Dr W Large An
Introduction to Kant's Aesthetics 30 January
2007 15:58
19 Distinterestedness
is
what defines aesthetic judgement including personal and non-personal
interests
- the agreeable and the moral. Interest
means here the
existence of the object. What matters to me is the representation in
myself. 20 'It allows
me to rely
more on myself than my own powers' No doubt I
can get
pleasure from natural objects, but it is not dependent on them - since
the
sunset could equally exist in a picture or in a film. If I was
disappointed my
its non-existence, then I must have some other reason for liking it -
the
warmth on my skin for example. Though
conceptually it
might be possible to distinguish pure satisfaction from interest one -
can I
ever be sure that my delight in the beauty of someone is not
contaminated by my
desire to posses them? This is not a subjective but an objective
criterion - no
one can tell this from the outside. But also it is logically universal,
since
it is true for everyone that they must make this decision (form and
content) 21 Beauty for
Kant is see
from the side of the subject and not the object. But this idea of
subjective is
very complex, it is not merely subject but involves universal elements
and
intersubjective criteria Beauty is
a distance
from the object but also from oneself - in terms of personal needs - to
do this
we need to have different conception of the subject - one that it not
just
pathological - thus there are two subjects in Kant. In both
the agreeable
and the good there cannot be a free satisfaction. In the agreeable, I
like the
object and desire it, in the moral, I desire the object and therefore
like it. But don't
we need
objects of art to exist if we are going to find any delight in them?
Also don't
we have to have some knowledge about art to be able to appreciate it? 23 There are
3 types of
satisfaction in Kant which are also 3 types of representation. Again this
is
subjective and not objective - I do not get pleasure of the beautiful
because
something is beautiful, but because I take something to be beautiful,
it is
beautiful. In the
other two cases,
there is always an interest. 24 The
ability to find
something beautiful is part of our human nature. What is
agreeable is
determined by our sensation - i.e. we are dependent on the existence of
the
thing Satisfaction
in the
moral good is not free but interested because we are determined by the
concept
of reason. Kant's
argument is
negative 1) if something is disinterested then is it beautiful, if
something is
neither agreeable or good, then it is beautiful These are
only negative
moments - Kant has to give us a positive
description of the beautiful. Universality
: The
Second Moment 27 The
judgement of the
beautiful is accompanied by a claim of universality, but this claim can
only be
Objective
- rather it
is part of my representation and satisfaction. Thus I can only make a
claim to
universality rather than require it. 28 Section 6
and 9 have
different arguments - the first is negative from disinterestedness
whereas the
second is positive from the idea of the 'free play of the faculties'. 29 When we
are speaking
about universality here, we are not speaking about object here as Kant
would
speak about them in the first critique, rather we are speaking about
our
reflection or relation to them with ourselves, and thus also so the
same
relation in other (this idea of the subject and the intersubjective
will be
very important later) But does
this let me
leap from saying just because it is not in my interest then it must be
for
everyone? Couldn't there also be a third possibility - a group or an
individual
for example - but this way of thinking is not possible for Kant. For
him there
are only two possibilities, one) either one thinks at the level of the
individual or at the level of humanity in general (the critique of Kant
therefore is that what he takes to be 'the level of humanity' is only Königsberg
universalised. 30 Although
philosophically we can make these distinctions, as individuals, i.e.
psychologically, we can never be sure (and this is true of ethics as
well - can
I ever be sure that I act from pure intentions). But for Kant he is
only
interested in these transcendental questions and never empirical ones. 31 When we
make judgements
we sometime expect universality and sometimes not. So in mathematical
judgements I would, but for a momentary inclination, I might not. But
why would
I expect universality in aesthetics? In the
first case, as
also in objective empirical judgements, it is the objects which force
the
intersubjective agreement at least in ideal circumstances. But
judgement of taste
are not objective but subjective, and therefore universality becomes a
problem
- we might immediately what to say that they must be subjective and
thus not
universal, since subjective statements by definition cannot be universal - subjective universal by definition seems to
be a contradiction in terms. Taste is
based on
sensation - I must hear the song my Will Oldham - but what makes taste,
taste
is not - it is prior to experience. But what of taste is prior to
experience?
It is the universal. So if we say that there is nothing universal in
aesthetics
we destroy it What do we
mean by the
universal? We have to distinguish the universal from the general. What
do we
mean by the general? We can imagine an exception - generally people
when the
hear will oldham like it, but I can imagine that some will not - this
is an
empirical statement not a judgement of taste. Even if everyone at the
moment likes
Will Oldham if I can imagine an exception then this is not an aesthetic
statement. What is an universal statement. One that has no exception.
