Very brief early notes after a very quick read
through of Klossowski, P. (1997) Nietzsche and
the Vicious Circle. Trans Daniel W Smith.
London : Athlone Press.
Dave Harris
[I found this exteremely difficult, partly because
I find it almost impossible to take Nietzsche
seriously, and I regard his elevation by
French writers as a kind of joke. That may be
because of the peculiarities of the English
reception of Nietzsche as Deleuze argues in his Two Regimes --
we didn't have to struggle with structuralism.
There is an obvious ontological similarity between
Nietzsche and other French types, including
Deleuze -- intensive forces go all the way down
{for Lyotard too, so his Encyclopaedia
entry suggests}. This book is very detailed and
technical and to take proper notes would require
months of work. As I am mostly interested in
Deleuze's take on NIetzsche which he says relies
on Klossowski, I have managed only a few brief
comments. I have rearranged the topics a bit.]
The book
draws on lots of letters and notes left
unpublished by Nietzsche, which partly explains
my puzzlement about Deleuze's emphasis on things
like the Eternal Return when there is hardly any
mention of it directly in the published pieces.
Nietzsche seems to have thought that the
alternations between euphoria and depression
were the results of certain intensities or
intensive forces, existing in nature and
fluctuating in his body. He came to develop a
whole semiology on this basis, seeing the codes
and signs of ordinary culture and its products
including philosophical thoughts, as
particularly limited and frozen snapshots of
these fluctuating intensities. The same goes for
wills. This is why we could not accept the usual
categories as self-sufficient — self, other,
consciousness, the unconscious and nature for
that matter. We use these only because science
is useful if critiquing ordinary thought.
N's aphorism are supposed to indicate the
inadequacies of ordinary formulations. Thoughts
are not our own -- but we have a powerful sign
that makes it look as if they are -- the 'I' {
functionalism again?}. We had to have these
highly restricted codes for good functional
reasons, in order to permit orderly social life,
but the function of the philosopher and thinker
was to attempt to contact these intensities all
over again. This will obviously be paradoxical
since there was no way out from culture back
into pure intensity. Nevertheless intensities
provided unique tonalities of the soul which
generated spectacular insights, and made
Nietzsche think that he really was a
revolutionary thinker ahead of his time and so
on. What a prat!
As a result of one of these particular ecstatic
tonalities, he came to think of the Eternal
Return. I must say I think the whole discussion
is haunted by guilt and regret on the one hand,
and a view that he would live things quite
differently if he had known about the eternal
return in the first place. What a prat again! He
was apparently haunted by the mood swings
and,multiple selves [and NB events must also
contain traces of earlier existences] revealed
to him by the fluctuations in his health, and
turned with great relief to the idea that all
these multiple selves were earlier incarnations
of himself in cycles of the Return. His grasp of
that was a major self-justifying enlightenment
for him and a promise that things would be
better next turn of the cycle. Of course, it
required some philosophical justification...
He tried to reason that the Return must exceed
any individual imagination because it implied so
many individual selves. He argued it must be
right because it came from one of the most
intense tonalities of his soul. He thought it
might be provable using modern science ( and
resolved to train himself as a scientist at one
stage). He worried throughout that it might all
just be the result of nervous exhaustion. His
frequent sufferings seemed to contradict the
whole idea of a higher purpose. Maybe it was
ultimately better to live without any
guarnatees.Somehow he was a hero who willed this
contradictory and unjustifiabe event. He tried
to express it all through the character
Zarathustra and his stupid assertions and
imagery, but finally came to reject Z's visions
as bombast and buffoonery [as a failed attempt
to mimic the high tonality of the visionary
etc].
Is the Return the same as the will to power and
if not, what is the relation [typical
philosophical question!]. In subsequent
discussions eg of mechanism, he saw the will to
power as a will to violence or against violence
rather than as self-preservation,that will
radiates out in its effects,that this is grasped
as the normal sorts of affect like happiness
etc, that it is a dynamic active force ( no
conservation of energy) a teleological
'primordial impulse'. The Return is the process
underneath these impulses and their variation,
beyond ordinary wills and desires ( and causes
and effects). We then get to the notorious
'sociology' -- that regulation and organisation
express weak impulse re the Return etc, that
this should replace our interests in specific
social ends or means etc -- hence his critiques
of convention, of religion etc. It is all
analagous to the psychology of impulses etc says
K (110) -- all the stuff about the intensity of
the soul is compatible with his general
ramblings about energy as never conserved [and
dubious stuff about healthy societies as those
in constant struggle etc] -- the same power is
found in individuals and societies [and nature].
It can all look like it leads to chaos and to
the decline of spirituality,but we find in it a
pure energy. Only a gifted [or 'fortuitous' as
he described himself] individual can finds this
truth within themselves, of course, as a massive
euphoria. The actual courses of events, the
domination of particular classes etc, are
only phases in the Return of course It follows
that each social formation must relativise
itself, foresee its own transcendence: humans
are gregarious but not committed to particular
forms of sociability (plebs make this mistake of
course].
