. Instead they are advocating
developing 'a flood of quantitatively disabled
sociologists primed with resentment and hostility'
(1426) [cracking stuff!].
The fundamental issue is what part does the
external world plane confirming findings? Can we
develop reliable knowledge by following the
methods of science, even if it is 'imperfect and
tentative'?. Or is science impossible because our
accounts are only 'social and linguistic
constructs'? Is debate fruitless, especially over
the facts? Is any version of the event as valid as
any other? — If so, obviously any attempt to
confirmation replication is pointless. These
questions point to the real division rather than
distinguishing positivists and non-positivists
[and these words were already abandoned in the
original essay, to reflect 'a more sophisticated
version of realism'].
We have two sociologies of science we might draw
on — Merton who sees external reality as the most
important in determining the content science,
while newer ones see content as more negotiated,
influenced by power, ideology and other social
factors. Of course social factors are important,
as even Merton demonstrated, although external
reality was ultimately responsible. Some British
sociologists, like Latour and Woolgar decided that
negotiation was the crucial factor. This is
'consonant with post-modernist thought', but it
tends to be more popular in the humanities, while
people in physics or biology see the notion as
'incomprehensible, alien to their experience'.
Seeing negotiation as essential fails to explain
the obvious success of science and science-based
technology.
Are we saying that gravity is 'only a social
construction', or that a physicist's discussion of
gravity is 'just a text'? (1427). Are
observational accounts in sociology just the
'observer's construction of reality'? Can social
scientist produce 'reliable (if tentative)
knowledge by using certain procedures'? Some
sociologists feel there are no standards here.
Denzin argues that no one actually holds such a
position — but this 'answer is disingenuous'.
We see this if we look at the controversy about Street
Corner Society in the special issue of Journal
of Contemporary Ethnography. [see for
example this]
An article had called into question the data, and
the author had gone back and got some more data.
Whyte was allowed to write a rejoinder, but other
critics had to be recruited as well, and one of
them was Denzin.
Whyte's response pointed to factual errors,
quotations out of context and 'other
misrepresentations' in the accusation that he had
falsified the data. Denzin never bothered to
address those, because, as the editors explained,
he 'found the broad question of validity neither
important nor answerable' thanks to his allegiance
to 'existential sociology and the post-modern
creed of multiple realities' [I must agree —
Denzin's response is a terrible weasel, possibly
intended to placate the warring participants] [A
note mentions the Sokal hoax] [In another note,
the author says that 'in our view all charges
against Whyte's scholarship lacked merit']
Denzin began by criticising Whyte for assuming
that the social world exists and that events can
be accurately recorded, then he raises '"
troubling alternatives"' (1428), which include the
possibility that 'the ethnographer's text creates
the subject', that subjects appear only in written
texts. Since any 'inscription on the memory disc
is but another version of the event… one multiple
inscription has as much validity as another' so
debates about who got the facts right are
fruitless. He ended by asking if we want this kind
social science any more anyway.
Whyte responded by saying that if his own social
realist approach is only one of several possible
strategies for telling stories, then everything
will depend only on the author's persuasive power,
and 'scientific arguments are thus transformed
into literary criticism'. This would stop
behavioural sciences altogether, because 'credible
interpretation depends on getting the facts
straight'. Indeed, if social research is only one
of several narratives, there is no point in
attempting to gather valid data [which is what
Denzin really is arguing, I think -- politics is
all]
back to Denzin page
|
|