Notes on: Barad, K. (2012)
Nature's Queer performativity. Kvinder, Køn
& Forskning (Women, Gender & Research)
1--2: 25--53
Dave Harris
[This is the one referred to in the Mousse interview.
A lot of the phrases in that article come from
here].
A recent news story about amoeba hints at issues
of foundations, stability, shape shifting, 'queer
critter behaviours' and lots of binaries.
Apparently there were billions of genetically
identical single celled individuals clustered
together. The article was written in terms that
seem to raise all sorts of anxieties. One is that
cells might evolve to produce a larger scale
organisation, another is that they might be
everywhere. The whole article is riddled with
'subterranean imaginaries' (26) touching on Cold
War fantasies. Some of the terms, even by
scientists are a bit odd, such as 'suicide',
and 'all that it implies about
intentionality and the metaphysics of
individualism'. The real interest is that amoeba
have mixed behaviours, some of them equal to those
of animals with ganglia or simple brains [citing
an expert]. Individualism is questioned, identity.
The creatures are often taken to be model
organisms, but they 'queer the nature of identity'
and display 'multiple indeterminacy'. We even find
the origin of the phrase[ in Mousse]
'managed to hoodwink scientists' ongoing attempts
to nail down its taxonomy', and the difficulties
of classifying it by phylum or kingdom. However
there is a 'rhetorical bias' which favours stories
about individual sacrifices for the good of the
whole, with obvious 'political and moralistic
undercurrents' (27).
Fears of the movie The Blob [sic] affected
xenophobia and anti-communism, as well as other
social fears based on 'loathing and contempt for
the Other' including recent health epidemics, and
the spread of racial religious or ethnic extremism
is. Overall 'an aggregate of angst and dread
labours beneath the surface' (27). There is even
an article referring to '"amoebic morality"', and
a lot of science reporting also uses moral
descriptors like noble or self-sacrifice, and
notices that amoeba are featuring in laboratory
studies of altruism. Images of nature are invoked
which range from 'exemplary moral actor or a
commie activist'. This is anthropomorphic, but she
is interested in anthropomorphism as a way of
breaking with anthropocentrism and human
exceptionalism, with humans alone featuring
agency or rationality of language. Anthropomorphism
can be used to call all this into question and
challenge the assumptions of anthropocentrism,
and this will be jolly brave, 'putting oneself at
risk' to generate response, opening the issue to
new discussions.
So the problem might lie in our current
conceptions of moralism with its 'forceful and
stinging character' (28) and its implication in
the nature/culture binary. If humans are the only
moral agents, this binary is implicit, and has to
be safeguarded — but breaches are also inevitable.
We can see this with reference to an article about
crimes against nature, including bestiality or
sodomy. Such crimes are subject to serious
penalties. Jaffa has even claimed that sodomy
offends against nature and is thus irrational [the
source apparently is an editorial in the Los
Angeles Times]. Distinctions between male
and female cannot be just arbitrary, and to argue
so would threaten all the distinctions central to
morality including those that condemn slavery and
genocide. Despite this, the underlying implication
is that unnatural sexual acts are worse than mass
killings of nonhumans. Among other problems, the
whole argument assumes that whoever commits these
acts have somehow escaped from nature, and thus
pose a particular danger likely to oppose all
natural behaviour. There is also a contradiction
in that bestial behaviour could be seen as
perfectly natural. The law itself implicitly
admits that humans are quite capable of engaging
in nonhuman acts.
Nature is seen to be a good Christian, but what if
she is a commie or a pervert? Haldane's quote
raises the possibility [see Mousse interview], and
Bagemihl insists that creatures themselves are
often homo, bi or trans, and that homosexuality
occurs in 450 animals and so on [but she has
objected to anthropomorphism like this above].
Atoms might themselves be queer. Queer means 'a
radical questioning of identity and binaries' [for
cultural and political reasons --humans
only?] including nature/culture (29). We
come to realise that all sorts of apparent
impossibilities are actually possible including
queer causes, matter, space and time. 'Queer' is
not fixed and determinate, [shouldn't be according
to queer theorists quoted in the notes]
however but itself turns on 'a desiring radical
openness… Multiplicity… Dis/continuity'. [This
very human form?] may reside at the heart of
spacetimemattering.
