Mad
and Bad: Lewis, Psychosis and the Culture of
Psychiatry Alan Munton David
Trotter, Literary Experiment, Psychosis,
and the Professionalization of English Society (
Yet—and surely this is an
inconsistency?—Lewis understands madness as well, for the debate at the
end of The Childermass is ‘his attempt to
redeem it [the afterworld] from schizophrenia—to restore a measure of paranoid modernism’. (350) This
suggests that paranoia is normative; it
is certainly offered as preferable to schizophrenia.
Yet at other times Trotter writes as though
any kind of madness is deplorable, and there is a persistent sense that
his
modernists are not only mad, but bad as well. This
cannot follow, for illness is illness, and in itself
neither good
nor bad. If madness means badness, there
is probably be something wrong with the argument as a whole. The decision to use ‘paranoia’ and
‘schizophrenia’ as an antithetical pair in either/or structures, as in
the
example just given, rules out the combined term paranoid schizophrenia,
which
describes the form of mental illness most common in the psychiatric
discourse
that Trotter has chosen to work with. The
paranoia/schizophrenia bipole notably fails when it is
applied, in a
major instance, to a text by Lewis.
‘If we were to attach a psychosis to
these descriptions, it would be schizophrenia, rather than paranoia’,
Trotter
writes. (349) In the descriptions chosen
Lewis uses a neologism, a ‘lunge at meaning’ which resembles the
word-invention
present in schizophrenic patients, and this means Lewis is, in some
substantial
sense, schizophrenic. This is so because
‘Bleuler regarded neologism as an “accessory” symptom of schizophrenia’
(348) It was Eugen Bleuler (1857-1939)
who in 1908 first presented the world with the term schizophrenia,
meaning a
splitting of the mental functions; Trotter relies upon Bleuler’s
symptomatology
to argue that there is schizophrenia in The
Childermass.
Wandering abroad in the afterworld,
Satters undresses and runs naked towards
What Trotter perhaps does not know
is that Lewis was fond of searching out unusual words in dictionaries,
making
lists of them, and incorporating them into his fiction.
He has done that here. ‘Clop’
is to be found in the Oxford English Dictionary, and
if Lewis
did not find it there he could have drawn upon his knowledge of
colloquial
French, for ‘clop’ is related to clopiner;
indeed, clopiner vers, which is
current French, translates ‘cloppers up’. The
word means ‘to hobble’ and the example in OED
(‘rare’) is quite recent: ‘I took my stick and clopped away
down to the White Hart’ (1863). The
contemporary poet Tom Raworth also uses the word.[1] The phrase ‘Satters
cloppers up’ means that he hobbles towards
This interpretative blunder shows
how very difficult it is to substantiate the psychiatric reading of a
text. The general argument too is
suspiciously weak. Why so few examples? What psychosis would Trotter attach to Finnegans Wake, where dozens of
neologisms are to be found on every page? Joyce
would surely be diagnosed as utterly and
irretrievably insane, but Finnegans Wake, an
inescapable point
of reference, is nowhere mentioned. Joyce
is saved from a humiliating diagnosis because he has
become (in
Dennis Brown’s words) ‘the revered super-modernist’,[2]
critically untouchable and consequently untouched by madness.
I have been careful to specify that
the author of Paranoid Modernism is
attempting a psychiatric reading of modernism. That
emphasis is a fresh one in literary criticism, where
psychoanalysis
has been the preferred theory. The move
is potentially interesting, but faces great difficulties.
Freud worked within a rich and varied
intellectual culture which provided him with his interpretative terms
(Oedipus), or his objects of enquiry (Leonardo), or his mode of
argument, the
essay or short story. His texts are open
to reinterpretation precisely because they deal with neurosis rather
than
psychosis, for Freud wisely kept clear of the truly mad.
Neurosis occurs within culture, psychosis
ends up (at its worst, and all too often) in the hospital ward. Trotter’s attempt to find a cultural
application for psychiatry runs up against the difficulty that
psychosis is
recalcitrant to interpretation. Schizophrenics
often interpret the world idiosyncratically
and, at the
height of their illness at least, may endure a sharp reduction in the
ability
to relate to others or to express themselves either coherently or at
all. Loss of affect is one symptom of
schizophrenia, and patients may be reduced to a relationship circle of
nurses,
doctors and therapists, often in an institutional environment where
their
behaviour is stabilised by drugs. Psychoanalysis
works in a different world. ‘Dora’ first
contradicted Freud, and then
walked out on him, privileges of the merely neurotic.
