Notes on: Pinch, T. (2011). Karen
Barad, quantum mechanics, and the paradox of
mutual exclusivity. Social Studies of
Science, 41(3), 431-441. Retrieved July 1,
2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/41301940
Dave Harris
Barad was talking( at a conference where they
met) in order to demonstrate quantum
entanglement. But she did not do 'deconstructing
or contextualising such experiments' but 'used the
results to support own position in science studies
— an approach she calls "agential realism"' (431).
Surprised, Pinch asked if she did not find it
'more than a little odd' that a metaphysical
position should depend on the outcome of physics
experiments. If the experiments had come out
differently, would we have to abandon agential
realism? Barad apparently said that she was happy
to connect science studies with the best work in
physics, whether that meant stand or fall.
Quantum mechanics is 'vastly successful', yet what
it actually means remains 'notoriously obscure'.
Relations between the entities it describes and
how it connects to space and so on used to be
discussed in the 1930s, as with the debate between
Einstein and Böhr, with the former arguing that
statistical bases are insufficient. The later
Copenhagen Interpretation became accepted wisdom,
and involves not worrying about foundational
issues all the time physicists could calculate and
make technologies 'and get funding for their
work'. As a result, philosophy took over the issue
of foundations, and 'Philosophy, as all physicists
know, is good for you in small doses but
ultimately can be dispensed with' (432).
The emphasis shifted back a bit to physics and to
quantum technologies, but how this is happened has
not been examined by Barad — she 'seems
uninterested in history'. She also omits a
particular article by Harvey who argued in 1981,
that 'the possibility of turning philosophy into
real experiments made the area much more
"plausible" (that is fundable)'. [Harvey had
interviewed many of the experimenters at work in
the 70s]. He also argued that social and material
practices of physicists and the credibility of the
results 'was far more complicated than suggested
in Barad's rather bare – bones account'.
Entanglement arose from an experiment first
performed by Einstein, Podolsky and Rosen in a
thought experiment. Apparently, it involves
searching for correlations 'between two remote
particles that once interacted'. The technique is
for remotely separated experimenters to measure
spin in different directions: the second detector
is randomly set. Apparently, despite random
variations, 'the spin of the particles at both
locations is found to be instantaneously
correlated' (433) according to the predictions of
Bell's Theorem.
All this is summarised really well by Barad, but
agential realism departs from 'crystal clarity'
and becomes 'very dense assertions about such
matters as agency, intra actions, becoming,
phenomena, causality, dynamics, materiality, and
the role of the post-human'. As well as
dense prose there is also repetition and sloppy
editing. Engagement with other science
studies people is left to the footnotes.
Barad does engage with some of the 'limitations of
popular accounts of quantum mechanics' as in
Frayn's play, which talks about Heisenberg and
uncertainty 'without understanding the physics
behind it '. She wants to address the common
notion of the disturbance exerted by measuring
instruments and says that Böhr goes deeper into
thinking this. Her goal is to conceive this
relationship but not actually measure it.
One strange absence is Kuhn's work, even though he
has referred to the history of quantum
mechanics. Her account of quantum
experiments''is not so much a view from nowhere as
a rather Whiggish account, where all the
experiments lead up to what we know these days—the
truth about quantum entanglements' (434).
She wants to reinstate Böhr in particular.
She misses out 'the messy history, the lacunae
... the grasping and stumbling in the dark
... most of the social and historical
context'. Instead, elite physicists are
revered as brilliant. Böhr sometimes gets
close to god. She agrees with Haraway about
the need to situate knowledge, but 'her own
failure to situate these experiments is one of the
paradoxes of the book'.
This might be because she's following a
philosophical take. Even so, 'history and
sociology do really matter here'. Context is
introduced in other parts of the book, where
science emerges from 'contingent human interests,
from messy materiality and practice, and from a
wider constellation of cultural, technological and
military interests', but this should also 'make
us... a little less likely to take them...as the
obvious grounding for a new ontology'.
Particularly relevant factors are the context of
world war two, the development of the bomb, growth
during the Cold War era benefiting 'a colossally
wealthy postwar physics community allied to a
military industrial context', then of the
counterculture and political protest.
