Dr W Large
Transcendental Theology
To be able first of all to
understand revolution in the concept of God
which happens with Kant, we first of all need to understand the scope
of the Critique of Pure Reason. We
must recognise that Kant is writing
philosophy in the age of the triumph of the new scientific method which
understands nature in terms of mathematics and not individual
substances as in
the metaphysics of Aristotle. The first
critique is a philosophical defence for the success of Newtonian
science. The natural philosophical partner
of science
is empiricism, and yet empiricism, at least as Kant sees it, cannot
offer a
secure foundation to the sciences. It
leads, as the work of Hume demonstrates, to fundamental scepticism. The problem is whether reason can know
something beyond experience, but which at the same time is not
vulnerable to
the criticisms of scepticism. The key to
Kant’s solution is that the only object of reason is reason itself. Or that reason cannot know of anything
outside of reason, or if reason does posit something outside of reason,
then
this is reason’s own outside. But this
would mean, against empiricism, that experience itself must be internal
to
reason, rather than something unknowable which remains inaccessible to
human thought,
for where dogmatism and empiricism remain the same is that they both
have an
outside, dogmatism in the idea of infinity and empiricism in the idea
of the
object. For Kant, it is not a matter of
knowledge trying to reach outside of itself to something alien (which
it either
fails to reach or distorts, since its essence is different from the
object it
desires to know), but of the recognition that what is outside knowledge
has
knowledge itself as its very foundation.
The truth of the object is to be found in the subject
itself. Knowledge must not conform to
objects; rather
objects must conform to knowledge. But
if reason itself is the ground of reason what possible limits could
there be to
reason’s claims as to what it can and cannot know?
It is the purpose of the Critique of Pure
Reason to answer this question. There
are basically two limitations for Kant:
experience itself and the a priori.
Nonetheless, as he underlines in the second
preface to the first critique, this self-limitation of reason is valid
for the
science only, whether pure or applied, and the limitation of reason as
to what
it can rightly claim to know is to make room for faith.
Thus, reason cannot know God, for reason can
only know itself, but this merely leaves room for belief. What we do need to be careful of here is not
to confuse the God of faith with the God of reason, as though they had
the same
content, but one we now say we believe in rather than know. On the
contrary, the
very content of the concept of God changes in Kant’s philosophy. It goes from being an object external to
reason, to an idea immanent to reason
itself. Why can Kant say
that objects must conform to our knowledge rather than our knowledge
must
conform to them? This is because he
takes the empirical critique of epistemology seriously.
Thus we cannot know what objects are in
themselves, but only how they appear to us.
But if we only know how objects appear to us, then this
very manner of
appearing is going to be determined by our own mode of knowledge. Kant argues that there is a fundamental basis
to human knowing which is a
priori, that is to say it does not
come from the object, or even the individual person themselves, rather
it comes
from the mode of knowledge all objects, and it is this mode of
knowledge which
determines the appearing of any object.
There are two sides to this mode of knowledge, one which
is space and
time, every object appears in space and time, and must conform to space
and
time in order to be an object for human beings, and secondly as object
of
knowledge, every object must conform to the categories of the human
understanding, which are the basic building blocks of human
understanding. The first two part of the
critique, the
transcendental aesthetic and analytic, seek to describe the two sides
of the a priori and also give a proof of their
validity in what is called the deduction.
The detail of their description and their proof does not
concern us
here, for what we are interested in is in the change of the meaning of
God once
we claim that objects conform to us, rather than we must conform to
objects. We must, however, underline
that for Kant the a priori is only
one side of knowledge. Without
experience, there would no knowledge at all. As Kant says, concepts
without
intuitions are empty, as intuitions without concepts are blind Without
sensibility no object would be given to us, without understanding no
object
would be thought. Thoughts without
content are empty, intuitions without concept are blind. It is
therefore just
as necessary to make our concepts sensible, that is, to add the object
to them
in intuition, as to make our intuitions intelligible, that is, to bring
them
under concepts. These two powers or capacities cannot exchange their
functions.
The understanding can intuit nothing, the senses can think nothing. Only through their union can
knowledge arise. (A51/B79) For there to be knowledge of
something an object must be given to
consciousness, but God cannot be an empirical object, and therefore the
knowledge that theology has claimed to have for centuries it simply a
bogus
one. Let us then look in a little more detail in Kant’s critique of one
form of
theological reasoning, the cosmological argument.
We can say that there are two
forms of Kant’s objection to this type of argument.
One concerns the possibility of thinking of
the universe as a whole such that one could think of a cause preceding
it, and
the other is that the cosmological argument actually sneaks in the
ontological
argument, which is equally invalid. One,
therefore is a scientific disproof not by showing that we can
scientifically
demonstrate the God does not exist, but that science requires no need
of the
concept of first cause, and in fact it is not scientifically
demonstrable. The other is a logical
disproof of the
cosmological argument by showing that it still requires a movement from
essence
to existence that is illegitimate. As we have
already said, to understand Kant’s argument here we need to understand
the
overall argument of the Critique of Pure
Reason. In this work, Kant wants to
show what the necessary limits of scientific, or theoretical reasoning
can
be. He argues that science or
theoretical reason must be limited to experience, otherwise we are left
with
dogmatic proofs that cannot be validated.
