Notes on Barad Book Chapters
Dave Harris
Very quick summaries of these, focussing on
implication for /from the 2007 book --highlighted
in bold.
Dave Harris
Barad K ( 2000) Reconceiving
Scientific Literacy as Agential LIteracy . On
Doing Science and Culture Eds. R Reid and
S Traweek. London: Routledge
Same old same
old, only early Only new thing is 'agential
realism' here means getting experiments to work.
She devised an ug course for science and
non-science students to get them to abductively
engage with classic experiments and they liked it. I like it myself!
Barad K (2001). Reconfiguring
Space, Time and Matter. In Feminist Locations
Global and Local, Theory and Practice,
edited by M Dekoven. London: Rutgers University
Press.
[I'm gonna gloss about yet another restatement of
agential realism, even though it has even more
extreme fomulaiton confusions and
circularities, and focus on the commentaries
on Fernandes which top and tail that
discussion. And the political implications
for feminism toabandon theold fixed notions of
identity politics or intersection. It's a bit
fuller and more ambitious than the discussion in
Barad 2007 in my view,becasue it is placed in this
extensive framework]
the piece starts by arguing how modern transport
and electronic communication produce 'an ambiguity
of scale that defies geometrical analysis' (75).
We should think of changing topologies instead of
a fixed Euclidean geometry, a pattern between
zeros and ones, a flow of capital which changes
material conditions globally, a 'cyborg
"trans-action"' that weakens boundaries.
Feminism has long insisted on a view from
somewhere, although some of it still operates with
'a Euclidean geometric imaginary' (76), spaces the
container, with easily mapped coordinates which
identify position, and with time as a matter of
evenly spaced increments. Soja has challenge this
as ignoring the inextricable connection between
time space and matter, providing space with '"an
aura of objectivity, inevitability, and
reification"'. Thinking of new conceptions of
space helps replace a politics of location with a
politics of possibilities. Foundational ideas of
location are challenged, and indeterminacy and
ambiguity 'coexist with causality' in a space of
possibilities. This will allow for 'normative
analyses crucial to critical political practices'.
It will be agential realism which cuts
across many old binary oppositions and reformulate
agency as something productive and exclusionary.
It is better than performative with the theory
because it takes account of discursive and
material elements of practice, this helps us
incorporate material constraints and dimensions
'into poststructuralist analyses' (77).
Materiality is not just a consequence of
discursive practices, but something active and
productive in its own right. See it that way will
help us better understand how discourses have
material consequences, and how relationships
between them can work both ways. The split itself
shows something about 'our current material and
discursive conditions'. Culture's theories can
provide crucial insights, but are inadequate in
terms of explanations, especially how things like
economic forces can re-form subjectivities.
Hence Fernandes, seen as 'theorisation of the
relationship between structural and discursive
forces' (77). In particular, it shows how
poststructuralism doesn't just oppose Marxism but
can help elaborate limited forms of structural
analysis by seeing class as a dynamic variable
with 'integral cultural ideological and discursive
dimensions' [nearly epic]. We can see how economic
capital materialises, and how cultural economies
have a material aspect. We are going to work
Fernandez and agential realism 'through another to
get a deeper understanding of structures
materiality and their relation to discourses,
especially the dynamics of power relations. This
will help us add new tools to feminism.
Political economy and cultural identity are
inseparable and Fernandez provides strong
empirical support. She uses tools from
poststructuralist and Marxist schools [Foucault
and Stuart Hall?], using both to understand the
multiple technologies of the production of the
working class. In particular, class structure is
not seen as uniform objective or pure compared to
other identities which are merely symbolic or
ideological forces. The different identities are
connected in a dynamic process revealed in
everyday life of the workers, and featuring
'ongoing contests over space, time, and movement'.
Barad calls this the 'iterative production of…
spatiality' and a matter of the 'dynamics of
structural relations'. Thus workers are positioned
on the factory floor through gendered recruitment,
gendered divisions of labour, the whole gendering
of space, so that '"gender in community are
integral to class 'structure'"'. Classes are
dynamic and contested, the result of local
politics.
This is not saying that classes just something
ideological or cultural. Fernandez argues that we
cannot see economic categories as material and
other social categories not, or indeed that the
categories are separable, or only interact [not
intra-act?]. For her, class is still about
economic capital, but the economic is not just
about class, but also gender in community. This
means that class will not be experienced equally
by all workers all over the world. In particular,
gender is a structural force not just a discursive
one. Capitalist machinery is both material and
discursive, and they produce by combining
different forms, they 'literally work through one
another' (79). The forces may be unevenly
distributed, but it is this that enables
'different potentials and performances' by the
various components.
It is an extension of Foucault on disciplinary
regimes that structure time space and movement,
understood as the codification of power, embodied
in factory codification of time movement in space.
Thus factory discipline organises space [actually
an 'analytical space'], complete with its material
borders, including those between class, gender and
community. However, they do this rather than
produce individual subjects, but this should not
be seen as a rejection of structural relations, a
focus only on the micro physics of power. Instead,
she wants to rethink the structural dynamics of
power, so that structure is not anything objective
or transcendental, but is '"shaped by modes of
representation and meaning that social actors…
Give to their positions and activities"'. So
structures are also produced.
But in what sense? How do the material and the
discursive dimensions relate? Agential realism
will explain [by transforming the description so
that the shop floor is understood as the
production of meanings bodies and material –
discursive boundaries]. However, apparatuses have
to be themselves produced through '"iterative
interactivity"' and we will have to radically
rethink causality and exclusions, and notions of
space time at and agency. In particular agency
will refer to the potential to change to
apologies, reconfigure structural relations, raise
accountability issues of matters such as boundary
articulations and exclusions [but how does this
turn into politics?]. It brings in nonhuman
beings, 'nonhuman and cyborg Ian forms of agency'
(81).