A diagnosis of schizophrenia may have
consequences in law that can remove patients from participation in the
world at
large. (In Britain they may be
‘sectioned’ under Sections 2, 3, 4 or 5 of the 1983 Mental Health Act.) The mind ‘gone’, the body too may be removed
from culture. Trotter knows how serious
schizophrenia can be—‘schizophrenia is meltdown’ (41)—but does not
adjust his
argument according to the implications. Paranoia
and schizophrenia are serious mental illnesses
that distance
patients from the world in which they live. To
exploit the clinical context, to define authors and
characters in
fiction as schizophrenic, and then to argue that this is an entry into
culture
is to set oneself a very difficult task.
Psychiatry is a rapidly-changing
field which has been completely transformed by diagnostic and
therapeutic
practice and by drugs since Emil Kraepelin established the diagnosis dementia praecox in 1896, and Bleuler
definitively replaced it with schizophrenia in 1911 with the book later
translated as Dementia Praecox or the
Group of Schizophrenias. Trotter is
heavily dependent upon these precursor figures, and it is not at first
clear
why. He opens the book with a flourish
by referring to the contemporary reference manual for psychiatrists
known as DSM-IV, and this suggests he is going to
use up-to-date terminology. DSM-IV,
as he explains, is the fourth
edition of the Diagnostic and Statistical
Manual of Mental Disorders, published by the American Psychiatric
Association in 1994. Trotter
is
writing about modernism in In his first chapter
Trotter writes a history of paranoia in which he
insists upon the urgency of differential diagnosis.
This allows him to separate paranoia from
schizophrenia and then attempt the move into culture.
Schizophrenics live in a world where every
action appears contingent because they are cut off from meaning and
value as a
result of what Kraepelin called ‘the loss of the inner
unity of the activities of intellect, emotion, and
volition in themselves and among one another’ (quoted 38).
But schizophrenics copy or imitate, Trotter
argues. They imitate sounds or
movements—this
is known as echolalia and echopraxis—and are thus engaged in mimesis. Mimesis is a key term for this argument,
where literary modernism is said to object to mimesis and therefore be
attached
to paranoia. Paranoiacs ‘cannot abide
contingency’ (38) and construct highly meaningful but delusional
structures
where everything that happens to them can be interpreted as caused by
(say) the
intervention of neighbours, or the actions of a distant lover. Here, Trotter takes Kraepelin very seriously,
so much so that he makes him sound like a contemporary literary
theorist: ‘To
imitate for imitation’s sake, Kraepelin thought, was to abandon any
notion of
meaning and value, of purposefulness, of inner psychic unity’. Against this, ‘writers from John Stuart Mill
to Wyndham Lewis’ would ‘fulminate’ against mimesis, in the process
‘constituting
an anti-mimetic paranoid postliberalism’. (40) This
is a very strange argument, not least because, as we
have seen, one
of Trotter’s main points about Lewis is that he or his texts are
‘schizophrenic’. Setting that aside
for a moment, let us turn to ICD-10.
Here we find a
sub-section entitled ‘Paranoid schizophrenia’ which begins with the
unequivocal
statement ‘This is the commonest type of schizophrenia in most parts of
the
world’. Patients suffer ‘relatively
stable, often paranoid, delusions, usually accompanied by
hallucinations’;
these are often auditory—‘hearing voices’, in other words. (89) The usual delusions may be present, and
threatening voices may be heard, or whistling, humming or laughing. Hallucinations of smell or taste may occur. DSM-IV
has a comparable section, a sub-type of Schizophrenia marked ‘Paranoid
Type’,
where the description is similar but lacks the emphasis on its being
the most
common type. If we bring these features
together, Trotter’s argument seems to be endangered.