The whole notion of the Eternal Return seems to
be riddled with paradox and ambiguity, as one
might expect. For example it requires us to have
forgotten earlier cycles, otherwise we would
have learned from them and discovered the Return
in the first place. Once we have discovered the
Return, we are enlightened, but this still does
not stop the cycle of the eternal return. There
is some wacky stuff about the importance of the
notion of a circular return to encapsulate the
process of solidifying the notion of the I , and
then losing it again, dissolving it in the flux
of intensity.The normal exercise of the will
operates only at the solidified moment, but it
is possible to will another turn around the
circle. This is also a way of overcoming by
compensation the apparent incoherence and
stupidity of normal life — nothing has much
coherence or significance in the ordinary state
of affairs, where it is all arbitrary.As usual,
we seem to compensate for our own twisted
ordinary lives by developing what seems like a
great ecstatic philosophical insight.It is
almost a way of overcoming the dreadful thought
of chaos at the bottom of it all — this is a
domesticated version of chaos.
Naturally, this is communicated in unusual ways,
through fables like Zarathustra, who has to
struggle to overcome the boring bits of human
destiny, like the exteriority of time. If he can
somehow will time to become a circle, this will
solve the problem. This will only be a ruse
however {a subjective story of the reality}. The
whole thing is to be contrasted to the actions
of the ordinary will that operates in ordinary
time and can only therefore think of and will a
return of the same. This is where we get a
connection to the early stuff on semiology and
intensities, since what we are rewilling is a
properly heterogeneous self, a multiplicity of
different intensities, not one frozen in a
particular moment.We can properly understand
that our passage through the cycles in the past
has produced certain limited selves, but they
are all part of us, and once we know that, the
future can work with heterogeneous selves {guilt
and apology riddle this}. We have to remember
that none of this is confined to human
intentions — the cycle works independently of us
{so it is not our fault that we happen to be
living in a rather nasty moment at the same time
as syphilis}. This revelation which occurred to
Nietzsche by chance opens the possibility for
the appearance of the overman, who wants to live
according to the progress of the virtuous
circle, naturally beyond the banalities of good
and evil.
So what political implications follow? How does
the Return affect human action? Maybe we were
ignorant of it before but should now change.
Maybe it has been revealed but only to a few
secret masters. How should N react specifically,
-- pursuing ordinary goals he knows to be
pointless [nihilism]? How could we create
conditions that would permit properly creative
individuals to (re) emerge? The latter question
at least was seen as a matter of healthy
physiology to create heroes in struggle with
their own personal and social health [like him].
Philosophers must make social life insecure
again, do violence to it, even if that involves
a necessary imposture -- the 'positive notion of
the false' (132). Buddhism could be admired for
creating these positive phanstasms (once we have
guarded against its passivity) [it's the old
notion of building a theoretical ladder to
escape commonsense then discarding it?]
We have to generalize the notion of falsity and
mystification to extend to the whole of
existence, and give the forces that produce it a
major creative role. The seems to be a way of
upping the stakes for scientific demystification
— a re-mystification. All this is to be
understood in terms of the general notion that
apparent stability and concreteness is a
representation of challenging impulsive forces,
'existence is sustained only through
fabulation'. 'Nothing exists apart from impulses
that are essentially generative of phantasms'
(133). A simulacrum is not just the product of a
phantasm but rather the reproduction of it in
human terms: this reproduction is not entirely
free, however because it must remain tied to the
necessity of the phantasm, so that proper
analysis will lead us to the phantasm and to
impulsive forces. Art is the only practice that
reproduces suitable simulacra. We only get there
after 'a ludic suspension of the reality
principle' (134).
Science by contrast relies on institutions and
therefore on the gregarious relations, and is
ultimately a product of 'the herd's "will to
power"' (135). This goes for all conventional
intellectual endeavour so that all knowledge is
a will to power and must reinvent the real as
particular simulacra. The gregarious impulse
will impose a limit to knowledge. Science
ultimately is tied to human purpose and this
makes it socially conservative, intolerant of
great individuals and groups. There is a
constant drive to maintain unanimity, and this
replaces earlier simple beliefs in reality.
Science is also affected by instrumental goals
to improve living conditions for the mass. We
have reduced the apparently highest form of
knowledge to a crude form of interest in
persistence which works against
individualization, except forms of the
individual which are compatible. Proper
individuals will soon discover that there is no
is stable core to their tastes or identity, and
this helps produce an incisive critique of
science.
Science invents simulacra that conform to its
own phantasms, aiming not so much at
comprehension as at producing mimetic behaviour.
It still partakes of a basic 'anthropomorphic
superstition' that nature displays intentions
and reasons. In fact these are supplied the
level at which simulacra are constructed (138)
[and there is a hint that a successful
technology verifies scientific reason as much as
delivering useful goods]. However science also
encounters a contradiction because it cannot
tolerate the notion of a fixity of the species.
