Notes on: Hollin, G., Forsyth, I.,
Giraud, G., & Potts, T (2017).
(Dis)entangling Barad: materialisms and ethics.
Social Studies of Science 47 (6): 918 –
41. [Repository copy]. DOI:
10.1177/0306312717728344.
Dave Harris
There will be at tension between quantum physics
and macro phenomena. There are 'both frictions and
unacknowledged affinities' with STS, especially
when discussing reflexivity and diffraction.
Agential realism both includes and excludes, and
although the latter has been neglected, this might
be its greatest utility in STS.
It is now possible to play 'Barad bingo' in a wide
range of options and articles. It is both
surprising and striking that the work has been
taken up in so many different fields [good list,
page 2], while being treated more ambivalentlly in
mainstream STS. 'Mainstream' STS implies that
feminist STS might be marginalised. Haraway claims
feminist techno-science is both inside and outside
classic STS, but care should be taken not to cut
it away, although both Haraway and Barad discuss
the relation.
Barad's influence has grown since she changed
disciplines and developed materialism. The output
is still fairly small, however, although there are
many citations. There are implications for social
science, especially hybridity and ANT, but Barad
(2007) herself argues that her work also
contributes to the field of science. She is used
to understand the Anthropocene, and epigenetiscs,
which involve an apparent collapse between nature
and culture. She has also supported inter-and
transdisciplinary work, which, happily, matches
recent calls to integrate social sciences and
humanities in publicly funded research.
Nevertheless this entanglement also produces
ambivalence.
We can start by looking at the role of quantum
physics. For Barad, this is not just a metaphor
but 'rather [it] underpins agential realism's
articulation of how the material world is brought
into being'. This provides a realist material base
and that gives it stability which helps 'avoiding
dangers associated with both social constructivism
and relativism' (5). However, there are still
questions about changing scale. Then we go on to
examine reflexivity and whether Barad has grasped
its heterogeneity especially within STS. Then we
discuss agential realism and the argument that one
reality excludes another when it is brought into
being — this is the ethics of inclusion and
exclusion. This is going to be a more important
discussion than that featuring the other concepts.
This reading will show how work can problematise
as well as use Barad and place it in a broader
context. Possibilities and provocations for the
future are produced.
In the 2007 book,
a secure guarantee seems to be offered by quantum
theory on the relationship of matter and meaning.
This needs to be interrogated to make sure it is
not just 'the new case of physics envy — of the
quantum variety' (6) [explained in the next
paragraph as admiration for the ontological
hardness of physics].
Barad avoids naive positivism but says her work
offers a way to undo constructivism and its
anti-realist implications. She wants to correct
positions where '"language has been granted too
much power"'. This hardness has attracted
economists or even positivists and behaviorists,
but Barad offers 'a rehabilitated objectivity: an
objectivity resting, oddly, upon principles of
uncertainty, paradox and "quantum weirdness"' (7).
This draws upon Böhr's '"philosophy–physics"'
which rejects Newtonian mechanics and instead
advocates principles of uncertainty and
indeterminacy. The universe is an entangled one
governed by subatomic particles. Measuring
instruments become 'inextricably snagged' in their
actual experiments. The scientist is a productive
force in experiments [partly, it seems because
they feel they are doing science — 'the sensorium
of the laboratory']. Nevertheless there is still
objectivity because measurements can be reproduced
and communicated via '"permanent marks… left on
bodies which define the experimental conditions"'
[Barad]. This predictability lends 'strange
stability'. It helps us move beyond deconstruction
or social constructivism by showing that we can
engage with the ontology of the world again, while
avoiding positivism
Chaos theory has had a similar trajectory in
social and human sciences, but this time 'used to
establish prestige, additional understanding, or
methodological innovation'. That can be both
fruitful and dangerous. However, Barad insists
that there is a continuity between quantum theory
and the macro realms — 'quantum physics is not a
metaphor, but is instead an instance of matter
with which Barad is working' (8). The same rules
apply in micro and macro domains. The results in
physics apply to other domains too. However,
responding to early criticism, Barad argues that
agential realism is still '"vulnerable to
empirical results… [and] could ultimately be
proven wrong"' [in Barad K (2011) Erasers
and erasures: Pinch’s unfortunate ‘uncertainty
principle’. Social Studies of Science
41(3): 443–454.].