Paranoid schizophrenia is a) the most common
type, and b) a sub-type of schizophrenia. Paranoia
has turned up on the wrong side, as it were. Paranoid
schizophrenia mixes inescapably the
two terms that Trotter must keep separate if he is to situate
psychiatry within
culture—so he ignores paranoid schizophrenia as a possible diagnosis of
modernism. Such rigid separation
of terms ignores the widely-accepted view in
psychiatric practice today, that the symptoms of mental illness occur
along a
continuum. There are no sharp
distinctions to be made in diagnosis, and symptoms of different kinds
come and
go; they may occur seriously, or as mild afflictions, or disappear
altogether. This view of mental illness
is not susceptible to an either/or interpretation, and at one point
Trotter
acknowledges that paranoia ‘also occur[s]’ in schizophrenia, but then
adds that
‘since Kraepelin’ the diagnosis of paranoia has been ‘to some degree’
(19)
differential, which gets him back on the two-way street separating
paranoia
from schizophrenia that allows him to pursue his cultural argument
about
mimesis being ‘schizophrenic’ and anti-mimesis ‘paranoid’. Just how reliable
were Kraepelin and Bleuler? Because his
approach is historical, Trotter
must take them both seriously: ‘They set up a durable
psychopathological
tradition’ he writes. (50) He needs the
1896 term ‘dementia praecox’, and describes effects which occur earlier
in
life, and for different reasons, than the dementia of old age. Trotter returns to Kraepelin’s emphasis, in
the seventh edition of the German-language Psychiatrie,
of ‘the “loss of inner unity” as the main cause of the disease’. (32) This is useful because the
unity/fragmentation dichotomy is already common in the study of
modernism. It is also vague, for ‘loss of
inner unity’
could be a symptom as much as a cause. Trotter
stresses that dementia
praecox is (or was) ‘a totalizing disorder’, distinct from paranoia. The ‘quantitative and clinically orientated
account’ offered in English as Dementia
Praecox and Paraphrenia in 1919, ‘put a new landmark on the map of
mental
illnesses [showing] profound disturbance of thought and language’. (33) One notices that Trotter is an extremist in
diagnosis: every mental illness is a serious illness, as indeed each
has to be
if cumulatively they are to have an effect upon the wider culture. Trotter disrespects the modernists—Mill and
Lewis ‘fulminate’—but is oddly respectful of Bleuler, whose absurd
belief that
schizophrenia was the result of an unknown toxin is reported without
comment. The arguments of Paranoid
Modernism are based upon an
acceptance of the scientific value of the diagnoses of Kraepelin and
Bleuler. But what is the
scientific value of these concepts? Very
little, according to Mary Boyle, who in Schizophrenia: a
scientific delusion?
(1990) argues rigorously and convincingly that the methodologies of the
two
researchers do not demonstrate the criteria necessary for the construct
‘schizophrenia’ to be considered scientific.[5] (She does not deny the existence of bizarre
behaviour or the suffering arising from it.) Boyle
shows that one reason Kraepelin’s Psychiatrie
expanded so much between early and later editions was
that he was including among the symptoms for schizophrenia the symptoms
of
other illnesses, notably encephalitis
lethargica (an affliction movingly described in Oliver Sack’s Awakenings in 1980). As to
Bleuler, who took for granted the
unproven ‘dementia praecox’ theory, ‘his work was at best misconceived
and at
worst futile’, Boyle writes. (60) Of
Kraepelin she writes that it is ‘surprising’ that his work ‘is given
serious
consideration by his successors...and is subjected to only mild
criticism by
modern writers’. (59) Research in the
1980s showed that ‘the kind of “severe and long-standing cases”
described by
Kraepelin and Bleuler are no longer seen’, and certain symptoms they
described
‘are now rare’. (65) Boyle concludes
that Kraepelin and Bleuler were investigating patient ‘populations’ to
whom the
term schizophrenia would today not be applied. (65)
Quantitative and clinically oriented his
research may have been, but it is of little or no value for diagnosis
or
treatment today. Yet, as we have seen,
Bleuler’s distinction between ‘fundamental’ and
‘accessory’ symptoms is used by Trotter to support an argument about a
moment
in Lewis’s The Childermass, where we
recall that neologism is an accessory symptom of schizophrenia. Boyle argues that the hundreds of behaviours
Bleuler put forward as accessory symptoms lacked scientific criteria
for their
inclusion, and were in fact arbitrarily chosen. Sometimes,
she writes, ‘accessory symptoms were said to
cause
fundamental symptoms’. (62) These criticisms
ought not to affect Trotter’s historically-based
argument, but here another peculiarity arises. He
concedes early on that the modernist writers did not
read the
writings of the psychiatrists of their own time (‘Obviously not’). But there was an ‘endemic’ (5) problem which
resolved itself in the belief that the professional classes were
particularly
prone to paranoia, and this leads Trotter to an argument I shall
address a
little later. Struggling, perhaps, to
find a definitive link between literature and madness, he concedes that
not all
modernists suffered from Paranoid
Modernism, but makes the following revealing remark, quoted here
with my
emphasis: I have on occasion
sought to extend the terms of my argument by
discerning ‘schizophrenia’, as that would
have been understood during the early years of the twentieth century,
in
the behaviour represented by my chosen writers, or even in their
literary
methods. (12) This
seems to mean that writers could only be mad in ways defined in the
psychiatric
literature of the time at which they were being mad.