Quantum mechanics became 'a hugely popular source
for the culture industry', and it is no good
Barad's just regretting this. Proper
students of science would have helped her here,
but instead she he relies on a bold 'pass on the
literature'
There are also physicists who rejected the role of
philosophy in interpreting quantum theory,
including Bohm who was suspected of being a
communist fellow traveller, and forced out of his
university, Princeton. He made an alliance with
Soviet scientists who were also questioning
quantum mechanics. The story needs telling,
but in an interview with Pinch, Bohm said he had
serious troubles trying to understand the theory,
and rejected 'Böhr as idealistic
metaphysics'(435). He produced a rival
'materialistic interpretation of quantum theory
[apparently 'known as a hidden variables
interpretation'], but was rejected by the
Copenhagen tendency. A colleague of Böhr,
Rosenfeld, announced that Bohm was wrong, and
relied upon an alleged mathematical proof by Von
Neumann. This seemed to be mathematics
trumping philosophy. Nevertheless both Bohm
and Bell developed new work, and showed this proof
'could trivially be overcome'
Bohm apparently returned to the USA with a revised
theory. Meanwhile, entanglement
experiments'had been taken up by a new high
powered group at Berkeley, who were open to things
like extra sensory perception as well as
entanglements'. Bohm presented some of his
results using 'several pieces of bent metal'
apparently produced by Yuri Geller, and Geller had
already been supported by two other 'laser
physicists' in an article in Nature.
It looked as if a quantum mechanics might indeed
be connected to parapsychology, until Geller was
accused of fraud and lost support, and as military
pressures became more important. Military
and corporate links produced 'quantum computing,
quantum cryptography, and quantum teleportation'.
Barad announces that she is departing from
conventional science studies approaches to suggest
that the study of science and the study of nature
go hand in hand. This is supposed to have a
direct relevance for science studies, especially
the way in which issues like agency and
relationship to the material world are thought.
She develops this through her account of the
double slit [quantum erasure] experiment, which
Feynman claimed 'entailed the whole quantum
mystery'. Interference patterns are produced
after beams of electrons or atoms are projected,
the interference pattern resembles
diffraction. Diffraction patterns can occur
even when only one [particle] atom at the time
passes through the system. However, one
electron at the time indicates particles. If
we detect which slit an atom passes through,
without humans observation immediately involved,
then this will confirm a particle status.
Once we know which slit is being traversed, the
atom starts to behave as a particle. We turn
off then back on the which slit detector
device after the atoms have gone through, and wave
like interference reappears.
For Böhr, this illustrates complementarity rather
than the classical separation of waves and
particles. He says that we have to consider
the whole measuring system, including the
apparatus—if we do an experiment to search for
particles we find them, and the same for
waves. This is not just observer
disturbance. The results are 'actualised
according to how the experiment is set
up'(436). There can be no independent
reality with properties waiting to be
measured. Instead, of the complementary
phenomena available, the ones that are realised
'depends on how the whole measuring apparatus is
set up'. Barad says this is not a matter of
changing the past, despite the name of the
experiment, because we're talking about
inseparable wholes including objects, agencies of
observation, space and time. Böhr's account
is certainly 'self consistent' and there is no
warrant for any connections with mysticism or
ESP. Böhr's work is objective because it
provides reproducible results which can be
'clearly described and communicated between
physicists'(437). The whole approach has also been
called relationism.
Böhr addressed the result of his experiments'
primarily to Einstein et al, but in the 'notorious
later writings', he applied the principle more
widely, including to 'all sorts of other
situations, including those of the social
sciences'. This full radicalism is not
always been recognized. Lots of people
support Böhr on quantum physics, but not on social
sciences. It is the same with current
allegiance to ANT, which has been partially
accepted by people inside science studies, but not
the bit about 'complete symmetry between humans
and non humans'.
Barad's great merit is to explicate Böhr clearly,
but she goes further. She tries to save him
from his commitment to humanism, a matter of
giving 'priority to humans' and how humans' agree
over measurements'. This is a mistake and
might lead to some notion of an overarching human
mind [indeed, transcendental consciousness].
It also suggests that quantum phenomena only
actualise when they encounter human
consciousness. The real criticism of Böhr is
that his notion of complementarity 'rested upon a
notion of what could be communicated in language
and by this he meant classical concepts'.
Bohm had already said that, and argued that we
need to find a new language for quantum phenomena.
The extension into agential realism involves three
steps. First, Böhr's notion of language is
too narrow, and assumes the sharing of
concepts. Instead, Barad draws upon a
'materialist reading of Foucault' to refer to
'material discursive practices'. Second, the
concept of apparatus is extended to mean more than
just the actual instruments—the cigar of Stern can
also be seen as a part of the apparatus.