That is
they are conceptual rather than merely description of fact - all
triangles are
3 sided figures - if this was merely a description of facts, a
generality, then
if I came across a 4 sided one, it wouldn't really bother me it would
just be
the exception that proves the rule - but in fact this is not a
generality it is
a universality, so I really would be bothered and I would have to
change my
very definition of triangle or at least realise that there was
something wrong
with my current one. Now when
we make claims
to taste this are universal but they are not objective - they are not
statements of generality, but of universality - all human beings should
feel
like me and if they do no they are lacking taste.' This is normative
and not
objective - the universality of the judgement of triangles has to do
with the
concept and not with my relation to my own feeling - here the relation
is
purely subjective - my perception and my feeling and the judgement that
everyone else should feel like this too.
When we
say that this
universality is not given by the object, we are saying that it is not
conceptual. The reference of universality is not the object but the
subject -
other subject - subjective in the sense that others should think the
way that I
do. This should be distinguished from the subjective ground of
judgement of
taste. What then
is the link
between subjective in the second and I first sense - what Kant is
trying to say
is that right at the heart of aesthetics judgement already involves the
relation to others, and it is this what distinguished moral judgements
from
merely agreeable ones or moral ones Is
there not
a relation to Others in Kant's morality - how would it be different
from this
relation? 34 What is
important is
that there are no external rules for Kant (it is this that makes him
different
from his contemporaries) - thus something is not beautiful because it
is x -
rather it is my relation to my representation of x which makes it
beautiful.
Thus it is the redness of the chair that determines that my statement
that the
chair is red is true or not - for Kant this not my relation to the
aesthetic object,
even if it is the same object, rather it is 'free play of the
faculties'
between imagination and the understanding. It is this free play which
cause the
feelings of pleasure and displeasure which are wholly related to the
subject
and not the object. What makes them universal is that they are
'accessible to
every human being'. 36 What is
the difference
between a transcendental philosopher and a mere logician. The latter is
only
interested in the relation between the definitions of objects - whereas
the
former is interested in the relation between judgement perception and
the
object itself - thus the relation between the imagination and
understanding -
intuitions and concepts - the philosopher is interested in how we
related to
the world - for Kant time and space and how this relates to how
categories
which are the basis of our conceptuality - the application of concepts
to
objects - in these sense singular and universal judgements are the same
for the
logician since tree and trees are the same, but for the transcendental
philosopher they are not. What
concerns Kant is
the application of concepts to experience - this is what
transcendental
means. This means what is the correct relation between concepts and
intuitions
(not just the formal relationship between definitions). The incorrect
application is called transcendent whereas the correct is
transcendental. 38 When we
say that
judgement of taste is subject, we mean that it is origin is in the
subject.
Section 9 tells us that the true origin of the aesthetic judgement is
the free
play between the faculties in the subject - the faculties being reason,
imagination, and the understanding. The second part of this subjective
origin
is 'subjective purposiveness' which is at the heart of this free play. In Kant's
other
critical writings - universal assent was thought possible only in terms
of
objectivity. It is this notion of subjective universality which is so
novel in
the So the
aesthetic
judgement is both singular and universal. This means that the
representation of
the object in the subject must be very different from cognitive
judgement. The
source of this difference must be in the idea of singularity, which
means that
we have one object in our minds, but we represent this object to
ourselves in a
very different way. 39 Why should
judgement of
taste be singular meaning that the statement 'all roses are beautiful'
could
not be an aesthetic, but only 'this rose is beautiful'. But Kant seems
to imply
that the idea of singular universal judgements are peculiar which is
not the
case since the following is singular and universal 'the number 5 is a
prime
number'. 40 It must be
that these
judgements are singular and universal in a special way. This rose
is
beautiful - does not depend on sensation,
or a determinate concept.
Thus it
can only be a
judgement of the beautiful and not the agreeable and morality. It still involves concepts, but in an
indeterminate way. That is there is no necessary relation between what
concepts
I use to express by satisfaction in the beauty of the flower. I could express it is a 'gesture or a poem'.