My reading of this book was for many chapters
troubled by the possibility that its author really held this view. On page 350 the suggestion returns: I do not in fact
believe that one ought to ascribe a condition like
‘schizophrenia’ to specific literary procedures without knowing how it
was used
by psychiatrists and social commentators at the time.
This it should not prove impossible to
establish. [W.R.] Bion’s thinking, for
example, was as decisively shaped by the First World War as Lewis’s. This
sentence begins as though it was about to deny the astonishing
assertion that
it does in fact make, that mental illness can only enter a literary
text in
ways consistent with the definitions then current in the psychiatric
literature. It is not a primary objection
to this formulation that the authors concerned had ‘obviously not’ read
that
literature. The difficulty lies in the
assumption that such a research project could work.
Kraepelin, caught in a time-sequence imposed
by the ‘praecox’ concept, wrote of the onset, progress and outcome of
the
illness. Are Lewis and the other
paranoid modernists to be tracked across their entire careers under
this
procedure—one that was criticised from the outset, is not used today,
and which
Trotter does not mention, although it was put forward just as early
modernism
was getting under weigh? What would
count as evidence that the behaviours Bleuler said were attributes of
schizophrenia, were also in some strong sense occurring in modernist
texts? The relationship would have to be
strong
because there is otherwise an easy answer to the question: Bleuler
listed so
many attributes of schizophrenia—hundreds of accessory symptoms
alone—that
there would be no difficulty in finding something or other that fitted
a text
or an author. Given that most of these
behaviours would not today count as attributes of schizophrenia, would
it not
then be necessary to say that any link established was provisional? And what would be the lasting value of that? We might consider other, slightly comical,
difficulties. Paranoia goes back only
200 years. Macbeth was notably
non-paranoid about the witches’ warnings about Birnam Wood making its
way to
Dunsinane. Is that because there was no
psychiatric profession in Elizabethan England? What
then of The Winter’s Tale,
where Leontes’ delusions about his wife are clearly paranoid? Let us look at
Trotter’s examples of his preferred state of madness,
paranoia. Early in the book, ‘monomania’
is endorsed. This mid-nineteenth century
term shows up later in the discussion of Tarr. Kreisler, of course, is the paranoiac (235),
but Tarr is the monomaniac (238), which comes as a surprise because
Trotter
does not quote the word as occurring in the novel, although we are told
earlier
that its legitimacy depends upon its use
in nineteenth- and early twentieth-century fiction, which was
apparently
‘consistent’. (18) Monomania means—if it
means anything at all—an undue focus upon a single object, and it must
therefore belong to paranoia, not to schizophrenia, and this is
confirmed by
Trotter’s surrounding discussion of delusions of grandeur. (20-21) It is therefore difficult to make much of
this sentence about Tarr: ‘Tarr, oddly enough, given his tendency to
monomania,
may in fact be the first schizophrenic in English literature’. That is inconsistent, but so is the next
sentence: In the account it
gives of ‘persecution mania’ and of the need to
eliminate mess from art, Tarr can be
considered Modernism’s closest approximation, Women in
Love apart, to paranoid narrative. (238) Well,
which is it to be, schizophrenic or paranoid? These
concepts keep popping about like a handful of
Mexican jumping
beans. The answer, one increasingly
feels, is neither. This theory does not
work. Even its originator cannot control
the terms he has chosen to use.