This is sometimes understood as a form of chaos
which has to be dealt with by 'self fabulation'.
However, properly understood chaos has no
intention, although somehow intentional beings
are constructed. This arises from 'pure chance —
in which the intensity of forces is inverted
into intention: the work of morality' (140).
Science does not recognise this process and lead
us back to chaos, but compensates for it in
efficacious activity [Nietzscbe offers a
grandiose account of how human cultures have
developed like this, all of which have prevented
the emergence of a properly adequate morality].
The way forward for Nietzsche is to go beyond
experimental science and question all
institutions, opposing 'the worst kind of
gregarious cretinism' (141). Even Klossowski
sees this as a pretext to nourish Nietzsche's
'Malthusian rage' against gregariousness (142).
He began by inverting everything previously good
into everything evil; the connection between
weakness and a tendency to posit everything as
evil. He condemned the domestication of the
passions, argued for great men following their
own desires, saw education as 'essentially the
means of ruining the exceptions for the good of
the rule', and higher education as 'essentially
the means of directing taste against the
exceptions for the good of the mediocre' (143 –
4).
[Now we come on to a bit that excited
accelerationists] if a culture has an excess of
powers, it can begin to cultivate the exception
and the experiment [Nietzsche immediately
announces that this is what has happened in
every aristocratic culture]. Civilisation is not
the same as culture and may even oppose it. We
need to go beyond the normal reality principles
of science and morality and recognise that we
must acknowledge 'the force that compels the
appreciation of a given state' regardless of
whether it helps gregariousness. We have seen
that scientific practice simply manipulates and
naïve reality principle and is easily bent to
the purposes of the herd — recover its autonomy
is how N puts it, and again this will involve
cherishing idiosyncratic individual scientists
[and artists]. A similarly autonomous art would
inaugurate a new 'counter sociology', dominating
social life instead of the institutions. Even
Klossowski can see that this might be simply an
imaginary 'conspiracy a philosopher – despots
and artist – tyrants, of which he is, strictly
speaking, the sole representative' (146).
There is even a possibility for the formation of
'international genetic associations whose task
will be to rear a race of Masters... A new,
tremendous aristocracy... In which the despotic
will of philosophers and artist – tyrants will
be made to endure for millennia'. This might be
a fit of rage or a joke, K thinks. It will all
depend on certain 'physiological and psychic
conditions' which will permit rare individuals
to emerge. N apparently argue that this would be
a phantasm in his sense, that is something
presupposed by humanity even though it does not
yet exist, and which represents the real goals
of human existence: in this sense, the proposal
is a kind of love.
This is 'the postulate of the "overman", which
is not an individual but a state'. The
production of this state provides both meaning
and a goal for humanity, and this clearly
contradicts a crucial point of his thought which
concerns the production of random events,
implicit in the notion of the Eternal Return,
irrespective of the will of human beings. It is
a way of reintroducing some version of the
reality principle, and some notion of human will
to the Return.
[K manages to get a useful critique of
industrial society out of all this]. He
discusses the notion of Masters of the earth and
their corresponding slaves, and this somehow
leads to a critique of industrial society as
functionality dominating everything else. It is
the dependence on the economy that provides the
real limits to knowledge. This cannot be the
result of some genuinely creative impulse
because it is 'highly gregarious' (149) [the
whole thing looks circular to me — genuinely
creative impulses cannot be social, so since the
industrial society is heavily socialised, it
cannot be based on a genuinely creative
impulse]. N is not advocating a return to some
past aristocracy. Nor does he have any faith in
socialist systems which will also be hostile to
the strongest impulses — although we can see
that this might help 'accelerate the massive
saturation of mediocre needs' which will
inevitably bring about some an assimilated
group. Whatever the wacky political oscillation
involved, N has got it right to criticise 'the
mercantilization of value judgements'(150), and
ultimately the way in which the reality
principle of science conforms to 'the reality
principle of gregarious morality'.
K thinks that this conformity is no longer
stable, that there is now a continual
experimentation which challenges
institutionalize norms, so there are variable
notions of social health and sickness, although
proper transgression is still rendered
unintelligible.
Overall, though Nietzsche has no strategy or
account of social processes. He seems to dabble
with the idea of emergent castes. Nevertheless
he does think that the perfection of the
mechanism will end with some kind of resistance
to it, following 'the progressive
de-assimilation of "surplus forces"' (152).
There will be some sort of catastrophe to
accompany this resistance, including the
disclosure of the doctrine of the eternal
return. Advocates of the return might be agents.
The whole thing is 'obscure and particularly
incoherent'. Again contradictions emerge between
the necessarily gregarious context for social
change, and the hope that the rugged individual
will be able to somehow connect with this
context. The alternative will be the end of the
human species, however.