She would like to 'thank the amoeba, an
exceptional comrade' for assistance and in
foregrounding the characteristics of moralising
cultures that turn to hatred.
Queer performativity is demonstrated by 'a motley
crew of queer co-workers', from social amoeba to
academics and atoms. The binaries that support
divisions between human and nonhuman are to be
challenged, including the nature/culture divide.
We can start by reconsidering 'acts against
nature' and the moral condemnation they evoke.
Human sexual activity can be seen in this way,
however, demonstrating the instability of the
logic, where perpetrators are damaging nature and
yet have somehow slipped back to it. Human
violence against animals, associated with the food
industry, might also be seen as a crime against
nature. Sexual acts are particularly focused upon,
however.
Performativity is central to queer theory, but is
usually seen as exclusively human. However human
exceptionalism is inadequate to ground a theory
relating to 'matters of objection and the
differential construction of the human',
especially if we grasp that humanness is graded,
and can include the inhuman, or dehumanisation of
oppressed groups. Himmler, after all, saw
anti-Semitism as delousing (31). [This is a tricky
example though, because it is an equivalence
between the human and the nonhuman, seeming to
agree with her — but a bad one]. We can
attack Himmler's view by insisting that human
beings have 'singular superiority' but this also
devalues the nonhuman, and thus reproduces 'the
very same calculus of racialisation deployed in
the first place' [implying that loathing of lice
is the same crime as hatred of Jews?]. This
exclusion is an ethical and moral matter and it
should be accounted for — we have taken a decision
to ignore how 'material conditions and
effects of how different differences matter', and
this leads to further erasures, such as those of
any question of the right to kill nonhumans.
Asserting and privileging animal rights will not
do either, because this still does not 'promote
accountability' (31). [A strange and largely
incomprehensible note 22 explains that we should
'be attentive to any underlying mathematics' when
accounting, and notice that 'the vulnerability of
the abject constitutive other' doesn't
depend on hierarchical rankings, but can build on
equivalence relations'. I take this to mean that
saying animals have the same rights as us will not
protect them].
We need an analysis to rethink equivalence
relations and how they are produced by cuts
producing distinctions between human and nonhuman.
The constitution of both terms is important and so
are there 'respective constitutive exclusions'. We
need to consider this before we get onto any
comparisons. Post-humanism would argue that we
should not blur the boundaries between human and
nonhuman, not erase distinctions and differences,
and certainly not just invert humanism. Instead we
need to understand how particular boundaries have
material effects [note 23 refers us to another
piece where she explains post-humanism and how it
questions categories and practices of boundary
making]. However, cuts cannot be just human or
cultural — we 'must not assume a prior notion of
the "human"'. We should ask instead what about the
nonhuman and performative accounts? [We assume
there are some nonhuman ones -- and then berate
Butler for not discussing them!]
This will widen the applicability of
performativity to include nonhumans. In particular
though, it will emphasise the practices of
exclusion and differentiating and their material
effects, rather than doing an analysis based on
leaving these boundaries in place. We will have to
consider 'not merely natural and social forces but
the differential constitution of forces as
"natural" or "social"' (32) [an equally baffling
note 24 says what this means is that we have to
rethink performativity not just widen it, in
particular understanding it as 'iterative
intra-activity rather than iterative
citationality' — I haven't yet got to the basis of
this reference to citationality --yes I have, it's
Butler, meaning cultural citations, or different
discourses?].
Instead of thinking of nonhuman performativity, we
should think of it instead as '[non motivated?]
materialising practices of differentiating' and
then not all the actors will be human. The
nonhuman can also make distinctions, by
differentiating themselves [they do, or human
observers do?] from their environments or
from others. This will also our effects of
'causality, agency, relationality and change'[am
afraid I can't see any way to do this. These are
human terms and can only be applied to the
nonhuman via metaphor or homonym]. We have to
think about differentiating, something that
actually makes space-time and matter, whose
exclusions are part of the very fabric. She claims
to have given such an account elsewhere — in the Signs article, 2003,
and in her book
-- and discussing agential realism.