First we need to think about how machines work and
how they relate to humans. A particular historian
of science, one N. Wise, suggest that industrial
machines 'mediate societal values in the
production of knowledge'. A steam engine gives us
both labour value, a concept in political economy,
and work, a concept in engineering mechanics. This
apparently leads to a whole structural analogy
between a network of concepts between the two
disciplines. [The example I don't understand —
before industrialisation, Kelvin was able to see
agency as some natural quality? Barad seems to
want to go back to that?]. We want to retain this
link between productive apparatuses social and
cultural values, political economy and human and
nonhuman forms of agency, but we cannot accept the
idea of a mediating role.
We need yet another radical shift. Both Kelvin and
Marx had Newtonian conceptions of force and
causality, but that has been dissipated by
quantum. Bora played a key part [then off we go]
bore this time questions assumptions of
observation independent objects with well defined
intrinsic properties, and continuous measurement
independent of those objects. Instead 'theoretical
concepts are defined by the circumstances required
for their measurement'(82). This is a 'fact'
supported by 'an empirically verifiable
discontinuity in measurement interactions' this
shows there is no inherent cut between object and
agencies of observation.
Board draws upon quantum wholeness instead and
uses the term phenomenon to designate 'particular
instances of wholeness'. In particular, we must
consider the interaction between object and
apparatus as an inseparable part of the
phenomenon. We should also offer '"a description
of all relevant features of the experimental
arrangement"'. This has epistemological
consequences. Concepts refer to a particular
apparatus which implies a cut between object and
observation [the example is given of the apparatus
to distinguish location from momentum]. The
implication for observation is that we should be
able to state the conditions necessary for the
reproduction of the phenomenon '"in an unambiguous
way"' (83), implying that the experimenter cuts
between objects and agencies of observation,
because there is no inherent distinction. It
follows that ambiguities are resolved 'only for a
given context', a particular instance of
wholeness, a phenomenon. However, we can still
attain objectivity in a reformulated form —
permanent marks, produced in an apparatus,
involving bodies.
Properties cannot be attributed to objects or to
measuring instruments, but must be referred to
phenomena. Interaction also means the
inseparability of objects and observations. We
have to revise strict causality and determinism as
well as the nature of reality. This does not
produce disorder or a rejection of causality, but
a reworking, something 'between the usual
dualistic thinking about causality — freedom and
determinism' (85). It explains contradictory
evidence like wave and particle experiments, by
seeing wave and particle as descriptive concepts
located in classical understandings but which
refer actually to 'different mutually exclusive
phenomena', so we can hold both wave and particle
explanations simultaneously. The key is a
re-conceptualisation of referential reality to
shift it from an independent object to a
phenomenon. Only then can we gain objective
knowledge in boards sense.
Apparatuses are not passive instruments but are
productive. Nevertheless, Bora needs a better
account. Apparatuses are specific to observational
practices, but this leaves the boundary problem,
which might include 'the scientific community that
judges the value of the research' (86). We also
depends on unambiguous communication implying some
scientific body. We have to acknowledge these
complexities too when we think of an apparatus.
Barad says she does this in the getting real
piece, incorporating Foucault and Butler. Thus
Foucault's notion of an apparatus can be combined
with Bohr's to bring in the production of
subjectivation as a dimension of power. But there
is gender performatiity in subject formation can
be seen as a form of materialisation. However,
both leave I theorise the materiality of nonhuman
beings. Foucault does not examine the materiality
of the prison, for example [I thought he did].
Butler sees performative to exclusively as a
matter of discursive citation, without looking at
'the material constraints and exclusions and the
material dimensions of agency' (87). It's hard to
see materiality just as an effect of power [later
on, she wants to see it as an effect of agency].
An exclusive focus on discourse dilutes the
notion. It as a spatial dimension as well as a
temporal one.
If we see phenomena in terms of constituting
agential reality, this is an elaboration an
extension of bore, from observation instruments to
a broader idea of apparatuses. Phenomenon needs to
be broadened as well and can now be defined as
something produced through interactions by
material – discursive apparatuses. The apparatuses
are not just observing instruments. Agential
reality is not a fixed ontology waiting for
epistemic enlightenment but is itself 'segmented
out of the process of making the world
intelligible through certain practices and not
others' [very confusing in my view, it's a better
concept because she has a better more enlightened
epistemology?]. We are responsible for this
knowledge and 'in part, for what exists' [since we
developed powerful technology at least?]. Notions
of realism and truth need no longer be based on
representationalism. We can get accurate
descriptions of agential reality. The iterative
processes of materialisation display a difference
in the efficacy of practices as partners [so
saying something will not cause it to materialise,
and some accounts are more 'empirically adequate'
than others].
Matter is not a blank slate nor an uncontested
grounds, not citation à la tea, not a support for
discourses, but rather pattern of interactivity
that both stabilises and destabilises. Materiality
is not an inherent fixed property of objects.
Materialisation should be the focus. Empiricists
are still Newtonian's, even if they do disagree
with others about how important language is, or
other social. The point is that materiality is not
nonbeing outside of the real, and we can still
make reference to material constraints and
inclusions and 'the material dimensions of power'
in agential realism. We do not need to naturalise
matter because materiality has to be referred to
agential reality.
It helps us to re-examine how the boundaries of
human and nonhuman are drawn. This always happens
in particular materialisation is, but these should
not be limited to human forms. We can better
understand power knowledge practices and the
production of bodies if we think about materiality
beyond the realm of the human. Apparatuses have a
physical presence. We can better understand how
they produce particular bodies, as materialising
them, a necessary part of regulatory apparatuses.
This is what she means by looking at 'how matter
comes to matter'. Material – discursive bodies
'are segmented out of the interaction of multiple
material – discursive apparatuses' and it is
through these apparatuses that 'phenomena (bodies)
become intelligible' [still equally well explained
by abduction dialectic or chiasm, recognising the
dynamics of matter and knowledge of course].