Here, the Eternal Return is suggested as an
alternative to mundane forms of social
reproduction. There will arise a singular case
to oppose de- valorisation of power at the
species level. The singular case illustrates
'the image of chance' (154) — it opposes
gregariousness but also possesses underlying
power [based on these allegedly impulsive forces
I assume].
We can proceed by stressing individuals and
destroying their gregarious links, as well as
wiping out the past history of the species as
somehow tutelary. Instead we 'will to re-will
life'(155), involving experiment even if this
looks like violence to gregariousness. In
practice, various initiates of the doctrine of
the Return will be able to emerge and create the
new type of overman. And this will be easier
once we have all realized the crisis produced by
universal levelling.
[Back to K apologetics for all this] Nietzsche
got it right that industrial growth will
suppress and control 'appetitive spontaneity of
individuals on a vast scale' (157). A new
aristocracy will emerge from the surpluses
produced by this activity, although it will not
be popular with the masses and will be seen as
parasitical. This group must find its very
strength in the hostility and indignation of the
masses. Members of the mercantile class will not
do this, and it is not just a matter of the
higher castes somehow leading the lower [with
Comte specifically mentioned] — they have their
own tasks.
All will be revealed eventually when the Circle
becomes apparent [still called the Vicious
Circle at this point]. The experimenters will
make it impossible to resist and revolt, in a
kind of 'planetary planning or management'
(160). Until then they must remain as a secret
order until the surplus men have been
constructed and the overman [defined here by
Nietzsche himself as a concept or parable for a
type] [a great deal of ranting about industrial
society then ensues 161ff] For Nietzsche, the
progressive dwarfing of man is what will bring
about the obvious need for a 'stronger race'. To
bring this about, we might even accelerate these
tendencies until it is obvious that a homogenous
species requires some higher sovereign species
to reintroduce 'beauty, bravery, culture,
manners'(163).
But how can all this be seen as necessary? We
might be able to knowingly will such events.
Society might itself already be in the grip of a
powerful transformation with serious
dysfunctions, but how all this is going to end
in some superhuman types is unclear. Much faith
is placed in policies 'to accelerate rather than
fight the ever expanding process...
Equalisation' (165). Homogenisation will lead to
'moral and affective numbing'. The impulse to
transcend these developments comes from the
Eternal Return itself — it is but one stage in
the Circle and the movement will go on to
produce a final intensity, a 'luminous
achievement' (166).
But how can we see this as somehow produced by
economic progress? The current economic system
has indeed produced aristocratic groups, but the
question is whether N's particular set of human
tastes tastes is already implicit, and whether
aristocracy is not already condemned as
parasitic. We already know the discomfort felt
by those who do not directly live in the realm
of exchange, who do not contribute to general
productivity — 'bad conscience'(167). Positive
efforts have to be made to overcome this. The
whole project is 'still too marked by the
political aestheticism of his time', although he
is on stronger ground by noting the
unforeseeable nature of the future, and how 'the
industrial spirit' is already under challenge.
[I think K uses a bit of dialectic to
rescue N here] there.
N is a philosophical nihilist in the sense that
he thinks that 'all that happens is meaningless
and in vain; and that there ought not to be
anything meaningless and in vain' (168). [Then a
very strange self-serving argument] This noble
sentiment rescues the philosopher from
dissatisfaction and desperation at the sight of
such a bleak existence, and this goes against
their 'finer sensibility as philosophers'. K, or
maybe it is N draws the obvious conclusion that
this is an 'absurd valuation... The character of
the existence would have to give the philosopher
pleasure'. Luckily, nihilism does not have to be
logical but is more a matter of 'strong spirits
and wills'.
Again this seems to give thought alone some
tremendous power to change society, based, no
doubt, on a conviction that it has previously
understood history as something premeditated.
Darwin's evolution 'conspires with
gregariousness' by valuing mediocre beings, but
we want to focus on 'strong, rich and powerful
beings'. Darwin represents the typical
coincidence of science with bourgeois morality.
It has to be countered by a deliberate
conspiracy based on the vicious circle, and that
in turn is validated by 'the lived experience of
the singular and privileged case'. This somehow
shows that experience itself possesses an
'unintelligible depth' that can never be
restrained by gregariousness.
Now we have a conspiracy based on the
experimental nature of the vicious circle.
Current existences seen as meaningless which
somehow seems to validate some philosophical
intervention, but unfortunately, the project
means that the return becomes a simulacrum,
something more specific and actual, designed to
meet a goal of producing the overman.
Metaphysical justification might be gained by
identifying the overman as necessarily connected
with underlying phantasms of impulsive forces.
Somehow the meaningless depth of existence has
to be reasserted against all notions of
reasonable progress, and this is in effect a
strange expenditure of affectivity beyond what
is useful.