Like Lather, Barad supports offering realism as
'"ballast"' against post-modernism. This can then
produce a number of political projects ranging
from cultural geography to Harding's new science,
to materialist feminisms [in Alaimo again --
Alaimo S (2008) Material Feminisms.
Indiana: Indiana University Press.]. For Barad,
there is 'a lively and worldly substratum… which
is testable and trustworthy'. There are
demonstrable material practices produced
performatively which provides a link with
political actions and ethical implications.
On the issue of scale, Barad draws upon Böhr to
argue that 'the micro and macro worlds are
entangled with one another… And that the same
rules apply both domains'. This compares with
Everett and the many worlds hypothesis and Bohm's
mathematics and lots of other interpretations in
the physics community. It makes scale particularly
relevant in discussing Barad's work.
She resists '"geometric"' readings of scale
[apparently around page 245] which assume that
micro is always smaller than macro. Scale is
instead an outcome of worldly processes of
production and reproduction. This draws upon the
work of a geographer, Smith, who also argues about
the 'givenness of scale' and argues that it is
constructed through a social process [but in
interaction with geographical structures]. Barad
and Smith both argue that diverse scales are not
real, but are rather '"nested"' —
'exteriorities–within–phenomena', so the proper
argument should be directed to boundaries,
collectivities and exteriority, or what Barad
calls topology. Smith also sees that there are
radical political issues in reconstructing scales.
Barad endorses this and often jumps scales
herself. Agential realism in particular is
deployed across a range of scales.
Some physicists have questioned this argument,
though, including a certain Tsing 'with whom Barad
also shares a great deal'. Jumping scales without
changing the research question is common in modern
knowledge, she argues, but she implies a negative
connotation and urges us to address scales that do
not nest. Something might be lost in the
transition between scales — 'those specific
qualities which are valuable precisely because
they are not scalable' (10) [for me that would be
all the human qualities — even if they are just
questions of scale, they are obviously crucial in
differentiating us from starfish]. There might
still be a political purpose in jumping scales,
and Barad's wide applicability might be one
consequence, but 'political and ethical potential'
is lost and should be revisited.
Barad has not received total support within STS,
especially outside feminist techno-science. Barad
sees criticisms as based on separation and
reflection and argues for the creative undoing of
any mirroring. Reflection still keeps the world
that a distance, offers only mimesis, or when the
subject is placed back in the picture, mirroring.
This is the '"same old geometrical optics of
reflections"'. Some people have argued this is an
unfair picture of constructivist views, or that
reflexivity is still useful, for example in making
us think about the influence of their own
activity. For Barad this is only '"turning the
mirror around'" (11).
Diffraction, after Haraway, is both a methodology
and a 'way of viewing the world' and is based on
the ways in which particles encounter each other
and the way this is different with waves. They can
occupy the same point in space and time — 'this is
called superposition', and the emergent wave shows
properties resulting from the combination of the
two, as in waves in water. A diffraction pattern
is produced, after diffraction apparatus has
brought the two waves together. We can learn from
the actual wave pattern about the diffraction
apparatus, and this is one of the benefits of
diffraction — it is 'a much more useful way of
bringing the method, the apparatus, into focus'
(12).
Diffraction then becomes a matter of reading
insights through one another, and attending to
details and specificities of relations of
difference, 'coming together, and entanglement and
emergent difference' and this is applicable to a
range of disciplines. STS is too limited by being
confined just to science. After diffraction, a new
object of investigation emerges which will be
neither sociology nor science. There is obvious
appeal for transdisciplinary research.