,
[So, I think the whole point here is to underpin
Fernandez with an ontologyclaiming that this will
make her more powerful, that she will be able to
explain more things. But what exactly? More
possible dynamic interactions — but she has
already pinned down those that matter in that
specific context. Why do we need a general
philosophy?] Back to it
We have to remember apparatuses are also phenomena
made up of specific interactions between humans
and nonhumans, although the boundaries are
constituted through practices [but who initiate
practices?]. Any apparatus 'is always in the
process of interacting with other apparatuses'
explaining the enfolding of phenomena in
iterations, and producing important shifts in
apparatus. Another example of the process of
materialisation. 'Apparatuses do not simply change
in time, they materialise through time and space'
(90) [more philosophical excess].
This can help us explain power dynamics, but this
is often still Newtonian, implying that the values
of variables change over time as an effect, with
an objective time as an external parameter.
However interactions are 'causally constrained but
nondeterministic irreversible enactments' which
sediment out matter, so that it can become an
ingredient in further materialisation is of
bodies. It does not take place in conventional
space or time, since these are also produced and
reconfigured. Certain exclusions produce
'conditions of possibility of new
possibilities'[so this is what allegedly is
gained, even more flexibility, this time to alter
space and time as well, and to trace even more
connections between apparatuses. Vertigo awaits].
Materiality is itself a factor in [further]
materialisation and iterative enfolding is.
Temporality is produced 'just as rings of trees
mark their segmented history of their interactions
within the world' — hardly a production of
temporality, though, more a measure of it. Matter
is segmented history of practices. 'Time has a
history' (91) [made to look very mysterious] so it
can't be just an external parameter. Properties
themselves are 'redefined through time' [no
argument with that, but daft to conclude that]
'temporality is constituted through iterative
intra-actions' [yes, but why would we use tree
rings when we have perfectly adequate metric
instruments].
Both Butler and bore focus on exclusions as a
crucial part of intelligibility. Butler's abject
of people are not yet subjects but are some sort
of formative outside, something unlivable peopled
by non-subjects, which help to define the rest of
us as subjects. This is the same as Barad arguing
that material discursive practices draw
boundaries, like the ones between interior and
exterior, intelligible from unintelligible. But we
do not see these as inherent, simply something
provided by exclusions, which never fully resolve
indeterminacy and lead to new possibilities.
Agential cuts are not independent, existing and
abstract space although 'they are indeed material'
[supported by citing bore saying that descriptive
concepts require particular material circumstances
for their very definition]. Space is not some
container. Speciality is a process of
restructuring, drawing new boundaries, making
exclusions, and this is crucial in
materialisation. Especially, the boundaries
between interior and exterior are changed and that
reconfigures space.
The example is the way in which position and
trajectory are no longer fixed values but are seen
are products of the dynamics, where particular
material conditions make concepts meaningful and
intelligible [and the other term unintelligible].
Newton assumed that you could specify
deterministic trajectories and causalities, but we
now know that position is contingent, and that
position and momentum are mutually exclusive [in
the quantum world it is necessary to keep
repeating].
For Stengers, this is a full recognition of
the productivity of time which is not just a
parameter negating becoming of natural beings [and
then a puzzling bit about we need an explanation
that reduces the diverse to the identical, the
changing to the permanent and '"as a result
eliminates time"' (92). But agential realism does
not eliminate time or demote it, but sees it as a
matter of space time, produced by iterative
intra-activity, space-time. Manifolds are
iteratively reconfigured, through enfolding,
changes in the internal connectivity as well as by
changes in shape or size, which widens the space
of possibilities 'entailed in exclusions'. We now
have a topology where interior, exterior, past and
future are 'iteratively unfolded and will you
worked, but never eliminated'.
Causality is not a matter of strict determinism,
but produced as a possibility [?] by exclusions
and particular boundaries. These exclusions also
open the future to possibility. Apparatuses
constrain but do not determine, so traditional
causality is reformulated to mean a space for
agency [pretty unconvincing, theoretical juggling
leading to better politics?]. We must recognise
human, nonhuman and cyborg Ian agency, not least
in realising that 'the world "kicks back"'. The
human itself is redefined by apparatuses remaking
boundaries, and again this widens possibilities
and helps us see better dimensions in the working
of power.
Back to Fernandez thank God, and the role of
machines. Structural relations of power are
reproduced and contested in the jute mill. Spatial
positioning is a marker of class. And an example
of the wider material practices and constraints.
These constraints are not obstacles, nor the
independent of discursive practices, nor reducible
to them. Instead, we can see Fernandez is offering
'contingent materialisation of the shop floor'
(94). The space of the jute mill is produced, as
are the workers as disciplined subjects. 'But the
spatiality of capitalism is itself produced
through the politics of gender, community, and
class and daily contests over the relations of
power' [if we take the jute mill to be somehow
typical]. Fernandez shows how the reproduction of
gender relations, for example arises from an array
of local practices and discourses that also
maintain 'the national hegemonic construction of
class' (95) nor is it a matter of just releasing
pre-existing ideologies, because gender is
constantly manufactured through specific local
notions of masculinity and femininity. These also
reinforce management power and weaken union
activity. This shows how exclusionary practices by
managers and workers create the spatiality of
capitalism. Just as the mill materialises capital,
so exclusionary practices materialise the mill.
There is no linear additive dynamics. The ones
that exist should be understood as 'part of the
technologies of capitalism'. In this way, local
practices reconfigure and enfold structural
relations, seen as apparatuses, but also
maintained or produced by various exclusions. We
can see the whole jute mill as an apparatus of
bodily production, materialising through
interactions 'among workers, management, machines
and other materials and beings'. Materiality is
not once and for all but something contingent and
contested, constrained but not determining, a
process whereby some practices come to matter, not
'mere brute positivity or some purified notion of
the economic'
The economic is no more material than the others
factors. We have to see production as 'iterative
intra-activity' (96) producing commodities and
also subjects and structures. It does not involve
the repetition of some fixed process, but is
constantly reworked by various forms of agency,
including nonhuman. This is what we see when a
machine refuses to work, it means lost wages, a
struggle between weavers and mechanics,
intervention of management, union responses, a
strike, a new configuration of machines and
workers on the shop floor. Boundaries and
divisions between various social categories also
affect these actions, such as wildcat strikes
being cross cut by cast positions.