They simply ways of expressing my feeling, but there is no necessary
relation
between them. It is
precisely this lose of indeterminacy which is lost in the analysis of
literature. 41 In
cognition there is a
necessary relation between the object and the predicate - rose and red
for
example, whereas in aesthetic judgements, I leave this relation open. In
cognition, it is the
relation between intuitions and concepts which determine the object,
whereas in
aesthetic judgements it is the facilities themselves. I still have a
perception
of the object, but what is important about is not my knowledge of it;
rather I
enjoy it in terms of 'open possibilites' of concepts and attributes and
even
memories and association through the 'free play' of the imagination and
the
understanding. 42 In beauty
it is not the
concept itself which matter - again I know that it is rose, but the
fact that I
do know this is not important to my judgement. This is what makes it
different
from other types of singular judgements which are determinate concepts
- fixed
relation between a concept and attributes. It is singular because it is
about
an object, but also it is only about the relation between faculties and
not
intuitions and concepts, and the 'object is not even cognized as an
object'. 43 Also what
is relevant
is the feeling that the subject has, rather than what is said
objectively about
the object. 44 If
aesthetic judgements
have nothing to do with logical judgements, then where does the
universality
come from? The
universality does
not lie in something about the object in terms of logical judgements,
nor in
rules or social taste, but in the autonomy of
the subject, which has open up the free
play of the faculties in relation to the object. 45 We say
that is
judgements of taste that everyone should agree - but this can't be
because of
something in the object. Why don't we find this in the subject instead
- and
not in my subjectivity, but subjectivity in general, or what we might
call -
intersubjective - what we might call the 'idea of humanity'. But here it is linked to the idea of
purposiveness. 46 Does
feeling precede
judgement or judgement feeling - what concerns Kant here is the logical
order
and not the temporal. That is that the judgement of tastes implies a
specific
kind of judgement, without which it would not be possible, and in this
sense it
must precede the judgement of taste. When Kant
talks about
'judging about the object' he does so in terms of communicability. If
there
were only 'mere' pleasure then there would be no possibility of saying
that a
judgement of taste has a universal claim. 48 Thus what
is peculiar
about judgements of taste is that at their heart they are communicable,
it is
not merely just a subjective pleasure, and this communication is not
just added
onto our experience of pleasure, but belongs to this pleasure itself.
The
ground of this is the universal capacity for the communication of the
state of
mind. This can be read in two ways. One as the capacity of
communication which
is held by the state of mind, and then the capacity of communicating a
state of
mind - it is the second which is important for Kant's interpretation.
It is this
universal
capacity which makes the aesthetic judgement different from the merely
agreeable So what is
it that is
universally communicable - is it a certain state of mind - what kind of
mind is
this? The answer is purposiveness. 49 In
cognition it is the
object which serves as the common ground which is universally
communicable.
What is the reference state in aesthetic judgement is that state of
mind in the
play of faculties - this isn't just personal, rather there is something
universal about this state of mind. What is
universal here
is the relation to cognition in general - it is in free play but not
chaos or
insane - rather there is something in it that we can all follow - 'it
still
makes sense'. It is universal because it involves faculties that every
human
being has happens in relation to 'cognition in general'. It is this
judging
which must precede the feeling of pleasure 51 The
condition is the
free play of faculties which is a certain state of mind.
- but this free play of the faculties is itself
the condition for cognition in general. The Judgement of cognition
requires the
harmony of understanding and the imagination which is determinate,
which is
different from the free harmonious relation in the aesthetic judgement.
It is
through the relation between the imagination and the understanding,
which is
either determinate, as in cognition, or free, as is aesthetics, that
the
judgement of taste has the ground for the source of its claim to
universality. Purposiveness
: Third
Moment 54 We can
understand ends
in terms of purposiveness - what is the purpose of the thing that I am
looking
at - for Kant when I look at an object aesthetically, I am not at all
interested in its purpose - what is it for. In terms
of the First
Critique, the most important logical relation is causality and that
there
are two notions of causality: efficient and final. It is the latter
which is
applicable to aesthetics for Kant. 55 How can a
concept be a
cause of an object? We might think that in terms of an intention or
will - we
say the roof is built to keep the rain out. It would not exist without
that
intention. 56 But Kant
does not refer
to intention or will but to representation. In other words he is
interested in
subjective and not objective relations, subjective and not objective
causality
- what he means by that is that I imagine a house and then build it
according
to my image. This means that in the imagination the effect is prior to
the
cause - I already imagine the house there, and in so doing I cause the
house to
exist. This has
to do with
aesthetics because it is subjective and not objective. It is the
feeling of
pleasure that maintains the relation between the representation and the
effect.