However, Barad neglects some differences in
reflexivity, numerous categories with
subcategories. Not all are based on optical
metaphors as Zizek argues with Hegelianism
notions. Reflexivity can be associated with
ethnomethodological enquiry into the mutual
constitution of both accounts and reality —
'"constitutive reflexivity"' for Woolgar, where
distinctions between things and what is said about
them is an actively created achievement, the
result of discursive work [which is probably why
that won't do]. So it is misguided to talk about a
single methodology of reflexivity, and more needs
to be done on examining the alternatives
especially in STS.
In STS, there is already some criticism about
'"playing the stranger"' in physics, and about the
unambiguous communication of laboratory results
upon which objectivity is founded. There is
rejection of the '"strong program in the sociology
of knowledge"' because phenomena can emerge. The
new materialism runs the risk of '"universalising
metaphysical claims about the nature of matter"',
and simply taking '"scientific truth claims about
the world at face value"' [quoting a recent
article]. Barad's text is 'less critical about
contemporary physics, nano science and genetic
modification than we expect from STS' (14), and
does not demolish certain speculative scenarios
and myths, especially of 'biotechnical
revolution'. What we should be looking at instead
is attempting to incorporate both reflexive and
diffractive approaches, including agential realism
— for example by examining more carefully
scientific apparatuses, already a significant
question for some strands in STS.
Agential realism shows how the problems come
together, since it reworks the notion of a
scientific apparatus in an important move. There
is nothing in the metaphysics of seeing things in
themselves as separate from representations, a
mistake both naive scientific realism and social
constructivism make. Tools of measurement are not
entirely separate from the thing being measured
and do not just convey neutral information, as in
realism, nor is language the primary source of
knowledge with inaccessible matter for social
constructivism. Both depend upon representation.
Barad apparently sees the origin of the problem in
Kant. Diffraction sees no given distinction
'between worlds and words' (15), and entanglement
is the way forward.
This draws upon Böhr and his solution to
Heisenberg's uncertainty principle. The
difficulties of measuring all the properties of a
particle, both its momentum and position is
usually seen as an 'epistemic problem'in that the
act of measuring itself disturbs the particle.
This is representationalism, though. Böhr argued
instead that we are looking at 'ontic
indeterminacy' instead, whether measurement itself
fixes the states of the particle, measurement
makes some properties become determinate. Both
position and momentum are 'complementary states'
where the existence of one property 'necessarily
excludes the other'.
Measurement is an intra-action, and we can
generalise from this to get to phenomena where
relata are entangled with relations. Any
separations, including those 'between words,
things, and knowers are real enough but… Are
effects of particular engagements with the world'
(16) this is agential realism — all the elements
in experimentation, the particle, the measuring
apparatus, the conceptual frameworks and the
scientist do not preexist the entangled state.
However, particular combinations will produce
reproducible results — 'same matter, same
apparatus, same outcome'.
This reading of Böhr is used to address unhelpful
binaries between nature and culture in social
science, in Foucault or Butler, for example. But
Böhr also has to be extended. The apparatus is not
just a laboratory set up, as illustrated by the
contingencies of the Stern-Gerlach experiment
which included cheap cigar smoke. It follows that
there is 'no intrinsic outside to the apparatus'
which extends infinitely. Here we go beyond mere
methods advice.
There are affinities with ANT and other approaches
to materiality. Strangely, though the implications
have not been pursued in human geography even
though they have already taken a step towards
nonrepresentational theories. By contrast, those
who focus on the nonhuman see Barad as 'neither
seismic nor entirely novel'. (17)
However, there might be an outside nevertheless
even though it is not intrinsic — someone using a
stick to navigate a dark room shows the
possibilities — the stick is both measuring
apparatus and an object of investigation,
depending on the agential cut. Those cuts produce
exteriority as 'a boundary making practice' (18),
and we have some control here — if we
bracket out some factors, we need to be
accountable, such as when we omit gender or other
social variables, [or just see them as passive
variables with no emergent effects of their own
which led her to the performativity of gender].