This assumes 'the world's performativity — its
iterative intra-activity' [apparently, note 27
tells us, it is Butler who has a notion of
performativity as 'iterative citationality' in her
book on the discursive limits of sex, 1993]. In
particular, matter is not an effect of
discursive practices but is itself agentive.
Individual entities are entangled parts of
phenomena which are themselves
material-discursive, and interactions extend
across conventional space and time. This reworks
notions of both material and discursive and moves
away from humanism. Phenomena are best seen as
entanglement in the special quantum sense — the
'(ontological) inseparability of agentially intra
acting "components"' [so intra-action and
phenomena more or less mean the same thing?].
Intra-action reconfigures notions of causality
agency space-time and matter. An agential cut is
not a Cartesian cut between subject and object but
only a local resolution of indeterminacy. They
enact 'agential separability — the local
conditions of exteriority-within-phenomena'.
Differentiating does not involve radical
exteriority but this form of separability [but
only because you denied radical exteriority in the
first place in the definition of phenomena]. Hence
the phrase to 'cut things together – apart (as one
movement)' [I'm not sure this is anything more
than a word game really — when we cut things
apart, we have assumed that they are together, and
they become together in the sense of both being
parts of what was once whole]. Identity is a
matter of phenomena rather than individuals and is
thus multiple, 'diffracted through itself —
identity is
diffraction/différance/differing/deferring/differentiating'
[note 30 tells us that 'diffraction, as a physical
phenomenon, entails the entanglement/superposition
of different times and spaces'(49), and refers us
to Barad 1993 which is not however in the
reference list — maybe she means 2003 which is the
Signs article].
She wants to show this by demonstrating that
nature is 'intra/activity' [written with a forward
slash this time] is a matter of queer
performativity. This will help us see ourselves as
'always already a part of nature'(33) and that any
claim to label some acts as against nature 'erases
and demonises'[so everything human beings do is
natural, including the nasty bits?]. This
literally means that queer critters are queer, not
just odd, not that they engage in queer sexual
practices, but rather that identity and
relationality are queered — this implies that
identity as a relation can only be among entities
'understood [not] to precede their relations' (33)
[baffling note 31 expands this point to say that
identity is multiple and fluid, but is itself 'at
stake and at issue in what matters and what
doesn't matter', but this assumes that
'accountability is part of the ethico– ontological
relations and entanglements of Worlding' (50). It
really is an attempt to baffle us into compliance.
It's worse than academic discourse — it is
deliberately evasive and incantatory academic
discourse?]
To refer to queer critters is to break with
conventional definitions of both terms [make a cut
that cuts across cuts in her absurd language]. The
term critter offers conventional exclusions that
we wish to question, especially the line between
animate and inanimate. It also implies something
that is in contrast to and distinct from humans —
'contrary associations' [are they?], And it can be
meant both contemptuously and affectionately. Thus
critters 'are inherently destabilising and do not
have determinate identities, by definition'
[absurd philosophical exaggeration from a routine
mundane ambiguity].
[A list of queer critters ensues]. All of them
display 'uncanny communicative abilities' and
'bizarre causal relatings' which follow from their
phenomenal or entangled nature. Their consequent
agential reality and queer performativeness will
become clear.
The first one is lightning [!] which 'inspires
fear and awe' and may be associated with the
beginnings of life in the organic soup, or with
experiments that go wrong as in Frankenstein. It
looks like 'an archetypal "act of nature"' causing
direct deaths and fires [so act of nature here is
a term validated by the insurance industry?]. Its
performances are queer, as her colleague, V Kirby,
explains — it might show a certain logic in not
striking in the same place twice [really? a
logic?], although this is denied by some
scientists. An 'intriguing communication, a sort
of stuttering chatter' (34) precedes any lightning
strike [Deleuze's 'dark precursor'], as with St
Elmo's Fire or ball lightning. It's common to
assume that it originates in a cloud and is
discharged towards the ground, but this assumes
there is some optimal path for the discharge.