Thus I have the image of the house in my mind and its effect is
maintained
through the subjective feeling of pleasure. The important thing is to
hold onto
the notion of final causality and not translate it into efficient
causality -
the representation does not cause our pleasure, rather it is the result
of the
'animation of my imagination and understanding through the
representation of
the object. It is what Kant will call a 'inner causality'. This kind
of
auto-pleasure of the mind is related to the cognition in general. The
actual
feeling of pleasure is empirical, but the origin of this pleasure is
transcendental.
and this
transcendental
condition of possibility is purposiveness. This
self-pleasuring of
the human mind cannot be willed or forced - its only purpose is
internal - it
is self-purposive. Here cause and effect are the same: free play. We
want it to
last, but it is a present or a gift. 57 We can
make
preparations for it, go to a concert or a museum, but there is no
certainty
that such a feeling of pleasure will happen - it is rare and fleeting.
Thus to
truly experience aesthetically I have to lose my intentions and will. What do we
mean by
purposiveness? The example of the watch - I find this object thousand
of years
later - I know that it has a purpose from the way that it is made, but
I do not
know what it is. But if I find out what it does, or what its function
is for,
then it would no longer be purposiveness without purpose. When we think
of
objects then there is not purposiveness without a purpose, but when we
think of
the subject, its inner causality, then we might speak of a
purposiveness
without a purpose. Our feelings are not the object of some external
investigation, rather they have to do with the way that we feel - there
is no
object of nature that would correspond to them. Everything
to do with
aesthetic judgement is purposive in some way, the imagination and the
understanding. But this purposiveness is felt subjectively. It is
purposiveness
which is a relation within our mind, and not between our mind and a
object, and
which does not require any reference to something outside of it - even
an
intention or a will that would cause us to have such thought - the a
priori
condition of aesthetic judgement is that we can have a relation to
representations within our minds that are purposive without a purpose. Why does
Kant drop
efficient causality for final causality - why can't we think of an
efficient
cause between the object and the subject - that the object causes this
pleasure
in my mind? 58 But this
would imply
that there are objective rules to aesthetic judgements - that if an
object had
such and such properties, then we could claim it to be beautiful in
itself
without any relation to any subject. The
difference from
morality is that the freedom of causality is an efficient cause - I
have an
idea then I change the world through it - but such a process is via
reflection
and principles. Aesthetic judgements have nothing to do with principles
- it is
a subjective feeling. What they have to do with is 'inner causality'
and
animation of our cognitive powers internally. If we say
that there is
a purpose to aesthetics judgements then we would have to ask who had
that
purpose in mind. 59 Rather for
Kant we just
happen to have aesthetic judgements that are without purpose. 61 Beauty for
Kant has to
do with form and not matter. It is the
formal as
opposed to the material aspects of the states of mind which are
communicable.
Charm has to do with our immediate sensation of an object, and is
therefore
personal and not universal which involves cognition (the beautiful
involves
reflection even though it is not conceptual - it is not merely a
sensation,
which would make the beautiful the same as the agreeable. Because charm
has to
do with sensation, it has to do with interest, and therefore it cannot
be
impartial as aesthetic judgement are meant to be. What Kant
is aiming to
do is make a connection between the purposiveness of form (the object,
space
and time) and forms of purposiveness that are in the subject. His
argument that
it is only formal aspects of the object (space and time) which can be
part of
any aesthetic judgement (the play of the faculties)
62 Wenzel
claims that
there are 3 kinds of purposiveness in Kant
In the
case of the
latter to we might say that they strengthen both our faculties and
cognition in
general. We can
therefore
understand what Kant means by purposiveness without purpose - it has to
do with
the powers of cognition in general without reference to an object or
the
concept of the object (auto-affection of the mind - increasing the
power of the
mind, the pleasure of the mind). But what
has this to do
with the formal properties of the object (space and time?) 63 purposiveness
without
purpose is the a priori principle of judgements of taste. This is the
source of
the universality of judgements. Thus it is not the object which makes
us say
that it is beautiful, but the subject. However Kant does not want to
reduce
aesthetic judgements to the merely subjective (since this would be to
reduce
the beautiful to a mere sensation). But what is it about the object
that we are
communicating in aesthetic judgement (we might want to make the
distinction
between secondary and primary qualities as in Hume, but this is too
simple).