This notion of exclusion is what makes Barad's
work 'distinct and important', especially its
ethical component. Agential realism is also a
matter of leaving things out, 'absence'. When one
apparatus cuts to produce a particular world,
'another is necessarily excluded'. This has
implications when we jump scale but it has been
relatively neglected with Barad, less so with
Haraway.
Haraway has now adopted the term intra-action and
used it to explain relatons with companion
species. It's been adopted in feminism, although
ethical implications less so, missing some of the
more radical demands. Entanglement has been
overemphasised by comparison.
Barad's intra-action goes beyond hybridity, which
implies relations shape entities, however
intra-action is not entirely novel [references,
page 19 include ANT] in stressing the agency of
nonhuman entities and their effects on humans.
Seeing this as enactment helps break the usual
ethical hierarchies between humans and animals.
Barad might be part of a broader '"turn to
ontology in STS"' [quoting Woolgar] to indicate
that things might be otherwise — a 'long-standing
core slogan' for STS. The ontological and
epistemological have been collapsed before, and
the performative composition of reality also
noticed. Nevertheless it is a novel emphasis on
ethics.
Barad can be read as insisting instead on the
'relative stability afforded to matter after it
has interactively emerged' (20). Things could
indeed have been otherwise, but the emphasis is on
how things congeal in specific forms [not enough
on this for my money], how the specific
intra-actions have produced distinctions between
subject and object, or object and measuring
agency. This brings with it 'particular sets of
ethical responsibilities' since we are accountable
for these cuts [so humans are radically different
after all]. In particular we need to focus on
'constitutive exclusions'.
Haraway focuses on ethics in the animal
laboratory, first decentring the human and then
problematising humanist ethics to rebuke ideas
that human good is more important or that animals
have rights. Haraway stresses that we must
generate here from these encounters, be open to
learning from them, formulate new kinds of
interest and attempt to 'understand how nonhuman
needs are articulated' (21) to produce
'cosmopolitical ethics that creates room for
nonhumans to impose their own "requirements" on
humans' [apparently attributed to Stengers]. If we
cut things differently, we can redistribute agency
'in ethnically significant ways'.
This has been taken up in a series of debates in
ethology, such as the ethics of allowing birds to
imprint on humans. When Lorenz encouraged
imprinting, he also found himself having to fulfil
the needs of the geese, so they affected him and
changed his identity. Others have seen this is a
more violent kind of exclusion of other ways of
being a goose. Haraway uses cuts to de-naturalise
distinctions between humans and animals by
pointing to their common entanglement. Barad adds
another dimension in discussing the exclusion of
whole realities. These may be difficult to reverse
'especially if they are instantiated through vast
sociotechnical networks' [indeed — she never
discusses this though]. We see this with the
commercialisation of laboratory animals, links
with military apparatuses or agriculture, even
disability politics. We learn that 'certain
responsibilities and manifestations of agency
could have already been foreclosed by a succession
of cuts' (22).
The conclusion emphasises that quantum physics is
not a metaphor for Barad. She has not been
entirely successful in jumping to sociocultural
contexts though. She overdoes the criticisms of
reflection, and does not see that diffractive
approaches are actually close to 'work grounded in
"constitutive reflexivity"' (23). Apparatuses
might not have an intrinsic outside, but there is
an outside nevertheless, beyond the boundary
produced by the cuts and this needs to be
emphasised, especially in applications.
Complementarity and necessary inclusion are
crucial if we are not to 'uncritically celebrate
relationality and hybridity without consideration
of alternative worlds lost at the moment of
emergence' (24).
Agential realism has potential but we must not be
uncritical. It is not that radical a break from
feminist STS and there are linkages with longer
standing work. Rose, for example, borrows some
bits of Barad to produce 'partial, plural and
attentive research', but she also maintains
elements of the old reflection model. This
suggests thjat Barad's work might be used as a
tool, building on pre-existing conceptual
developments rather than a break. She should not
be a 'tome to cling to but a tool to synthesis'
(24).
social theory
|
|