Making it all positive depends entirely on
various experiments that will validate singular
cases. We can no longer just referred to notions
of what is true and false — the reality
principle disappears [very handy!]. This leaves
only an arbitrary reality constituted allegedly
by simulacra depending on underlying phantasms
and impulses. Apart from anything else, meaning
can always be revoked.
Nietzsche clearly thought that his revelation
about the vicious circle was sufficient to
'break the history of humanity in two'(170). The
vicious circle will lead to the superhuman,
although 'Nietzsche should have said: the
inhuman'(171). It is true that advanced
industrialization can be understood as 'a
concrete form of the most malicious
caricaturization of his doctrine', but as the
'exact inverse of his postulate'. We have
neither the mediocre nor the superhuman, but
rather 'a new and totally amoral form of
gregariousness'.
Some marvellous bullshit on page 172 attempts to
defend Nietzsche by saying that he deliberately
wrote in riddles: 'the will to interpret
deliberately encloses itself and simulates a
necessity in order to flee the vacuity of its
arbitrariness'. I suppose it is clear that if
you see culture and language as unfortunately
frozen and gregarious versions of attempts to
make meaning you will have a real problem in
deciding how writing and interpretation can
actually work. According to Klossowski,
Nietzsche 'explicated himself by implicating
himself in a preconceived interpretation of the
"text"' (173) — in other words he posed as a
deliberately naive or possibly even a mad
philosopher?
Much then ensues on Nietzsche's dreams, and his
increasing bipolarism, including a reworking of
the Oedipal schema. Nietzsche clearly believe
that during the worst times, he 'reached the
lowest level of his existence and received as
compensation an exuberance of the spirit' (174).
In another inversion, he explored his own
decadent instincts and was then led 'to reverse
perspectives and thus to [discover] the
Revaluation of Values'. Klossowski says that we
should not overdo this psychoanalytic reading,
although it is deeply tempting — she felt
terrible guilt towards his father, and saw his
mother in standard terms as 'the sign of his
sickness, and not of the healthy life'. Other
strange effects are listed: 'Mourning was turned
into a voluptuous delight in sound, while
libidinal images, which were beginning to haunt
the adolescent, would eventually be expressed in
the elaboration of a necrophiliac cynicism'
(178) [more unpublished autobiographical
material is cited, including his adoption of an
imaginary persona so that he could give 'vent to
his hatred for the human species' as well as
demonstrating his skill.
Later on, the cycle of vitality and lethargy
produces 'two fundamental utterances' (184).
First, 'the relationship between Chaos and
becoming, which implied a read becoming', second
the death of God, which was a rejection not just
of the divine but 'of an identical and once and
for all individuality'. Other strange forms of
reasoning are apparent — Nietzsche discovers
that whatever he has previously been told about
his inner life is a lie so therefore there must
be some outside of myself which will be where
his authentic persona lives. This will be
located in the past, or wherever he might find
an absence of himself in contemporary society.
He prefers to think that 'my constitutive
elements are dispersed in past time and in the
future' (185). All this is combined with an
obsessive observation of his own health and the
need to explain away some pathologies — the
migraines and threat of madness were attributed
to possible heredity.
[More Freudian analysis of family dynamics
ensues, 186ff. His relationship with Lou Salome
complicated things in that he became proud of
his own variability, but also had to condemn it
as an example of a normalised Eros. He was also
becoming much more secluded and could see the
risk in that it might lead to an ultimate
decline. At that point, something fortuitous
arrived, something that led to the insight that
we wore social masks, to present 'a false unity
in relation to others' in order to simulate our
own internal secret life. However, the reliance
on chance also brought a nasty implication, that
this secret life itself could 'only be dreadful
chance, fragment, riddle' (192). He could only
rely on a more positive result of chance, helped
by a reconciliation with discontinuity — 'chance
ceased to be dreadful and became a joyful
fortuity' (193). Overall, 'Nietzsche loved
himself only for his aim; he hated himself as a
victim of the traps of life' (195). All this
arose from seeing the relationship with Lou as
somehow expressing his inner essence.
Overall, the failure with Lou led to a negative
implication of his overall thought about
phantasms — 'The phantasm was produced only as
the result of a failure. A positive experience
ran counter to the phantasm the condition this
organisation' (196). Madmen might well choose
their alienated states and express themselves
through stereotypes of madness, but this changes
the relations between phantasms and concrete
actualizations — experience becomes a matter of
exchange between vision of life and art, not
life and thought.
Nietzsche was unable to think of himself as
willing his own thought [maybe], and
psychological dissolution was the result. The
failure with Lou also blocked his virility and
this 'constituted a profound wound, a hiatus in
which Nietzsche's ego was deactualized and
broken'. The moment was so profound that the
whole of his past was interpreted in its terms.
Again Klossowski warns us about adopting too
'coarse and easy' analysis, however [mostly
because the key figures in the drama are not
just a conventional Oedipal ones, but include,
for example, the Minotaur and Ariadne].