One such dogmatic proof is the cosmological argument. Experience for Kant is made of two elements,
concepts and intuitions. His basic
position is that the cosmological argument confuses concepts and
intuitions by
treating concepts as though they were intuitions. If in employing
the principles of understanding we do not merely apply our reason to
objects of
experience, but venture to extend these principles beyond the limits of
experience, there arise pseudo-rational doctrines which can
neither hope
for conformation in experience nor fear refutation by it.
Each of them is not only itself free from
contradiction, but finds conditions of its necessity in the very nature
of
reason - only that, unfortunately, the assertion of the opposite has,
on its
side, grounds that are just as valid and necessary. (B449) Let us look at
this argument is more detail. The argument works negatively, or
critically,
Kant would say, by showing that if we treat space and time as
properties of
objects, rather than our representations of objects, then we are
involved in
paradoxes that insolvable. These
paradoxes Kant calls the ‘antinomies of reason’. In
terms of the cosmological argument, there
are equally valid arguments, Kant hopes to demonstrate, for showing
that a necessary
being must exist as the first cause, but also that no absolutely
necessary
being is possible. This pair of
conclusions is contradictory. Kant
solves this antinomy not by demonstrating that both are false, but
there are
true of different objects: the object of reason, which might be called
an idea,
and the other the objects of the senses.
It might be true that the idea of causality implies an
unconditioned
cause, but this is not true of the objects of the senses.
The mistake comes when we try an imply an
idea of reason beyond the limits of experience.
Now the universe as a whole, or what Kant calls a
totality, cannot be an
object of experience, therefore the causality of nature cannot be
ascribed to
it, but this is precisely what the cosmological argument wants to do. What Kant is saying is that it is perfectly
possible to think the idea of the unconditioned cause, but this does
not mean
that there is any object in reality.
Such a notion of an unconditioned cause is dependant on a
complete series
of causes, but the concept of a complete causal series is an ideal for
reason
alone and not an object of knowledge, for an object of knowledge can
only be
something that is given, that is to say present both in terms of the
concepts
of the understanding and the forms of intuition, and an unconditioned
cause, by
definition can be neither. Such as idea
of completeness might be necessary to a system of knowledge, but it
does not
permit is to claim that there is an actual existence corresponding to
it, and
still less that this existence is a supreme person: Such transcendent
ideas have a purely intelligible object; and this object may indeed be
admitted
as a transcendental object, but only if we likewise admit that, for the
rest,
we have no knowledge in regard to it, and that it cannot be thought as
a
determinate thing in terms of distinctive inner predicates. As it is cut off from any reasons that could
establish the possibility of such an object, and have not the least
justification for assuming it. It is a
mere thought-entity. (B 593) Natural theology
treats God as though he were an empirical object subject to the
categories of
the understanding like other objects in the world, despite all the
speculative
and metaphysical colour of its language.
Thus, it denies in advance what it wants to set out to
prove. It is involved in trying to prove
what it
itself claim lies beyond experience by the rules of experience. The logical
disproof of the cosmological argument is slightly different. The form
of the
argument can be broken down to 6 steps as follows: 1.
Experience
tells us that things exist whose existence is
contingent 2.
Because
their existence is contingent there must be cause,
whether contingent or necessary, which brings them to be. 3.
If the cause
is contingent then it too must have a cause
that brings it into existence, and if this too is contingent, then it
too must
have a cause which is either contingent or necessary until arrive at a
cause
that must be necessary 4.
Such a
series cannot be endless otherwise what does exist
would not have a reason to exist at all. 5.
Therefore
there must be a first cause which is intrinsically
necessary 6.
What is
necessary must exist. The last step is an
ontological argument for Kant – it argues from a
logical necessity to a real necessity, which is invalid: The attempt to
establish the existence of a supreme being by means of the famous
ontological
argument of Descartes is therefore merely so much labour and effort
lost; we
can no more extend our stock of theoretical insight by mere ideas, than
a
merchant can better his position by adding a few noughts to his cash
account.
A602/B630. Thus, the critique of the
ontological argument is also a critique of the
conceptual form of the cosmological argument. What is important to
stress here
is that Kant is not claiming that we cannot know God, because God is
some
mysterious object or being beyond knowledge, for all objects are from
the very
beginning constituted by consciousness.
There could be no object on the other side of
consciousness. Rather he is asserting that
definitions about
what God is are nonsensical. They are a
misuse of language, rather than a failure of knowledge. We must accept
the
limitations of human knowledge in order to save reason from itself.
This
self-limitation of knowledge, however, should not lead to a crisis of
faith,
rather they should strengthen it by placing it on safer rational
grounds. This
new foundation for a rational faith, as we shall see next week, will be
morality and not science. |