Boundaries are not easy to delineate [they seem
infinitely extendable]. Fernandes fits in by
examining 'the political economy of apparatuses':
the jute mill is a piece of apparatus which
produces not only jute but workers, bodies, post
colonial relationships and so on. Third,
humans are produced by Nature, argued
through looking at the work on ultrasound scanning
and parenthood, and also through a materialist
critique of Butler.
Her new 'performative approach of agential
realism' (438) is still indebted to Böhr
especially the notion of the phenomenon and the
way in which material agencies instantiate
them. This leads her to suggest that the
world is a place of becoming, intra-actions are
everywhere producing phenomena. Agents are
not just humans', and can become intelligible to
non humans'who can respond [this is what the
brittle star staff allegedly shows]. Space
time and matter continually unfold from these
intra actions. Experiments' are not the only
apparatuses'. Human beings do not just
observe the world but intra act in it.
Ontology and epistemology cannot be
separated—'they study practices of knowing in
being'. These will also help us identify
'which specific intra actions matter'.
Agential realism is seen as or more self
consistent way of describing quantum mechanics,
systematizing Böhr, avoiding subjectivism, leading
to new ways to think about connections between
humans and non humans'. Pinch is still
uncertain that the 'notorious difficulties in that
field' have been solved. Barad goes on to
say that agential realism should be the basis for
science studies and also a grounding for a new
ethics.
The history of science studies is sometimes seen
as moving from representation through an interest
in practice to the modern interest in
performativity and its ontological turn.
Pickering is important here and he too has written
about physics and agency. He does appear in
Barad's work but only in footnotes, where it is
dismissed as 'overly humanist' (439) others like
Mol and Law are also neglected. Barad has
cited other interpretations that are close
to her own, however, but Barad never really
explores similarities and differences. This
is odd for 'someone committed to the diffraction
metaphor and its emphasis upon difference'.
Barad does emphasize reproducibility, but, 'like
Karl Popper' , (439) does not see that this is
contested, and that there are difficulties in
agreeing that phenomena are the same or that an
experiment is repeatable. Everything depends
on 'the culture of trust, a shared form of
life and shared practices, including tacit
knowledge, learnt and passed on in communities of
practice', obviously human practices again.
Epistemology doesn't just go away.
Entanglements experiments can be described 'in a
simple realist way', effacing all the 'history,
sociology, and struggle of the physics community
to obtain a precious consensus' [I think she does
this by stressing the single decisive experiment
that split Böhr and Heisenberg]. Barad never
discusses how agreement is actually
realised. That might be just too human
centred, or just seen as another becoming of the
world. She says the results are never
incontrovertible. In the end she adopts the
'physicists' typical viewpoint' '(caveats and
all)' in saying that experimental findings offer
direct evidence [of Böhr in particular]: this is a
'a long way away from a science studies treatment
of experiments and the grounding of experimental
findings in the society and culture of physics'.
The turn to ontology disputes the claim that
knowledge is situated in human communities.
How they actually do epistemology, reach agreement
is neglected. Barad calls both for a more
situated account of science while still 'drawing
in a realist mode upon experiments' to support her
position'. She seems to offer a kind of
exclusion between doing science and writing about
it, separately, as a scientist and as a science
studies practitioner, but this 'negates the
history of a field' which aims to produce a
productive dialogue between the two camps.
Efforts so far have revealed it to be 'a most a
difficult and fraught enterprise, with much
misunderstanding and miscommunication going both
ways' [I think Barad bottled out of it when
confronted with objections to feminist science
studies]
Barad thinks physics and its results are not just
a metaphor but have 'direct implications for
science studies' (440). At times this
'courts a form of scientism', using prestigious
elite science to support a view in science
studies. The outcome may be benign
there. Böhr's work is hardly 'at the centre
of the scientific enterprise these days'
[nasty]. Most feminists are concerned to
reconfigure science 'or at least its social
relations'. Barad's sees feminist science
studies as about gender and science in the making,
how the two co-constitute each other. The
new ethical framework on the materialism of bodies
has important consequences for gender. But
the connection of entanglement experiments is less
understandable. She knows that it might be
'the right political move' 'to have science on
your side', and we do need to think about how we
engage with people, including the ones we've
studied. But this 'paradox of mutual
exclusivity between science and science studies'
is not the solution, and it risks losing 'the
earlier insights gained from the contextualising
and the cultural and social embedding of science'
Note two says that Bohm's explanation referred to
hidden variables 'acting at the sub quantum level
producing the statistical fluctuations at a higher
quantum level—in the same way that the kinetic
theory of gases can be used to explain Boyle's
law' (440).
back to Barad page
|
|