Instead 'according to experts', there is more of
an 'arcing disjuncture that runs in both an upward
and downward direction', and objects on the ground
can initiate strikes by extending 'upward moving
"leaders"' to a spark travelling downward'. Some
clot called Uman explains this 'in terms of speech
acts', so that lightning starts from the cloud
without any knowledge of what is below, being
unaware of objects until it nears them, and
awareness produces the final connection projecting
upward. Barad wants to know 'what kind of bizarre
communication is at work here' [anthropomorphism I
would say] — she prefers 'some kind of nonlocal
communication' (35), 'by some mechanisms
scientists have yet to fully explain', although we
do know that electrons are stripped from atoms and
gathering different places producing a massive
charge, not a unidirectional one yet though. That
time she quotes Discovery Channel to
repeat the explanation about both upward and
downward. She renders this as 'it is as though [!]
objects on the ground are being hailed by the
cloud's interpellative address'. The discharge is
not continuous but tracks between upper and lower
parts of the channel. This is 'an enlivening and
indeed lively response to difference if ever there
was one'. We don't know the mechanism, but
apparently 'awareness lies at the crux of this
strangely animated inanimate relating' — because
the ground can be seen to be 'animated into an
awareness of its would-be interlocutor'. The
message is being sent, but it is still unspecified
so conventional [!] sender and recipient notions
do not apply. Lightning is somehow 'on the razor's
edge between animate and inanimate' [note 38, page
50, discusses the expansionary notion of a field,
but says there are still bizarre features and
puzzles about electrical fields — such as the fact
that they don't seem to be big enough to generate
lightning flashes. Linear causation is challenged
in favour of 'a division of separate polarities'.
Kirby says that scientists '"are now looking to
outer space for the answer"'].
Let's look at stingrays and clairvoyancy.
Apparently stingrays can anticipate a message
which has been addressed to them because they
'"unlock themselves in readiness"', as a kind of
generalisation from a receptor cell [this is Kirby
again, presumably comparing this to her highly
simplified version of human communication as a
matter of SR links]. Apparently these paradoxical
cases can be extended, by Kirby. She talks about a
group of scholarship recipients [presumably human
ones] having to explain their intellectual
projects to benefactors — in her case
deconstructive criticism. A young biologist before
her talked about stingrays and how cells talk to
neighbouring cells via special receptor cells
which require particular keys or messages,
producing an effect of '"some mysterious
clairvoyancy"' (36). Kirby realises that this
might involve an entangled identity of human
proportions, so the biologists somehow had
anticipated her own intellectual labours — '"what
infectious algorithm had already brought us
together before our actual meeting?"'. Barad says
this is a 'scandalous'mixing of different
phenomena, and Kirby gets there through 'a
materialist reading of Derrida's grammatology',
where she says quantum paradoxes, whether those of
lightning, stingrays or humans, have to be denied
any empirical validity because that degree of
ontological complexity would be bewildering, and
needing domestication. She argues that properly
understood 'as a positive science', deconstruction
would reveal 'the liveliness of the world in a way
that speaks to my agential realist account of
worlding', that entangled relations and not just
human ones. She has been in conversation with
Kirby ever since, as 'untimely collaboration… One
of a multitude of entangled performances of the
world's worlding itself' (37).
[Kirby has four books in the references — 1997
Telling Flesh: The Substance of the Corporeal.
Routledge; 2001 Quantum Anthropologies in L
Simmons ed Derrida Down Under. Dunmore press
Palmerston; 2006 Judith Butler: live theory.
Continuum; 2011 Quantum Anthropologies. Life at
Large. Duke University Press. Much of the stuff on
page 36 seems to come from Kirby 2001].
Pfiesteria pisicidia[P], a
microorganism, a one celled predator that can
seemingly transform from animal to plant and back
again, implicated in a mass killing of fish in
North Carolina. It is apparently a dinoflagellate,
unicellular and microscopic, sometimes producing a
toxic red tide. They are 'neither plant nor animal
but can act as both'. They can photosynthesise and
also eat other organisms, changing their habits
according to varying environments, and also
changing the way they reproduce, including
sexually [here, the references to an unpublished
version of Schrader 2010, which has apparently
been published in Social Studies of Science
2010/40/2. The references also have her doctoral
thesis, and a 2008 paper delivered to the American
Anthropological Association]. Their appearance
caused a kind of scientific hysteria because
scientistss were unable to identify its basic
features or agree about its life-cycle. They are
not even sure if they did cause the deaths of
millions of fish, so there are 'real-world
concerns at stake'. Policymakers can only wait and
see, but for Schrader this is a dangerous
position, assuming that science will always deal
with certainties, and that gaps in knowledge will
be filled in [the notes have an example of where
this happened though] . In this case, 'its very
species being is indeterminate', that there is
ontological indeterminacy not just epistemological
uncertainty. The species is inherently
indeterminate and can never be unambiguously
separated from its environment. Rather than having
a definite life history, it seems to vary
according to what needs to be done — they cannot
be made to kill fish for example, but only do so
in particular circumstances. The toxic variant
seems to be different from other variants.