If we see apparatuses themselves as phenomena, we
can redevelop the analogy of a gear assemblage
with uneven forces different potentials and
performances, but it has to be thought to be
reconfigured while itself it produces others, some
new gears are produced or re-milled, some are
enfolded into the assemblage. Processes of
inclusion and exclusion reworked the boundaries.
[Most puzzling of all 'the accumulating marks of
time do not correspond to the history of any
individual gear, but rather are integrally tied to
the genealogy of the assemblage and its changing
topology' — we can chart the changes in machines
in terms of different configurations]. This might
be too mechanistic, but it highlights some limits
of common conceptions of production, which often
focus either on the human dimension, usually what
happens in the economy, or on material cultures
which invariably split humans and nonhuman is. We
have to understand dynamics much more fully as a
general reworking of the nature of production,
something non-linear, causal and nondeterministic,
enfolding, changing to apologies and boundaries
between interior and exterior, seen as agential
processes reproducing apparatuses. These are not
aalthuserian apparatuses which are 'rigidly fired
and separable formations of power' operating
outside.
We don't get to understand them through Euclidean
geometry. We need to see it as 'a topological
animal'. For example, if we take intersection
analogy in feminism, colour helps displace
hegemonic discourses that just stressed gender.
Even some intersectional lists still had a
'Euclidean eyes Asian pathology' (98), because of
a reservation about questions of race and how it
might be misappropriated. The result was some
Euclidean geometry with sets of axes of
identification positioning marked bodies [as on a
graph]. This still produces limits in seeing
gender race & are separate characteristics of
individual human beings, that taxes of identity
are at right angles to each other and are
independent, that intersection goes on in marked
bodies, not just in specific ones [gender affect
women], that multiple identity is just one of
these Euclidean intersections.
Instead, we have to see identities is not
separable so they can't interact. There produced
by topological dynamics of intra-activity. Some
constrain, some enable various apparatuses of
bodily production. They are a contingent material
process, thus constantly open to contestation. We
should study them as genealogies of topologies
[different structural relations of power which
have materialised]. This is what Fernandez shows
us in the multiple dimensions of the union
management conflict, how class is contingent, only
sometimes connected caste hierarchies after a
specifically political process, how caste is
itself produced through hegemony and resistance,
narratives of class and gender. All these
identities materialise through and are enfolded
into one another. They'll constrain and enable but
not determining. They are in interaction with
other apparatuses of bodily production. Together
they make up 'the changing topology of the
space-time manifold'and show the need for
responsibility and accountability [so shifting to
this absurdly general ontology somehow leads to
union and workforce sitting down and discussing
their mutual responsibilities?].
The shop floor is not neutral, not Euclidean.
Workers do not have fixed trajectories. Position
itself is contingent and contested, just as a
worker is not a property of individual human
beings but something contested and disunified
['but nonetheless objective' (100)]. Referring to
specific phenomena, subjects in interaction.
Workers are not just pawns on a Euclidean
chessboard. Capitalism itself is contested and
ever-changing in its attempt to spatialise.
Class is therefore the result of a dynamic,
particular 'material discursive practices' that
locally define categories including gender and
community. Thus the overall category can have
status differences. It can appear as an habitus in
reproducing patterns. It is affected by
materialising relations including economic
structures, but enfolded into gender and
community. This might be a kind of discursive
production, but this is not to deny materiality.
Material conditions matter not just because they
support discourses but because both discourses and
matter comes to matter through materialisation.
They are intertwined, enfolded. We can't determine
any individual effects of material or discursive
factors. Agential realism helps us see both
material constraints and conditions but without
falling into empiricism or positivism, and by
investigating processes in far more detail than is
usually developed just by insisting on mediation.
Mediation should be replaced by accounting. At
least we are taking the empirical world seriously
again, as long as we remember that we are studying
phenomena not apparently given empirical objects.
Geometrical analyses are no longer sufficient to
analyse complex events, but what are its dynamics?
There is no simple metric, but rather
reconfigurations and folding, requiring
topological analysis. This will include
reconsidering questions of size and shape, and
scale. So a geographer sees scale is an
exclusionary matter, produced in and through
social activity, it refers to spatial properties
which are always interactively produced contested
and reproduced, so it actually has an active form
for social processes. Different scales are
agential and enfolded through one another [which
challenges the idea of geometrical nesting
according to size, and reinstates intra-activity
and topological dynamics, agential enfolding is
that reconfigure connectivity] [clearance flocking
mud]
Boundary transgressions have to be rethought as
well, for example as a result of information
technology and its transparency and disregard for
obstacles. But such technology does not produce a
flat manifold or level playing field, but can even
exaggerate the unevenness of distribution of
material goods, can further constrain that.
Fernandez apparent in this volume says that of
trans-nationalism and globalism, for example —
these are topological matters where the global the
local and the national intra-act.
We need genealogy's of changing to apologies,
including connectivity across different scales,
seeing how different regions affect each other.
This also requires 'ethics of knowing and being'
(103) opening up possibilities for change into
apology, interventions, a space of possibilities.
That space is not a fixed uniform container but
has a dynamics produced by agential interventions
which can reconfigure it. We can see this with the
politics of identity and the politics of location
which still operates with the old geometry.
Instead we need a politics of possibilities, 'ways
of responsibly imagining and intervening in the
reconfigurations of power', (104)
[So this is the real claim that if we shift from
Euclidean geometry to topology, we don't just have
to operate by manipulating the fixed positions
that are already provided, inverting hierarchies
between identities, for example. You can explore
far more connections. We don't need to stick with
determinism, or even with fixed objects. All is in
flux. The possibilities are endless. We should
have an ethics of possibility rather than one that
just sticks with manipulating fixed positions]
Barad, K. (2008a) Queer Causation
the Ethics of Mattering In
Queering the Non/Human, edited by N
Giffnet and M Hird, 311-- 338.