There are two problems - one are we not sure that the examples that
Kant gives,
tone and colour, cannot be reduced to time and space, and secondly is
it really
possible in the aesthetic judgement to abstract from form and sensation
- where
is the dividing line between the two? It is
important for
Kant though that if we are going to make sensations the object of
aesthetic
judgements that we can abstract them - thus his reference to Euler's
theory of
colours. But what would this have to do with aesthetics? Isn’t this
science? It is the
form of the
object that then becomes the source of the free play of the faculties
which is
universal to all - this is the basis of the universal claim - it is not
a mere
sensation, it is cognitive, but it is not conceptual (related to an
object) but
internal (the relation of the mind to itself), which I can say anyone
could
have (sensations on the contrary are always personal) - of course you
might not
have it, since aesthetic judgements are singular not conceptual, but I
can
imagine that you might have it. 65 We tend to
think that
when we say that something is beautiful that it is perfect. Kant's
argument is
thought ideas of perfection might accompany judgements of taste, we
should not
confuse the two. This is because ideas of perfection always include the
concept
of an object. 66 Here Kant
is arguing
against Baumgarten. Even if we thing that beauty contains perfection in
a
confused way, then we are still promising that in some future date, we
might
have a concept of beauty, and this would make beauty something
objective as
opposed to subjective - that we could have a definition of what art is
from the
outside, listing certain properties, which if something did not have,
it would
cease to be art at all. Again we need to remind ourselves that
aesthetics has
to do with subjective and not objective purposiveness - animating the
mind, and
not defining the function or purpose of an object. We do not need to
know what
an object is for in order to feel that it is beautiful, and even if we
do know
what an object is for then we can always abstract from its use, when we
take it
to be beautiful. 67 This
means, against
Baumgarten, there can be no rules for taste. The object does not have
to 'live
up' to a perfect idea of what the object must be, rather all I am
concerned
with are its formal properties which cause the powers of mind to
increase and
to become animated - art makes me think but not in a conceptual way.
Thinking is
not conceptual - or not just conceptual - art increases by power to
think (what
could even think of this in terms of Spinoza) that is its purpose. 69 If we look
at a house
and say that it is beautiful because it is a perfect embodiment of what
a house
should be, then for Kant, we are not making an aesthetic judgement,
since this
must be based upon a concept of a house. At best we might say that we
are
making a impure judgement of beauty. Of course
it is almost
impossible for us in reality to abstract from such knowledge, therefore
in
relation to certain object (such as houses) it might be impossible for
us to
make pure aesthetic judgements, because we cannot forget that we know
what the
object is. But even with what we might call purely aesthetic objects
such as
music is it right to say that we don't need any conceptual knowledge,
or that
we can abstract from this knowledge complete - doesn't one appreciate
Bach more
because one understands musically what Bach is? 70 When it
comes to nature
it seems easier to say that we don't
need conceptual knowledge, because when we observe a
natural object as
beautiful then precisely we are not viewing it in terms of its function
(the
colour of a flower is to attract bees). But then we did not make these
things,
so to appreciate them we do not need to know how they work. What Kant
means by free
beauty is that they just 'signify for themselves' we don't need to look
outside
of them in order to appreciate their beauty. But this does show that
are
experience of them as beautiful as nothing at all to do with our
objective
knowledge of them, since we can still say that they are beautiful even
if we do
not have any knowledge of them - beauty is subjective, not objective. 71 We other
objects,
because we do have knowledge of them, it is difficult for us to
abstract from
our knowledge. This is
why Kant makes
the distinction between free and dependent beauty. The first does not
presuppose a concept of the object, the other does. Thus in entering a
gothic
church, I cannot say that the beauty is totally free, because to
understand it
I have to have some knowledge of what it means to be Gothic (human
history and
the purpose and function of cathedral building). And in this sense
taste
becomes fixed in terms of knowledge, and also beauty becomes to have a
function
and a purpose - the gothic church is beautiful because if fulfils a
purpose. 72 The
difference between
the two is that in dependent beauty, concept are more important in the
experience of beauty - the free play of the faculties - sensations are
immediately referred to representations without the mediation of
concepts Are
concepts
then just attached to dependent beauty - if they are determinate then
how can
we say that this is a judgement of beauty at all? This is
especially the
case with art, since they are man made objects, and therefore we can
also speak
of the intentions of the artist (which must be an end) in relation to
our
aesthetic judgement - but this still cannot be a pure judgement. The real
reason perhaps
why Kant will allow concepts to re-enter our experience of beauty is
that he
want to tie together morality and aesthetics. This has to do with the
ideal of
beauty and the importance of the human figure 73 Kant makes
a threefold
distinction between
The latter
two are
empirical - the ideal is an empirical image, whereas the normal idea is
the
figure of the universal of a species. The normal
idea has to
do with the imagination - thus if we reflect in our mind images of
horses, if
we combine them together we will get the normal idea of a horse. This
is purely
empirical and is determined by what we imagine - thus the normal idea
of human
being will differ between the Chinese and the European. Once such a
normal idea
has been established then we have a norm in which to judge specific
instances -
we appear to have a rule. The exemplar. This isn't beautiful in itself,
though
it does not have to contradict it, since for Kant, the beautiful is
always the
singular and the individual - it is without comparison - otherwise
beauty would
be conceptual - if such and such a object had these properties then I
would
find it beautiful. 74 The ideal
of beauty has
to be more that the normal idea, because it can always break with
conventions
(in fact Kant's definition of genius means that it must). But such an
ideal of
beauty is only obtained through the idea of morality. This means that
the ideal
can only be the human figure where we connect the play of
representations with
the moral idea of humanity as a whole. The
difference between
the normal idea and the ideal of beauty is the notion of the idea - it
is the
idea of humanity as an end in itself, which makes the difference
between the
ideal, connected to the play of representations, and the normal idea.