Schrader argues that there is no simple emitter
transmitter receiver model [again] to
explain these events, and trying to define P's
procedures in such terms would preclude 'the kinds
of toxic agential performances' in which they
engage [assuming indeterminacy that escapes simple
models is an ontological problem]. There is
apparently another procedure in a laboratory that
does not impose deterministic models, but allow P
to 'engage in heterogeneous temporal and
nondeterministic causal relatings'. What this
means is that they don't see toxicity as an
inherent property of a particular life stage, but
that P can be understood as a set of performances
belonging to '"an assemblage of morphs"[quoting
the unpublished version of Schrader 2010].
Particular temporal manifestations '"cannot be
isolated from the intra-actions that bring them
about"' [so she is happily using Barad's terms] —
the apparent fixed categories can transform into
one another, where toxicity is affected both by
present environments but also by the history of
the organism, rendered as '"the effects of
indeterminable intra-action that have led to P's
current material mode"'. Recent contacts with
fish, apparently, produce different action towards
fish newly encountered, implying '"a biochemical
memory"'. This in turn means there is a temporal
dimension in their relations with their
environment. [Coldn't we have used the less
mysterious locust here?]
To Barad, this shows how responsible laboratory
practices must deal with agential performances.
This is a form of responsibility which 'entails
providing opportunities for the organism to
respond' [not asking if it is reponssible to
'sacrifice' them] . They do not respond to
deterministic models but 'insist that their
agential performances be taken into account'. It
has to be a particular performative account at
that, not an assumption that we can see
performances as effects in the old causal sense.
They are 'choices… Not simply deterministic
causality, acausality, or no causality' (39).
Instead there is a particular mode of causality as
'iterative intra-activity' [with a reference to
Barad's book] and this can be an inheritance,
introducing temporality. In the right
circumstances, things like deadly toxins are seen
as 'cutting together'. Specific matters have to be
included [like these?] if the experiment is to be
repeatable. Clearly ethics are involved as well,
woven together with good responsible scientific
practice [which she renders as woven with
'justice–to–come'] [weird and anthropomorphic
again for me, simple determinist models have to be
replaced by more complex determinist models
including past states].
The atom can be seen as queer — inherently
indeterminate, not just strange. This queerness
emerged with quantum physics. Böhr applied the
idea of energy quanta to matter and developed a
new model of the atom to replace Rutherford's
solar system model. Electrons occupy discrete or
quantised orbits around the nucleus and there are
a finite number of discrete energy levels.
Electron jumps between levels emit photons with
different frequencies, and this can be used to
identify the atom. The emission spectrum of
hydrogen was one of the first to be predicted and
it was that that earned the Nobel Prize. However
there is further queerness. Each line in the
spectrum with a given colour results from an
electron making a leap or jump, but what is this
leap? In ordinary discourse 'quantum leap' means a
substantial qualitative leap, but the quantum is
of course a very small area. The thing about
electron leaps is that they are discontinuous,
with electrons changing energy levels 'without
having been anywhere in between! Quantum leap is a
discontinuous movement'. The emission of the
photon is similarly problematic. For Böhr,
electrons do not act a bit like planets around the
sun, but instead occupy 'one of a set of discrete
energy levels at a time' (40). Following a leap to
a lower level, excess energy is emitted as a
photon, but not continuously [by definition] — so
at what point is the photon released? Not when the
electron is in passage between two energy levels,
because it never is. Not when it first gets
released because it does not know where it is
going to end up [higher or lower] before it makes
the leap. The emission of the photon cannot be
seen as an energy conservation device because this
would involve 'a strange causality' [for the same
reason — energy would have to be conserved before
the leap happened]. There is 'an inherent
discontinuity', and Barad wants to extend this as
'(constitutive of all intra-actions)' [still at
the quantum level?].