[this is heavily reliant on her earlier works on
bio engineering in the trans-piece, and the
inevitable brittle star commentaries in the
follow-up. We have slightly different intro tough
and some minor additions]
Causality has been challenged by Foucault and
Butler. Ziarek notes that Foucault talks about
discursive events and series which exhibit
irregularity, which is not the same as mechanical
causality or an '"ideal necessity"'. Butler notes
that this is linked to Foucault's conception of
power, which appears in its effects rather than
existing before events, and includes even
'"dissimulation as one of its attributes or
modes"'. (311) Butler says that the material is
not just the effect of a discourse, and that we
should focus instead on effects instead of
presuming some ontologically prior cause. This
goes over into queer theory as a challenge to
traditional concepts of identity — challenging
causality opens up 'possibilities for resistance
and agency in a space evacuated by deterministic
conceptions of causality'.
A commentary by Kaufman- Osborne on Butler notes
different kinds of causality in Western
philosophy, for example organic and mechanistic,
the former link with agrarian practices, the
latter with craft. This might be an example of
linkages between material and discursive
practices, and a 'transfection of metaphors' (312)
rather than technological determinism. However, he
still operates with a foundational difference
between humans and animals.
This is carried by a comparison of how he
experiences causality as opposed to the way
a guinea pig pet experiences it. Greater
awareness for us leads to a conception of
causality, 'an intelligible account' even though
the guinea pig experiences it. Barad challenges
this, initially through all sorts of witty remarks
about how the guinea pig still occupies a telling
moment, tells all, speaks volumes and so on. The
remarks show 'meta-questions and underlying
presuppositions' that need to be examined. One is
that it is the ability to intervene in causal
events which is a 'condition for producing
discourses about causal relations', so that
intervention matters. There is also a suggested
'inverse relation, between agency and causality'
(313). This is a distinctive 'un-/queer moment' in
his paper.
Generally, the nonhuman has an outside entangled
with the inhuman and the dioferentially human
'haunts these accounts' that are based on
causality in terms of human sociality and
processes of subjection. We need to queer these
accounts still further. We do this by 'seeing what
we can learn from some very queer creatures' [oh
no]. These will show that causality is entangled
with notions of difference and the differences
found in nature.
Before we get to brittle starfish, we consider
another example of biomimicry discussed in the
trans-paper. The activities of an abalone making a
shell, in producing 'a delicate crystal lattice…
[That]… Calls to mind the flawless thin film
layers on a silicon chip' (314). This leads a
professor to say that Mother nature is the '"only
true nanotechnologist"' and that we must learn to
mimic her.
Biomimicry is going to be important in a new
post-industrial era. It's based on what we can
learn from nature. The author has received lots of
awards and has founded a 'biomimicry Guild'
bringing together all sorts of big companies like
Nike and Novell. It's fans see it as an answer to
Carson's Silent Spring, but there are clearly
dangers of misuse and abuse. We can see the
risks from examining how the Wright brothers
learnt about lift and drag by watching vultures,
but by 1914 aircraft were used to drop bombs. Biomimesis
can also be a kind of camouflage, raising
projects 'above the murky pool of ethical, legal
and social concerns'(315), as nature loving.
One Canadian biotech company has set up a farm for
thousands of goats. The point is not to clone the
goat, not to alter nature, but rather to harness
it to produce a variant of spider silk. Spider
silk is 'the holy grail of material sciences' with
wonderful qualities and possible applications in
surgery, industrial fibres, recreational
applications. The biochemist concerned explains
the 'ingenious engineering talents of this
arachnid' in terms of natural competition,
'a kind of arms race between spiders and bugs'.
So 'What could be more natural then than
scientists that the Canadian biotech company Nexia
teaming up with the Materials Science Team of the
US Army Soldier Biological Chemical Command to
take some lessons from spiders' (316). This is
'emulating… Nature's best ideas for peaceful
coexistence' and 'her ingenuity in the face of
military challenges', both 'taking nature as
inspiration to a new level'. Happily, the
collaboration is productive and it led to 'a way
to spin silk from goats milk' with enormous
potential. Nexia holds the patent. Luckily, 'Bio
Steel©" is eco-friendly as well. The CEO
obviously is talking this up. When
challenged with ethical implications, 'he responds
with the confidence of the jujitsu master' and
sees the spider as working in concert with the
fly, using the fly's own energy. The argument
is 'what could be more natural than taking
nature as inspiration? Even nature does it'
The misuse of biomimicry is also well recognised.
Goats might be being turned into cheap
factories, not treated with respect,
illustrating hubris. This suggests a further
ethical issue — we should not do what nature does
not do herself [rukles out all industrial
applications?] This applies particularly to gene
swapping. If things have not emerged in nature
that's a sign that "there is probably a good
reason for its absence… Natural selection is
wisdom in action'" (317) [citing Benyus]. We have
'an ethics based on the principle of following
nature's lead', but this has had unfortunate
consequences in some 'misguided attempts' to
justify 'every possible social prejudice' as in
social Darwinism. Benyus points to the dangers
especially and says they arise because we have
selectively attended to particular species or
behaviour.
She thinks we are '"a unique species, an ethical
moral animal"' (318). This seems reasonable at
first, says Barad, but everything depends how we
are to understand nature and human exceptionalism.
There is also an assumption that we can read
nature's designs immediately. And that we can
separate 'material designs [from] the agential
practices that produce them'. All this leads to
exceptionalism, and the old mirroring practice
separating humans from others. But there is no
pure nature. Its purity has been invoked in such a
way as to lead to 'some of the most highness crime
is known to humankind' [so don't blame nature
blame men — human exceptionalism again though?].
