Notes on: Scheurich, J and Young, M. (1997)
Coloring Epistemologies: Are Our Research
Epistemologies Racially Biased? Educational
Researcher 26 (4) 34 – 16.
http://wwwjstor.org/stable/1176879
Dave Harris
[Old/classic piece. Much cited. NB
'epistemological racism' is often rendered as
'epistemic racism' these days]
Others have suggested that epistemologies in
education research may be racially biased ways of
knowing, implicitly, suggesting that there might
be 'epistemological racism' (4), although this has
led to little response, certainly compared to the
usual debates about quantitative versus
qualitative or objective versus subjective. Is
that because this is too disquieting, or because
it is another example of white people ignoring
race?
The authors are both white and they intend to
offer a substantive response. Their own view is
that researchers have not understood that race is
a significant epistemological problem, affecting a
whole range of research epistemologies 'including
positivism, post-positivisms, neorealisms,
interpretive-isms, Constructivisms, the critical
tradition, and post-modernisms' (4). All are
racially biased. Five categories of racism in
particular are linked to research.
The first two, overt and covert racism, operate at
the individual level, the next two, organisational
and social categories, 'create the social context'
for the first two. The final one is a
civilisational category creating or constituting
the possibility for all the first four, and it is
that one that is the most salient.
The individual level is the most commonly
understood and arises where say a professor makes
a public racial slur during a lecture. This is
usually agreed to be unacceptable. Covert racism
might appear say when ethnic minority applicants
are not promoted, and there may be publicly
acceptable reasons provided, although such acts
are regarded as unacceptable and may even be
unlawful. In academia as more widely, racism is
seen mostly as intended, conscious and individual,
a matter of personal evaluation, and this
restricts understanding, especially of research
epistemology. As it is, even antiracist
individuals might still use an epistemology that
'could be judged to be racially biased' (5).
Institutional racism arises when there are
'standard operating procedures (intended or
unintended) that hurt members of one or more races
in relation to members of the dominant race' (5).
Institutional or organisational cultures rules
habits and symbols may have the same effect, and
be found in, say, promotional policies,
pedagogical methods, or where beliefs or
assumptions are embedded in a research discipline,
community of researchers, or even labels or
concepts of discipline, for example a phrase like
'"culturally disadvantaged" or "cultural
deprivation" to indicate why some students of
colour did not succeed in school [is]
institutional racism'. Some have argued that this
kind of racism 'is endemic to the social sciences'
ignoring or demeaning members of minority races or
distorting minority conditions and potentials (6)
[the reference is to Gordon et al 1990]. The
superiority of the white race can also be found in
other work such as inheritance and different
racial groups, racial difference in anthropology
and biology, race and intelligence, and even in
current ideas of black people being at risk,
emotionally disturbed or '"learning disabled".
This is still not epistemological racism, however,
even though research might use uncritically these
labels, and the critical tradition has argued this
particularly strongly.
Societal racism exists on a broad societywide
scale and appears in major social conflicts or
major social events such as the O.J. Simpson
trial, or national debates about leadership or the
rights of native American Indians, or governmental
programs for social relief. This is still not
epistemological racism, however which comes from
an even deeper level the civilisation level 'the
deepest most primary level' (6), fundamental to
Euro-American modernism itself.
At this level we find broad civilisational
assumptions, not usually held consciously, but
related to fundamental ideas about what the world
is, or the real. These are different for different
civilisations. They often include dominant and
subordinate cultures with different civilisational
assumptions, leading to quite different
interpretations of reality and ways of thinking.
Modernism describes the major ways that the
Euro-American dominant culture constructs the
world and the real, and it has as one of its major
assumptions 'civilisational racism' (7),
associated with colonial and territorial
expansion. The Tempest is an example of
white supremacy and widely accepted racial
hierarchies. They were central to the founding of
the USA, to the wars against Mexicans, to slavery.
The assumptions of the white subset have become
seen as natural, the dominant way to construct the
world. Edward Said is cited. Thus epistemology and
axiology are deeply woven with social history,
affected by privileged residents [NB!] of
historically specific societies. All the dominant
philosophers have been white. They have all been
influenced [determined by?] by dominant ideas in
the cultures and sub- societies in which they have
lived, even 'constructed by their position place
and time' (8), thus 'reality is determined largely
[!] through our cultural context'.