A quantum discontinuity is not just the opposite
of the continuous, not just a displacement in
space. The rupture itself 'helps constitute the
heres and nows and not once and for all'. So it's
not just that electrons appear here and then there
without having been anywhere in between, but that
'here – now, there–then have become unmoored'. If
we cannot deploy conventional causality to follow
cause into effect, as an unfolding of existence,
we cannot 'orient oneself in space or in time? [In
theoretical physics]. Can we even continue to
presume that space and time are still "there" ?'
Overall there is a dizzying destabilising, and
existence itself seems indeterminate, somewhere
between possibility and impossibility, producing
'the open-ended becoming of the world which
resists acausality as much as determinism'
[acausality is an interesting category, presumably
one that is of special interest to physicists who
do not wish to abandon causality altogether
because it would have awful consequences for the
Newtonian world]. Not only that, 'the nature of
change changes with each intra-action' (41),
implying quite a different sort of change from the
normal which takes place in space and time. As a
results, existence is not just some manifold that
evolves in space and time, but should be
understood instead as 'iterative intra-active
becomings of spacetimemattering' [note 48, page
51, just really reasserts this argument saying
that space and time are not just there but are
constituted through 'interactive performances of
the world']. We can see entanglements in this
[non-Euclidean] way as well as 'enfoldings of
spacetimematterings'.
Quantum entanglement is characteristic of quantum
mechanics, and the main reason it has to depart
from classical thought, as Schrödinger once
argued. Derrida seems to say [!] something similar
about pasts having never been present, and futures
which are not just reproductions of forms of
presence. Feynman has said that the phenomena of
quantum mechanics are '"absolutely impossible to
explain in any classical way"'.
However 'physicists now claim to have empirical
evidence that it is possible not only to change
the past, but to change the very nature of being
itself in the past', in the quantum eraser
experiments. According to Böhr, there are no
inherent ontological identities for quantum
objects which can be both particles and waves, so
identity is 'not given, but rather performed'. The
two slit apparatus shows this [summarised page
41], so waves and particles are not distinct. The
results apply with atoms, neutrons or photons. It
is not like macro diffraction though because
'particles don't "interfere" with one another
(they can't occupy the same place at the same
time)' (42) and are never sent through the slits
at the same time anyway so they never encounter
each other. The problem then is to explain waves
[which classically do show interference patterns].
If we were able to watch each electron going
through the slit, as Einstein proposed in his
[gedanken] '"which – slit" device', we would
be able to see that the entity would be revealed
to be definitely contradictory — a particle
at the slit, and a wave at the screen. Böhr
disagreed and argued instead for
'complementarity', where something can be either a
wave or a particle 'depending on how it is
measured' because it becomes entangled with the
measuring apparatus. If we add which-slit
detectors to a simple two slit experiment,
electrons will perform like particles, showing the
dependence on the experimental apparatus. This
replaces contradiction with complementarity 'and
enabled objective results to be obtained'. The nub
is that we should not refer to waves or particles
as objective referents with separate
characteristics, but rather refer to a phenomenon,
implying emergent entanglement or inseparability
of object and apparatus.Böhr came to this from
philosophical speculation about how concepts work
and how they come to mean what they mean [with a
reference back to her own 2007 book — I don't
remember it as being particularly clear there,
unless she means the bit about humanism?]. The two
slit detector experiment has been much discussed
ever since as 'the gedanken (thought) experiment
of its time' [apparently, 'it could exist only in
the rarefied realm of pure thought']. But now it
can actually be performed in the lab — 'without
going into too many details' we have a two slit
device and a which-slit detector where the which
slit measurement does not disturb the motion of
the atom, but considers only some of its internal
parts. [It looks ingenious — the atom passes
through a laser beam which raises one of its
electrons to a higher level. Particular devices —
'"micromaser cavities"' are placed at each slit,
and they force the photon to go back to the lower
energy level as the atom passes through — this is
a signal, made by the photon as it's left in the
cavity, so we know which slit the atom went
through {with minimal interference}. If we run the
experiment without this which-slit detector we get
a diffraction pattern, but with the which-slit
detector, we get particles just as Böhr predicted
{the implication is that it is the presence of the
measuring apparatus which produces this change,
but it is not a human observer}. For Barad 'this
is direct empirical evidence that identity is not
fixed and inherent, but performative' (43)].