A major theme in Paranoid Modernism is
the new idea of
paranoid professionalism. The argument
is that during the mid- and late-nineteenth century British society
became
professionalized, that specialized groups had to defend their
interests, and
that paranoia ‘helped’. (83) These
professions sold an ‘expertise’ which made up their cultural capital. Clergymen, lawyers and doctors were the first
professionals, and writers and artists were close behind.
Expertise was crucial to Modernism, and
Lewis’s professionalism was to advocate abstraction in art. In the early modern period, as professional
identity grew, writers spent time becoming paranoid about their
aspirations and
careers. But if clergymen belong to the
Church of England, lawyers to the Law Society and doctors to the
British
Medical Association, to which professional association do a group of
disorganised and often badly paid artists and writers belong? Lewis was briefly a lecturer in
This conclusion again suggests some
fault in the argument. Snooty is a
psychopath, therefore Lewis is a
fascist. But Snooty is Lewis’s creation,
and a satire on Behaviourism, which is a pernicious scientific theory
perpetrated by American psychology. Lewis
objected that it reduced people to automatons, but
for saying so
he is found to be a fascist. It’s not
probable. One may think of other
consequences of professionalization: doctors who kill the terminally
ill,
archbishops who declare just wars, barristers who successfully defend
guilty
criminals, judges whose wrong convictions are unravelled years later. I see a difference of scale and of impact
here between real-world professionals and professionals of word and
image. Trotter is a professional of the
latter kind,
as am I. Unlike him, I do not want to
judge the forces of understanding and resistance by the values of
capital and
control.
Paranoid
Modernism is founded on the assumption that a literary critic can
make a
medical diagnosis of a text or a person. When
Paul Edwards asserts that Lewis’s polemics are ‘a
permanent insight
into the nature of modernity’ (quoted 289), Trotter replies that those
polemics
are ‘mildly psychotic’. (289) These are
different kinds of statements, and they
do not match. An intervention into
culture is not answered by saying ‘You’re mad!’ Apart
from my doubts as to Trotter’s interpretation of the
history of
mental illness, and the failure of his attempt to tie the concept of
paranoid
professionalism to the rest of his argument, and hence to ‘culturalize’
psychiatry, there is a distinct problem with his attitude to mental
illness
itself. He sometimes seems to think it’s
funny—paranoia was ‘the professional person’s madness of choice’
(7)—and at
other time treats it with a melodramatic intensity intended to enforce
its
significance for culture. Both attitudes
falsify. Paranoia and schizophrenia are
intensely distressing medical conditions that belong, and should
remain, in the
world of the clinic. The effort to
demedicalise mental illness damages the interests of the mentally ill
by
elevating schizophrenia into something supposedly special, and (as in
this
book) finding paranoia everywhere and cheapening the distress it causes. At the same time, Trotter’s diagnostic
extremism prevents him from acknowledging how widespread and manageable
are the
mild and controllable forms of both illnesses. Certainly,
his book lies within culture, but not quite
where he would
wish, I suspect. It is a contribution to
the insensitive culture that attaches blame and guilt to the concept of
mental
illness. NOTES 1. ‘What
You Got?’ begins ‘The far-off cattle seem to
clop’. See Tom Raworth, Tottering
State: Selected Poems 1963-1987 (London:
Paladin, 1988), p. 102. 2. Dennis
Brown, ‘James Joyce’s Fable of the Ondt and the
Gracehoper: “Othering”, Critical Leader-Worship and Scapegoating’, Wyndham Lewis Annual VII (2001), p. 37. 3. The
ICD-10 Classification of Mental and Behavioural Disorders: Descriptions
and
Diagnostic Guidelines (Geneva: World Health Organization, 1992). 4. DSM-IV:
Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders, Fourth Edition
(Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Association, 1994), p. 301. 5. Mary Boyle, Schizophrenia: a scientific
delusion? (London: Routledge, 1990). This
review appeared in the Wyndham Lewis
Annual VIII (2001), published 2002. |