Biomimetic's itself challenges a sharp boundary
between nature and culture. Such challenge can and
do become prejudices if they are based on a
dualism. The notion of a pure nature is not
helpful — it is itself a construction. The real
issue is as Haraway says '"what counts as nature,
for whom, and at what costs"' (319) [then a
banality] 'these practices hold both incredible
promise and unfathomable dangers. Which is not
the end point but the beginning point for
ethical considerations'
[Then on with the brittle starfish, maybe with one
or two extra popular accounts and talk ups, but a
lot of very familiar argument. NB some gripping
chapters in this collection, including one by
Kirby which I must summarise, and lots of highly
entertaining looking ones like those on werewolves
or queer canine literature]
Barad, K (2008b) Living in a
Post-humanist Material World. Lessons from
Schrödinger's Cat. In Bits of Life.
Feminism at the intersections of media,
bioscience and technology Edited by A
Smelik and N Lykke. London: UNiversity of
Washington Press.
[Mercifully short, summarising the main points
about agential realism and the phenomenon. I read
some of these comments as clarifications of some
of the key terms, although Barad says in a note
that it's based on a paper she gave in 2004. Not
some witty challenge to temporality through
Derrida, but rather a conflict between two ways of
measuring the development of an idea — via a
career or via a calendar. Some things are
clarified, such as post-humanism, and some are
clarified unwittingly — discourse becomes like a
material unfolding because things are developed
over time in both. We have syntagm but not
paradigm. What about metaphors? The whole thing
strikes me as Hegelian or some other kind of
vitalism, with humans being produced, perhaps
deliberately so that nature can know itself?]
The piece starts by explaining how Schrödinger was
one of those predicting a new scientific tone for
biology, one which finally explains some of the
residual mysteries, '"a science that tolerated no
secrets"' [citing Keller] (166. Secrets have a
flirtatious quality, but it also tells us about
ethics, in the sense that it implies the 'mastery
of Nature's secrets and her recreation in Man's
image'. Science challenges the underlying
ontological presuppositions including 'geometrical
relations of depth and surface, inside and
outside, thinking and being'. There is also a
sexual connotation where nature is the 'coy female
awaiting the heroic advance of the masculine
scientist who will lift her veil'. Science is
already also driven by 'its expanding role of the
great technician' [and this role will persist even
if we no longer think of revealing secrets]. The
connection of all these issues shows an
entanglement between technology, quantum theory,
physics and biology.
We can begin with Schrödinger's cat paradox. We
have to begin by thinking of classical or
Newtonian physics, where nature is both
determinate and deterministic, objects have
boundaries and we can predict the future of
objects as well as their past [it is this
Newtonian mechanical notion of time that is
attacked so joyfully, but subjective time rejected
it long ago, as in the above example of my
readings]. Objective knowledge will reveal the
objective state of the world. Newtonian physics
was seriously questioned by quantum physics which
denied fully determinate states and saw prediction
only in terms of probability rather than causal
determinism.
So we cannot predict with certainty whether the
atom will decay in a given period of time, but we
already know the probability that it will — 50%.
The experimental setup clearly links the fate of
the to the fate of the atom: 'their are two fates
are entangled' [but this is the ordinary sense of
entangled not the quantum sense?]. Schrödinger's
wave equation therefore predicts two states
superposed — decayed and non-decayed atom, dead
and alive cat..
We can now clarify superposition and entanglement.
Schrödinger was really questioning the complacency
of physics which just assumed states like these
without considering the consequences. His aim was
to lead to further investigation of entangled
states.
This is just one issue raised by a whole set of
quantum quandaries. In this case, it is about
[collapse], why we do not find the superimposed
state when we open the box, but rather one of the
more determinate ones. Schrödinger's wave equation
does not account for this. Quantum theorists of
various kinds have tried to explain this
'including the shockingly anthropocentrism
hypothesis that human consciousness collapses the
superposition… And the bizarre, metaphysically
hyper schizophrenic "many worlds" interpretation'
(169). Barad's notion of entanglement makes more
progress.
The existence of the cat is not smeared or blurred
between two states. The cat must be either alive
or dead [because we have defined it that way?
Elsewhere, she is quite happy to smear the binary
between organic and inorganic]. It cannot be both
simultaneously, because 'this possibility is
logically excluded, since "alive" and "dead" are
taken to be mutually exclusive states' [but we
don't like binaries!]. The cat might be partly
alive and partly dead, or neither.
The 'correct way to understand' the paradox is to
say that 'the cat's fate is entangled with the
radioactive source' [no less mysterious, and still
depending on definitions of cat and radioactive
source]. This is not just an epistemic
entanglement as shredding a thought but an ontic
one. The cat and the atom do not have separate
states of existence. There is indeed no enclosed
entity despite our normal understandings of cat.
'The fact is that no fact of matter concerning the
life state of the cat exists independently of some
way of measuring/defining "life state"' (170).
These measurements or definitions resolve the
indeterminacy of the boundaries and properties of
those concerned. A cat has no determinate life
state. Indeed, we can't even really speak of a
well-defined life state since there is no
determinate meaning [if it is a human error to
define things as if they were separate objects,
why is it not an equal error to claim to have
objective measurements?].
Quantum mechanics attacks 'the metaphysical
substrate of representationalism', (170) that
words and things a primary unit with determinate
boundaries and properties. Quantum physics has
'yielded compelling empirical evidence for the
surprising claim that things do not have
inherently determinate boundaries and properties'.
Instead, we need agential realism. Concepts are
not just ideational but 'are specific material
configurations' [so scientists have no real role
at all, and science becomes a matter of just
fooling around until we reveal the truth]. So it
is material arrangements that resolve
indeterminacy and also produce a cut between
object and subject [so nature provides human
consciousness and subjectivity]. We need to talk
of intra-action not interaction.
What does it mean to materially specify a concept
like life? Why can we not just work with agreed
definitions? However, there are 'five different
definitions of life' (171) and most of those
assume living organisms as the reference point. We
now know that we must break these dualisms, and
lots of others, not least because there are
'genetically modified trends life' forms including
artificial intelligence or artificial lifeforms.