Nietzsche struggled, to no one's surprise, to
find a language which might express his
symptoms, and suspected that the symptoms of
strength or health looks the same as those of
weakness and sickness. This became part of a
more general contradiction, making it difficult
for Nietzsche to allocate particular meanings to
terms that would be massively misunderstood,
including 'will to power'. Although this was
addressed to singular cases, it seemed
necessarily addressed to social intelligence.
The Eternal Return also referred to a single
case [I think this was himself!] and then became
a thought. In an attempt to avoid domesticating
philosophical convention, Nietzsche thought it
would be addressed to 'sensibility, email to the
tea and affectivity, thus to the impulsive side
of each and every person' (200). The same
problems arise using terms such as health or
sickness — these were 'caught up in the
designations of institutional language and...
Became subject to the reality principle'. Was
there any mileage in considering the insane or
the monstrous as exceptional cases? Apart from
the banality about madness being close to
genius, there would be much to explain.
Klossowski admits that 'We have absolutely no
criteria for determining when the sick, the
insane, and the monstrous would be cases of
[political] sterility, as opposed to exceptional
cases, nor when the latter would be considered
fecund'. Nor will it be enough to identify some
sort of cultural surplus or excess, since this
overabundance would be by definition 'something
unexchangeable' (201).
Nietzsche opted in the end to exalt life 'even
in its blindest forms'. Naturally, this had
personal implications — he could talk about
'"the most beautiful invention of the sick"—
that is, to a sovereign malice, and thus to his
own aggressiveness' [with all that ranting about
how the weak are even more malicious, and
including a rant about women: 'one half of
mankind is weak, typically sick, changeable, in
constant — woman need strength in order to
cleave to it; she needs a religion of weakness
that glorifies being weak, loving, and being
humble as divine. Or better, she makes the
strong weak... Woman has always conspired with
the types of decadence, the priests, against the
powerful, the strong, the men' (202), and a
condemnation of civilisation which only promotes
criminals and neurotics, 'the refuse, the
waste'. There is the attack on equal rights,
'the superstition of "equal men"', who bear
ressentiment, slave instincts, and miscegenation
— 'two, three generations later the race is no
longer recognisable — everything has become a
mob' (203).
Klossowski insists this is not all bad, that the
sick, for example, are at least credited with
having a compassion [apparently, Nietzsche was
influenced here by Dostoevsky]. However, there
seems to be an increasing role for 'aggressive
and asocial forces' in the creation of
simulacra, rather than sublimation. Klossowski
comments that 'Certainty takes on the offensive
characteristic of delirium' (204), exacerbated
by the 'certainty of the irreducible depth' of
reality. Nietzsche might have concealed these
'monstrous dispositions', citing a view that it
was Bacon who pretended Shakespeare had written
about them, but Nietzsche was certain that
making a simulacrum required great strength, and
hence that suffering was necessary for the
artist or philosopher. The most general
implication is that 'knowledge is an
unacknowledged power of monstrosity' (205),
which might mean that it is terribly tempting
not to be courageous enough to argue for
strength and aggression. Any philosopher who is
so tempted will settle for 'histrionics'
[pretending to be a philosopher].
Nietzsche remained uneasy about all of this. He
deliberately produced caricatures of his thought
so as to compensate for 'the silence or
incomprehension of his Germanic public' (206).
This involves a claim to great visionary power,
far from the idea that his was a fortuitous
case, discovering the Return through luck. Now
he somehow came to stand for an historical
moment. He came to generalise [as usual] by
arguing that all mechanisms of thought involve
deception, both behaviour and speech — reality
is rejected, but what deception stands for is
never made clear.
Overall, Nietzsche will always 'be able to find
himself' in any particular occasion scandal or
incident, and he interested himself in society
gossip. He just expected that anyone else would
understand him and tried to grasp his
perspective — 'he had now become his own
propagandist: somewhere in the contemporary
world there exists an authority who will decide
both the future and the moral and spiritual
orientation of his generation' (207).
[It all ended in the final euphoria followed by
catatonia. I've not summarised the story which
occupies chapter 9. It is tempting to see all
the previous thought leading up to this crisis,
but even here Nietzsche's thoughts cannot be
separated very thoroughly from his reason —
reason and unreason were tightly connected for
that thought. Even his friends were 'not quite
sure if it was a mystification or a delirious
idea' (213), and one sympathetic person —
Overbeck -- attempted to apply an optimistic
understanding even though Nietzsche himself had
done 'his utmost to destroy [it]' (215).
Nietzsche's commitment to the fundamental role
played by chaos meant that he both invoked
chaotic forces and 'feared their imminent
irruption' (216).
Increasingly, the hidden roots of thought were
seen in terms of 'Intensity, excitation,
tonality: such is thoughts, independent of what
it expresses could express, and its application
in turn arouses other intensities, other
excitations, other tonalities'. Nietzsche
increasingly embraced 'the viewpoint of the
emotional capacity, and no longer the conceptual
capacity' [with an inevitable slide to fascism
in my view].