The
question is how can something empirical exhibit what is purely
rational, an
idea which cannot be perceived? The connection is ourselves - and has
to do
with the power of reflection - only human beings can be moral because
only
human beings can be both the subject and the object of the moral law,
and this
is analogous with aesthetics - I am both the subject and the object,
because it
has to do with reflection - the difference is that morality is
conceptual. 75 The human
ideal is
moral not beauty, but beauty can express this ideal - thus the human
ideal is
not a pure aesthetic judgement - but one that is attached to a moral
idea. What Kant
is driving at
is that beauty can serve as the bridge between nature and freedom,
because it
is the sensuous manifestation of freedom. 76 When Kant
says that
this is no mere judgement of taste, then we should not view this
negatively -
for Kant it might be quite the opposite, that a mixed judgement of
taste is
more valuable than a pure one. Necessity:
Fourth
Moment 77 Kant first
begins with
how we think and speak about aesthetics - only later does he go onto
the
philosophical reflections - thus the way that we speak about aesthetics
is that
they do have some necessity - the question is what kind of necessity is
this? 78 The answer
goes back to
what has already been said about universality. The claim to
universality can only
be made if some one actually makes this judgement. It is not derived
from some
conceptual or logical definition. Rather the free play of the faculties
has to
happen in order for you to make the claim. This is
why the
necessity here is called exemplarity This seems
to be a
rule, but in fact it isn't - the JT comes first and then set up the
rule - it
is exemplary for others to follow (and they might not).
79 Thus the
JT is original
and it is an example that other can follow (just as genius work of art
is
something that other can follow, though the rule cannot be know in
advance, and
even the author of the work might not know how they produced it). This
means
that one has to have genius in order to make a JT, otherwise one just
imitates
what everyone else things, and not follow one's own tastes. There are
only two
possible forms of necessity in the JT
The JT is
the free play
of the cognitive faculties - this is what it is based upon and
subjective
purposiveness - there appears to be a necessary relation to this and
the free
play of the faculties. And then having this feeling also necessitates
the
assent - I have this feeling why don't you as well? 80 Although
there isn't
any rule, given in advance, it seems to us that there is. This is
supported my
what Kant calls a 'common feeling' - I have to allude in an aesthetic
judgement
that to something that we all feel. Does Kant mean that I would be able
to have
the aesthetic taste of Martian, or he of me? This
common feeling is
what takes the place of the rule which we don't have - it is only an
idea. That
is I imagine that we all feel the same way. It isn't
the common
feeling which explains the play of the faculties and the subjective
purposiveness, but the other way round - it is they that make sense of
the
common feeling - we only have the idea of the common feeling because
the free
play of the faculties and subjective purposiveness. 83 But this
still does not
tell me what justifies me making this appeal to necessity What we
should not
think is that idea of a common feeling appeals to a real common feeling
such
that we would all feel the same in relation to the same object. This is
why for
him the real ground for agreement is the free play of the faculties and
the
subjective purposiveness. There must
be principle
by which I can argue that others ought to have my taste, and this
common ground
is this common feeling - but all Kant means by the common feeling is
precisely
what he explained before hand in the other 2 moments. 84 In
aesthetic reflection we demand the agreement of others, thus we reach
out to
them, we think of them as being in our situation. To be able
to do this,
we have to abstract from any thing that is personal - indeed anything
that
might be personal about the object itself, and our interest in it -
this is why
it is the form that is important, because it is this that relates to
the free
play of the faculties. |