Even if we could work with a concept and
operationalise it into a measuring device, we
would still be 'left with the question of what it
is that we've measured', because measurements 'do
not reveal the already determinate state' of an
entity, but rather constitute boundaries and
properties. What is the objective referent for a
measured property? Not some measurement
independent determinately bounded object.
We need the phenomenon 'the entanglement of
interacting agencies ("objects" and "subjects")
however [the boundary problem emerges] because the
phenomenon 'includes much more than we could ever
drawing a diagram… The entangled and enfolded sets
of apparatuses of bodily production of all the
beings and devices relevant to this example' [and
how have we defined relevance?] Humans are also
phenomena, 'produce through the interaction of
multiple material – discursive apparatuses of
bodily production'. Consciousness is not an
inherent property of individuals [and we are
referred to the 2003 article on post-humanist
performative accounts].
Post-humanist here means not 'post-modernist
celebrations' of the techno-human, nor the next
stage of Man. Instead it involves a 'commitment to
accounting for the boundary practices'through
which human and others are constituted. It is not
'a celebration difference for differences sake'
but rather 'accountability to and for differences
that matter' (173). It implies that matter is not
a fixed essence or property and we should talk
instead of mattering as 'a dynamic process of
iterative interactivity'. Matter is substance in
its becoming, 'a congealing of agency' [but how
does this happen?] There are no inherent fixed
properties.
Phenomena are not just produced in laboratory
exercises, nor are apparatuses just scientific
apparatuses. Instead they are 'boundary drawing
practices through which differential boundaries
and properties come to matter' [I'm not at all
sure what is distinctive about this, of course
there are purposive rational elements in designing
apparatuses. That matters to scientists, but does
it matter to Nature?]. Discursive practices are
also 'specific material configurations which
determine ['differentially enact'] boundaries
properties and meanings [which defines discursive
as meaning any sequence of determination: notions
like boundaries properties and meanings are found
only in human discourse?]. Phenomena are not just
laboratory constructions but are found wherever
there is 'complex agential interactions of
multiple apparatuses'. They are agential. Meaning
is 'a performance of the world in its differential
intelligibility', so that matter emerges out of
the configuring and reconfiguring of boundaries
just as with discourses. Thus 'the material in the
discursive mutually implicated in the dynamics of
intra-activity' (174) [human interactivity,
perhaps even in something explicit like, science,
she means?]. Matter is agentive alive with
possibilities and these possibilities are
differentially configured [swings from Buddhism to
vitalism].
So what is life? 'If quantum physics has any
insights to offer' (174) it will direct us
not to revealing nature's secrets or pinning down
a definitive answer. 'There is no pre-existing
Nature, and we are not Nature's keeper'. Humans
are not external to nature but 'rather a part of
the lifeblood of the universe in its ongoing
recreation' this is why we must be accountable to
becoming an relationality is rather than looking
at the epistemologies ontologies and ethics
employing secrets. We should trust the universe.
'Life is not a secret to be revealed' but 'rather
an entangled agential performance of the world'.
There is no final answer to the question of life
because 'there is no final state of aliveness that
can be pinned down'. Instead we have 'the
inexhaustible creative vitality of the world'
Barad K 2014 Invertebrate
visions:diffractions of the brittlestar in The
Multispecies Salon, ed E Kirksey. London:
Duke University Press.
https://doi.org/10.1215/9780822376989-015
The brittle
star story in the New York Times is cited.
It's 'skeletal system… Also functions as a visual
system'. It can also reconfigure the boundaries
and properties of its body. It has raised
implications for what counts as human, and the
creature is being 'enterprised up for new
computer designs and telecommunications optical
networks' (222) . The author, J. Abraham, as also
published in Nature stressing the ability
to escape predators. 10,000 calcite crystals
function as micro-lenses which focus light onto
nerve bundles. This forms a compound eye in the
sense that it can optimise light from one
direction{better than focus and resolutiomn
see below] They can navigate and detect
shadows and turn lighter at night, which seems to
increase the visibility to predators but overall,
it helps make their vision more effective.
The technique in Aizenberg was 'optical
lithography' the same one that is used to inscribe
circuits on microchips [with some details of the
experiment including cleansing dorsal arm plates].
By shining light through the sample they could
etch a patent on recording wafer. They then
detected bundles of nerve fibre. Aizenberg's press
release likens the brittle star to a digital
camera and says we can learn from this marine
creature because it's very good at peripheral
vision and that would be very useful in cameras.
Sambles also expresses enthusiasm [as in the 2007
quote]. We have to give nature a credit for this
'superior ingenuity which exceeds the current
technological ingenuity of humans'.
It could be the potential applications that have
attracted interest, however. There is also
understatement 'considered good professional
etiquette in scientific publications' (225), while
'statements of the popular press follow a
different set of rules altogether' (226.) Press
releases are also 'very upbeat' and promised
'biomimetic lenses'. Aizenberg's more recent
achievement was also praised, stressing how
naturally designed crystals can have implications
for nanotechnology.
So this is a new optical system, contrasting with
the classical ones that you find in science
studies and cultural studies, and it leads to
comments on the 'different kinds of
epistemological and visualising systems' found in
Western epistemology (227). It should challenge
our ideas of representation which means that
nature is held at bay. There is horrendous anthropomorphism:
'the brittle star is not a creature that thinks
much of epistemological lenses the geometrical
optics of reflection'. It does not have eyes, but
rather is eyes, so it's visual system is embodied
it is a 'visualising apparatus'. Therefore 'it
does not suffer the Cartesian doubts of an alleged
mind-body split', nor are they obsessed with the
boundaries of their bodies. It has 'discursive
practices… [of a very limited kind]
Boundary drawing practices by which it
differentiates between "itself" and the
"environment"… [Which are] materially enacted'.
It's very substance is morphologically active and
generative so it plays 'an agentive role'. It
differentially enacts the cuts between self and
other as in intra-action.