There is no racial conspiracy, more a series of
limits from social context, which affect not only
those in the past but ourselves [we liberals and
activists as well?]. 'No epistemology is context
free', and all the dominant and legitimate ones
have arisen 'exclusively out of the social history
of the dominant white race', thus they must be
'racially biased'. They need not be covertly or
overtly racist, it need not be conscious, it is
simply that dominant epistemologies 'logically
reflect and reinforce that social history and that
racial group (while excluding the epistemologies
of other races/cultures) and that this has
negative results for people of colour in general
and scholars of colour in particular'. This
excludes the range of possibilities and has
negative consequences.
It delegitimise other epistemologies and research
such as African-American social history or First
Nations social history because the real merit of
those approaches cannot be judged — e.g. Apache
stories and songs. Applying standard
epistemologies distorts the lives of other racial
groups and tend to pathologise them. This can be
internalised and/or lead to time-consuming
struggles to reject and resist. The dominant
approaches just fit white researchers better, and
do not require scholars to be bicultural. [All of
which assumes that the dominant white culture has
not actually been that dominant, that the
historical lag somehow persists?]
The critical tradition might be exempt? There has
been much white participation in antiracism, and
has even led to a new interest in a recovery of
history for nonwhite people. Nevertheless it is
still based on European paradigms and still open
to critique for residual racial biases [they
accuse all the different critical approaches —
'critical theory, feminism, lesbian/gay
orientations and critical post-modernism' (10)].
Nor is critical theory identical to race-based
emancipatory epistemology.
We need a new race-based epistemology, such as
Collins' black feminist thought, which is
Afrocentric. She stresses concrete experience as a
criterion of meaning, the use of dialogue and
assessing knowledge claims, the ethic of caring,
the ethic of personal accountability. This was
based on experience and relations with
African-American women, who were encouraged to
develop their voice. This admittedly reflected the
conditions of its creators. It has become
respected by other black women and has been used
in research, for example in a more recent study of
teachers of African-American children [must look
it up] . Apparently its adequacy lies in
reflecting who people think they are and the
experiences they have had in helping them manage
membership in a marginalised racial and cultural
group, something that fits social history, that
emerges from a particular social history not the
history of a dominant race. Others have developed
an Afrocentric epistemology using similar
perspectives and there have been other
applications [cited on page 10]. The claim is that
this perspective '"allows Africans to be subjects
of their own historical experience rather than
objects… On the fringes of Europe'. It is claimed
to be emancipatory. It includes qualitative
methodology and critical dialogue 'with those
involved in the research education and action'.
Another perspective originated in legal studies —
critical race theory, which began to look at how
legal thought and doctrine constructed and
maintained social domination and subordination. It
became necessary to criticise assumptions and
presuppositions of the prevailing paradigms in
legal institutions, both liberal and conservative
and also to address the silence of critical legal
studies, who had largely ignored race and racism.
This has migrated into social sciences and there
have been calls for papers on CRT in the USA. It
has been largely confined to race oriented
academic journals so far because mainstream
journals do not accept papers which 'do not
conform to acceptable paradigms'(11). This makes a
nice case — 'the very existence of these journals
is one of the consequences of the mainstream
exclusion of race-based epistemologies'.
There are others and these need to be respected
and discussed. Above all though we need to rethink
what racism is. White researchers might be
'unconsciously promulgating racism on an
epistemological level', promoting the social
history of the dominant race. Vigorous debate and
dialogue is required especially among methods
scholars. Traditional researchers want to argue
that their epistemology reaches towards context
free truth but they need to join the discussion —
'let us have a fierce row over this '[we can't].
New antiracist epistemologies need to be taught,
even though they are more risky. We should support
doctoral studies and encourage publication, even
sponsoring special editions and new research
methods courses we must make the problem visible.
We cannot continue in our old ways.
[Interesting piece but a bit paradoxical?
White/colonial epistemology seems to have no
contradictions, alternatives or crises? No white
people opposed colonisation, racism or slavery?
Europeans had no time for Islamic, Arabic, Greek
or Indian philosophy (although not African or
First Nation, to be fair except via various
romances)? There are no reflexive or self-critical
bits -- although these two white writers have
managed to come up with a fundamental critique --
did they draw on indigenous knowledge to do so?
The philosophies of the elite seem simply to have
dominated. In other words, this is a dominant
ideology thesis, particulalry tricky to apply to
methods I would have thought. The problem is that
e[pistemic racism is so general and pervasive that
it rules out any kind of effort other than
indigenous (any kind of indigenous?) critical
thinking, implies that all such thinking is
racist, whether the thinker themself is racist or
not, and presumably disqualifies all but the
authentically indigenous unsulllied by
whiteness?].
|
|