Chaos itself was increasingly expressed in more
manageable terms — 'first the ring; then the
wheel of Fortune; and finally the circulus
vitiosus deus'. Any individual seeking to
establish a firm centre for their personality is
bound to experience 'vehement oscillations' as
he swept up in the circle. He has to realize
that 'each [personality] corresponds to an
individuality other than the one he believes
himself to be'. Any stable identity can only be
'essentially fortuitous', as is the insight that
all the past identities have been necessary.
'What the Eternal Return implies as a doctrine
is neither more nor less than the insignificance
of the once and for all of the principle of
identity or non-contradiction, which lies at the
base of the [usual form of] understanding'
(217).
However the experience so vivid for Nietzsche,
'became obscure once Nietzsche tried to initiate
his friends into it'. The effort bumped into the
contradiction of trying to use conventional
terms after all, and his friends also 'felt the
delirium'. Nietzsche knew only too well the
problem of the contradiction: 'a word, once it
signifies an emotion, passes itself off as
identical to the experienced emotion, which in
turn had strength only when it had no word. A
signified emotion is weaker than an
insignificant emotion… [Any attempt at
communication introduces] a discrepancy between
what was experienced and what was
expressed' (217). [You can see the appeal
for Deleuze, but I think he also runs into the
same contradiction, as does Guattari — how to
express those swirling intensive forces that
underpin the actual? Borrowing bits of science
like embryology is one solution, but I suspect
the whole thing is really aimed only at
critiquing reification or scientism, and cannot
really produce any positive politics or
analysis].
When Nietzsche attempted to get people to think
with him, 'he was really inviting them to feel,
and thus to feel his own prior emotion' (218).
Nor could he do without presupposing some
skilled agent who would maintain the continuity
of links between emotions and words while
holding both ends open. The contradictions
involved led to Nietzsche's 'rise or fall
(euphoria – depression)', unmaking and making
the agent respectively.
In summary, Nietzsche argued that 'it is our
needs that interpret the world', impulses; it
follows that 'everything is an interpretation,
but... the subject that interprets is itself
interpretation', and 'the intelligibility of
everything that can only be thought... Is
derived from the gregarious morality of
truthfulness', and that to talk of truth implies
gregariousness [a social correspondence theory
in modern terms]. It also implies a knowable and
stable person.
Nietzsche never overcame ambiguity here. He
'ceaselessly oscillated' between seeing signs as
clear constant and fixed, and a 'propensity to
movement', a recognition that signs cannot
signify what is beyond their fixity. He tried to
come to terms with this using his 'theory of the
fortuitous case': first he tried to find some
new centre for his beliefs and personality, but
realise this was impossible and that he should
find some sort of strength in dissolution, that
'we have to be destroyers'. Some individual
natures can perfect themselves in such
dissolution becoming 'an image and isolated
example... Of existence in general' (220). Such
would be fortuitous cases, beings that can
thrive, become 'strong, crafty, and creative'
such fortuity of cases would in turn become
active agents. In his case, the great activity
conveyed by his travels in dissolution led to
the eternal return, an active response to 'the
paralysing sense of general dissolution and
incompleteness'. Nietzsche 'would incarnate the
fortuitous case' and attempt to reproduce the
world in thought, going beyond convention to the
unforeseeable.
These thoughts were present at the very start of
Nietzsche's career, although they might have
been made more apparent by his final collapse.
You can see his career as a kind of exchange
between health and insight. In order to fully
see yourself as expressing the eternal return,
you have to accept 'the destruction of the very
organ that had disclosed [this insight]: namely,
Nietzsche's brain, a fortuitous product realised
by the randomness that constitutes the Law of
all the possible (but limited) combinations of
the Return of all things' (221). This is how
Nietzsche himself understood. 'His authority was
not that of an individual... But that of a
fortuitous case, which is nothing other than the
expression of a law — and thus of a justice'.
He was forced to speak in a monstrous way in
order to break out of 'easy-going agnosticism'
(221). We have to 'speak the language of an
impostor – fool... And therefore we will say
this absurd thing: everything returns!' (222).
[Then we get back to the necessity to engage in
histrionics, connected to the critique of
Wagner]. The ability to produce something false
can be a guarantee of authenticity. We have to
reject the traditional notion of the true and
the false, and thinking of actors helps us do
this. That's why he talks so much about masks,
both in personal terms and as a powerful general
metaphor. He came to see himself as possessing a
necessary ego, but as a mask, and this would
help to vindicate him
[and a lot more elaboration of this view which
ended in a paranoid view of the world so that
Nietzsche believed he was applying some
programme — to convert people? The case is
closely argued in terms of the correspondence he
wrote in his last few years, especially letters
to and from Strindberg. Strindberg seems to have
encouraged his euphoria and high estimation of
himself. This estimation of himself escalated to
the point where 'what he was conscious of was
the fact that he had ceased to be Nietzsche,
that he had been, as it were, emptied of his
person' and had become almost a divine figure.