In one agential cut, a particular arm is part of
the self, but in another, part of the environment.
These categories are not fixed because there is a
need to discern the reality of their nature as a
living creature. It can enfold bits of the
environment within itself and expel other parts of
itself [the paradox of being both entity and
relational system]. It challenges notions of
embodiment which are firmly located in the world.
The body's performance Objectivity needs to be
changed as a result to a matter of 'occupying
political coordinates in space and time, in
culture, and in history' (228).
We can also rethink conventional ideas of space
and time. Space is not just a container, nor is
time uniform. For them the relation between
'space, time and matter is much more intimate'
(229). But nobody stands outside the world,
although we can construct 'exteriority within…
Agential separability'.
A jettisoned limb can be a survival tactic to
distract predators, but be should we understand it
just as a piece of structure with 'remnant reflex
energy'? If we think of it that way, the
organism itself must also be seen as energised
like that. It seems much more animated [classic
circular argument] and there is a video clip
on the multispecies – salon website]. What of
diverse behaviour like sexual behaviour? Sometimes
a broken off limb can be an offspring. Only
positivists would see visual separation as
defining bodily boundaries, while real
connectivity 'does not require physical
contiguity'. There are implications for 'lost limb
memory trauma' in psychoanalysis.
We can use brittle star optics as the illustration
of Haraway's diffraction. It can be a 'useful
counterpoint to reflection' (230). It stresses
patterns of difference rather than reflection, and
so do brittle star optics, because they are
'attentive to different optical effects all at
once'. There lenses might experience diffraction
effects which is in a trade-off with resolution.
In this way they 'live at the edge of being
diffraction gratings' [in a different
one-dimensional sense?].
Diffraction is about differences which matter.
Interaction between brittle star and environment
shows the ultimate relational nature of the world
rather than interaction between things. There is
dynamic 'iterative intraactivity'. Small
compound lenses that favour diffraction rather
than resolution can have a survival effect as
with insect eyes.
Brittle stars are 'in a different genus' from
common figures of vision like lenses panopticans
and others. Technically, this simple form of
geometrical optics 'will produce a fuzzy image'(231)
[and so is rejected] It would also ignore
quantum effects. It reveals anthropocentrism,
but challenging that would also be to 'welcome
women, slaves, children, animals and other
dispossessed Others… Into the fold of knowers'
(232).
The animal shows us that 'knowing is a direct
material engagement, a practice of interacting
with the world as part of the world', and does not
involve mediation. This means '"mind" is a
specific material configuration of the world,
not necessarily coincident with a brain',
because the brain does not hold memory
exclusively. Brittle stars can respond without
brains. Somehow, the existence of tacit knowledge
makes the same point.
Generalising [!], Knowing is not exclusively
human, knowers are not always self-contained
rational human subjects, there is no thinking
spirit inside the body. Subjects are
differentially constituted through intra-action,
and may range across the traditional binaries.
Even science takes place with humans as 'part
of the larger material configuration of the
world and its ongoing, open-ended
articulation' (233). Intelligibility is 'an
ontological performance of the world''s own
knowing 'does not require intellection in the
humanist sense' [but only because we have defined
knowing as] 'a matter of differential
responsiveness to what matters'. However, it also
requires 'differential accountability' [with a
reference back to Rouse on the different apparatus
needed to study position and momentum, where their
actual use produces '"discursive significance"'.
We do not need 'cognition in humanist terms',
because a brittle star can already 'recognise a
predator' [anthropomorphism], because it matters,
'life and death are at stake'.
So brittle stars are not just useful models but a
living testimony to intra-action. They cause us to
challenge assumptions that boundaries are sharp
and inherent. This is not the same as celebrating
the blurring of all boundaries asin pomo,
which is 'simplistic', but we 'do not trust our
eyes'. This is part of a wider error to 'put our
faith in representations than in matter', assuming
we have a better access to those.
So diffraction is a 'much subtler and more
profound phenomenon' than classical understandings
imply. Not only does it disrupt
representationalism and all the metaphors of
reflection, it shows the connection between ethics
ontology and epistemology. We are all intra-active
in the world's articulation, and diffraction as a
'material – discursive phenomenon' challenges all
the conventional assumptions about binaries.
Instead it focuses on differential entanglements,
implying 'their very inseparability'. This is the
'deep significance of a diffraction pattern' [only
in the quantum world?]. Agents can be separable
but not individuated, differentiated but also
entangling and we need to think about what will be
'the right response to the other'.
Brittle stars are not just resources or tools but
are phenomena,[as entities? no
environment?] 'agentive beings, lively
configurations of the world', not just objects of
our knowledge. This is how we 'learn about and
co-constitute one another through a variety of
"brittle star" – "human" interactions' (234).
This also gives a deeper understanding of
biomimesis. It is not just copying nature as some
pure essence, any more than the brittle star is
just an object for us. Instead we need to follow
nature's example, be responsible and accountable
for entanglements that we enact [only as nature
does?] Proper biomimesis will preserve
difference and oppose sameness by opposing
geometrical optics and attending to differences.
It honours nature as the first engineer, but
does not stick with her methods. It still
wants to bring the new to light, of course there
are 'very practical reasons' [she seems to be
justifying copywriting new innovations here? —
The © is a sign of responsibilities for
different materialisations (236)
Brittle stars are 'trans/materialities', not just
classifiable as organic, machine, matter and so on
they 'already know how to do nanotechnology' and
do it better than humans do. Their successful
evolution, [bringing ancient nanotechnology
together with current examples] marks 'a
rather queer temporality that comes from the
past and the future'. We should think of
forming partnerships with natural phenomena. The
ethical issue is 'how our desires and our beings
are co-constitutively reconfigured'
Optical lithography has added to our understanding
optics. Using the apparatus itself has led to
changes in them. Studying brittle star lenses
inspires new optical lithography. 'Tools are used
to rework tools' (236). This is enfolding.
Differences are important, diffraction effects and
how they produce differences which matter.
|
|