Spinoza’s EthicsDr William LargeAncient philosophy, as Curley suggests, sought to understand the power of emotions through the division of the mind against itself, like Plato’s famous image of the chariot in the Phaedrus, where the irrational part of the mind fights against the rational part. Spinoza, on the contrary, like Descartes, wants to understand emotions through the action of the body on the mind. We have already seen in Part 2 that the human mind for Spinoza is only the idea of the body. We only have a limited understanding of what the body can do, and how it interacts with other bodies. Ethics, for Spinoza, is knowledge of our bodies. When we normally think about ethics, we think about some moral philosophy which would prescribe our actions in advance. This moral philosophy would be based on defended some kind of moral ideal that separates human beings from the rest of nature. Only human beings are capable of moral action, because only human beings can have moral ideas such as responsibility, freedom and duty. To be moral is not to follow one’s nature, but quite the opposite; it is to go against nature. For Spinoza, on the contrary, ethics is only possible by understanding our own nature. There is no fact/value distinction for Spinoza. What is good is what follows our nature, and nature is to be understood in terms of our desires or appetites. We do not desire something, as Spinoza writes in the scholium to proposition 9 in part 3, because we say it is good, rather we say something is good because we desire it: We neither strive for,
nor will, neither
want, nor desire anything because we judge it to be good; on the
contrary we
judge something to be good because we strive for it, will it, want it,
and
desire it. IIIP9S. Such a statement is precisely the opposite to any kind of idealistic morality which believes in the existence of moral ideas in advance that determines how we ought to act. There is no ‘ought’ for Spinoza if we imagine this to be the contrary to our desires, since what we are is our desires and nothing more. We have to see ourselves as part of nature and not a ‘dominion within a dominion’ and this is just the case within morality as it is with any other sphere of human activity. Again it is in Deleuze lectures on Spinoza that we might find the best explanation of the full scope of Spinoza’s ethics.[1] Why does Spinoza call his ontology an ethics? This is very peculiar, since we normally think of ethics and ontology being very different things. First of all we have to ask ourselves what is Spinoza’s ontology. It is the unique infinite substance which is being. This means that individual beings, singular things, including ourselves, are only modes of this one infinite substance. What does mode mean in Spinoza? Deleuze replies that we should understand the word ‘mode’ as meaning ‘a way of being’. So a tree is a way of being of substance, just as we are ‘a way of being’ of substance. He writes: ‘Et un mode c’est quoi? C’est une manière d’être. Les étants ou les existants ne sont pas des êtres, il n’y a comme être que la substance absolument infinie’ [And a mode what is that? It is a way of being. Beings or existents are not being; there is only being as an infinite absolute substance].[2] He adds that if we are to think of ethics in a Spinozist sense then we have to sharply distinguish it from morality. Ethics has to do with our ‘way of being’ as a mode of infinite substance. As a ‘way of being’, it is better to understand ethics in the same way that we understand ethnology; that is the study of human behaviour, in the same way that we study the behaviour of other animals. How is this different from a morality? Morality, Deleuze answers, has to do with knotting of two key concepts, essence and value. Morality indicates what our essence is through values. This has nothing to do with ontology, since values are meant to point beyond being (think of the idea of the Good in Plato, which is ‘beyond being’) – they indicate what being should be rather than what it is. The aim of every morality, he continues to explain, is the realisation of one’s essence. This means that one’s essence, is for the most part, not realised; that something is lacking or absent. Thus Aristotle, in book 1 of the Nicomachean Ethics, will define our essence to be eudemonia and the object of ethics is to reach this essence. The reason that we do not realise our essence is that we don’t act in a rational way, since we lack knowledge of what it means to go beyond our being in order to reach its moral realisation. This moral end, which allows us to reach our essence, what it means to be a human being, is supplied by our values. Thus we see how in morality essence and values are ultimately tied together. When we come to Spinoza’s ethics, Deleuze says, we have to stop thinking in terms of essence and value. An essence is not a general definition of something, like the definition of what it means to be a human being; rather essence always means a singular thing. As Deleuze says, there is an essence of this or that, but not of human beings in general. Another way of thinking of this change in the meaning of the word ‘essence’ is to say that what really interests Spinoza is existence not essence understood as a general term. For what is general is only the unique infinite substance, everything else is a mode, which is a determinate mode of infinite substance. Thus what truly differentiates one thing from another is existence not essence, since there is only one essence, strictly speaking, which is the infinite substance itself. An ethics, then, Deleuze argues, as opposed to a morality, is interested not in general abstractions, but the existence of singular things. But why is this different from morality? Deleuze gives a concrete example. With morality always the
following
operation ensues: you do something, you say something and you judge
yourself.
Morality has always to do with judgement and it is a double system of
judgement: you judge yourself and you are judged by someone else. Those
who
have a taste for morality always have a taste for judging themselves
and
others. To judge, Deleuze insists, is always to have a relation of
superiority
to being and it is value that expresses this superiority. But in ethics
something quite different happens. In ethics there is no judgement at
all,
however strange that might appear to be. Some says or does something.
You do
not refer this to a value which is superior to it; rather you say ‘how
is this
possible?’; that is to say, you only refer the statement or activity as
a way
of being in the same way that one might refer the activity of a lion
hunting a
gazelle – you don’t judge this has being bad or good in
relation to a
value that is superior to it. The question of ethics, then for Spinoza,
is not
is this good or bad, but ‘what am I capable of?’ Which really means,
‘what is
my body capable of?’ ‘Qu’est-ce
que tu dois en vertu de ton essence, c’est qu’est-ce que tu peux, toi,
en vertu
de ta puissance’ [what you must do in virtue
of your
essence, is what you are capable of, you yourself, in virtue of your
power].[3] The most important aspect of the existence of any singular thing is the desire to preserve its existence, which Spinoza calls conatus and defines as follows in IIIP6: ‘Each thing, as far as it can by its own power, strives to preserve in its being.’ This is not just a definition of human existence, but all existence as such, whether we are talking about a stone, a plant or even human beings. To the extent that nothing prevents it from existing, everything that does exist will strive to preserve itself in its existence. Thus, to use Curley’s example, if doing X preserves its existence, then it will desire to do X unless a more powerful external cause prevents it from doing so.[4] Spinoza’s argument for believing that this is case follows from his definition of essence. We tend to understand the meaning of essence, as we explained via Deleuze above, from Aristotle as the general definition of a thing which defines its nature in advance, but this is not how Spinoza understands ‘essence’. For him essence does not just define what something is, rather a good definition ought to be able to tells us how a thing is produced. Thus, if I want to properly define a circle what I have to be able to do is not just say what a circle is, but how a circle might be constructed. So again to use Curley’s example, the proper definition of a circle would be ‘a figure produced by the rotation of a line around a point’.[5] The essence of something tells me how it and why it exists, and also why it continues to exist. It is, so to speak, its power of existence. We can see why, therefore, conatus, the striving to continue to exist, would be the same as the essence of something and any activity that went against it could not be properly speaking an activity at all, but caused by some external cause, and therefore passive. How do we apply this conatus
doctrine to ethics? The answer is that everything which helps me to
preserve my
existence I take to be good and everything that goes against my
existence I
take to be bad. What is good is what is useful, relative to my
existence, and
what is bad, is what is dangerous, relatively speaking, to my continued
existence.
This striving is not only a striving for self-preservation, but also,
as we
shall see in the next lecture, an increase in the power of action,
since in
relation to the external causes that would extinguish my existence, all
I have
is my power to act. |