He saw himself as liberated from the reality
principle, and increasingly affirming the
fortuitous case 'and hence the arbitrary case
[as] the only reality' (236). He began to sign
himself variously as the crucified one, or as
Dionysus, again representing particular strands
in his philosophy. Increasingly, his philosophy
came to represent the final stage of paranoia
where the patient 'seeks to reconstitute the
world in a manner that will allow him to live in
it' (238). One development was a unified
Nietzsche relating back to the strains of his
childhood, but another was 'counter-Nietzsche...
Experienced as a liberation'.]
In the final additional note on Nietzsche's
semiotic, we revisit the problem of reconciling
impulses with the intellect, the incoherence and
arbitrary nature of these thoughts and the need
to obey intellectual constraints. [It's very
difficult to understand because of the absurd
style that Klossowski develops]. For example,
the notion of the will to power in his thought
is a primordial impulse somehow beyond
intellectual coherence, which distinguishes it
from classical notions of the will to power. It
is important not to adhere to intellectual
rigour which would exclude impulses. The tension
or competition is between the 'arbitrary
constraint imposed by the freedom of the
impulses, and the persuasive constraint of the
intellect' (255), although the intellect itself
can be seen as an impulse. Impulses are seen as
an end in their own right, but Nietzsche still
needed to make them into some sort of persuasive
constraint. What is needed is a form that
retains impulsive fluctuation and incoherence
while producing some version of the coherence of
the intellect, something which will interpret
concepts — and this is the aphorism.
The aphorism represents the full nature of the
fortuitous thoughts, something unpredictable,
something which does not rely upon a whole set
of intellectual conventions but which is
[somehow] 'pushed to a limit where thought puts
a stop to itself' (256). Thought here stands as
'the premeditation of an action... The
representation of a possible event', something
that happens to thought.
This notion of an outside, something that
resists thought strengthens his view of the
conventional nature of intellectual
representations. Every meditation presupposes a
premeditation. Representations can only
reactualize these prior events. There is also
something in conventional intellectual activity
that resists this outside. The aphorism
preserves this outside to conventional
conceptualisation. One implication is that we
should replace conventional concepts 'with what
he called values'(257).
The intellect is seen as something which
represses impulses, and breaks the connection
between the impulse and the agent. We are used
to interpreting this as a sense of threat.
Repressing impulses is required before the
intellect can be coherent and seen as connected
consistently to agents. In this sense, 'the
intellect is the obverse of the impulse' (259),
and it coheres with the agent at the expense of
seeing intellectual forms of identity as
coherence, and the end of the agent as being to
achieve coherence. If individuals connect with
the impulses instead, intellectual identities
become much more fragile. [Using earlier terms,
this can be seen as a coherence with phantasms
not simulacra].. Individuals can then become 'at
ease with the impulsive movement' and want to
express it. The problem arises when this
expression has to be achieved in a conventional
form, especially if it is to become an idea,
something 'valuable for another intellect'
(260). The impulse then becomes a kind of false
idea, reduced to something intellectual.
If communication is successful, however, it must
relate somehow to the coherence as an agent of
the other. This substitutes and necessary
coherence with another for a proper coherence
between phantasm and self.
We can never get to the bottom of the connection
between the phantasm and our impulses. We must
necessarily interpret the connection using
conventional signs. This turns the phantasm into
a simulacrum — 'we simulate what it means' — but
this means that we can never properly contact
phantasms and work out what it is they are
willing.
We can now understand conventional language as a
simulacrum relating to 'the external resistance
of others' (261), which might mean the need to
treat them as human others not just as simple
objects. Language provides us with 'a sphere of
declarations', and within that sphere, we can be
free to describe and manipulate the real.
However language is also the home of the false
and the simulated [I am not at all sure I have
understood this extremely complicated section],
given that false representations of our own
phantasms can appear to be true for others. This
can have the unfortunate consequence of making
it extremely difficult to grasp the phantasm and
the singular case, but it is a necessary
fraudulent consequence 'because it is willed as
such by both the generality and the singular
case' (261).
[Maybe the argument is] proper singularity is
doomed to disappear because it must engage in
conventional significations, and then it appears
just as 'a particular case of the species', a
conventional individual. There is no way out of
this. The singular case cannot think of itself
or express itself except through conventional
signs, and this immediately produces a
subtraction from singularity — 'it cannot
reconstitute itself through these signs without
at the same time excluding from itself what has
become intelligible or exchangeable in it'.
[And with that, I gratefully abandon any further
attempt to grasp these ridiculous arguments. I
do think they have implications for Deleuze
though who encounters all the same
contradictions trying to use ordinary {sort of}
philosophical language to explain the 'phantasm'
of the virtual and the singularity of the event
or haecceity] ]
|
|