Böhr explains performance in terms of quantum
entanglement of the apparatus and the object of
measurement. It is not just that things behave
differently when measured differently. There is
only ever the phenomenon where apparatus and
object are already inseparable. This conception
can explain apparently impossible things. What if
we can erase the evidence in the cavities
[above] after the atom has gone through? It seems
that if we do, we revert to wave patterns just as
if there were no which-slit detector, but this
means that we've determined the nature of the
particle afterwards — 'the entity's very identity
has been changed'. This is 'empirical
evidence'that the identity or ontology of the atom
is never fixed 'but is always open to future and
past reworkings'.
It is actually not correct to talk about having
changed the past, or erased information. A more
careful interpretation, not so based on
conventional assumptions about being and time will
see it differently. Assuming 'a metaphysics of
presence' with 'individually determinate objects'
makes erasure of information and effects facing
backwards inexplicable, implying some strange
reverse causality or instantaneous communication,
'spooky action-at-a-distance causality'.
The conventional ontology is at fault after
a'diffractive reading [of] insights from
physics and poststructuralist theory through one
another'. If we do that we can 'elaborate'
Butler's performativity theory 'beyond the realm
of the human' (44), which we should do anyway even
to explain the human. This will make us rethink
notions such as materiality, agency and causality.
We can resolve the paradoxes with the quantum
eraser evidence in this way, and this will give
'deconstructionism empirical traction'. We have to
make 'the wager that the radical reverberations of
deconstructionism are not merely perverse
imaginings of the human mind or of culture but
are, in fact, queer happenings of the world' [note
54, page 51 says that Kirby 2011 would agree with
this and she even provides 'compelling evidence
that the story can be told from within
deconstructive theory']. Such a reading would help
us see that the past and future are not
modifications of the present, not involving
production or reproduction of presence in
Derrida's terms. So the experimenter has not
changed a past that had already been present by
erasing the information. Instead, 'the past was
never simply there to begin with and the future is
not simply what will unfold' instead both are
'iteratively reworked and enfolded through the
iterative practices of spacetimemattering' [in
other words pixie dust]. Both space and time exist
only in phenomena, never as some outside
determinate. In this way, 'the evidence is against
the claim' that events are erased or recovered.
The diffraction pattern produced after erasing
information is not the same as the '"original"',
it is not just simply evident, but requires
tracing from 'extant' entanglements [measurement
has cut these entanglements, and we need to find
its traces?]. Traces of measurement remain even if
information is erased, but 'it takes work to make
the ghostly entanglements visible'. The past is
neither closed nor present. Past and present are —
guess what — 'iteratively reconfigured and
enfolded through the world's ongoing
intra-activity' not connected by any determinate
relationships, not definitely located in space or
time. Phenomena are material entanglements, and
are 'enfolded and threaded through'
spacetimematterings. [So sometimes such matterings
produce phenomena — but not always? The other way
around? Phenomena belong with other
materialisations, and then produce further more
empirical materialisations? There has to be some
notion of the virtual behind all this?
'Materialisation' is certainly ambiguous]. A
diffraction pattern might return, but this is not
going back or restoration of the past. Memory is
always written into the fabric of the world, held
by the world. It consists of 'sedimented
enfoldings of iterative intra-activity', and the
world 'is its memory (enfolded materialisation)'
[so everything is material — but the material is
itself several things?].
In conclusion [thank God for that] there are many
challenges to classical ontology, defined as 'a
worldview that posits the existence of discrete
entities that interact with one another the
locally determinate causal fashion, wherein
changes in the result of one event (the causing)
causing [sic] another event (the effect) and
causes effect the motion of entities moving
through space in accord with the linear flow of
time' [so we have to accept all of those together,
or intra-action — there can be no modification of
classical views, no exceptions, no probabilistic
findings, nothing typical and marginal?]. Further
implications are that the world is composed of
individual objects, properties and boundaries are
determinate, space occupies a given volume, time
is linear, effects follow causes [by definition,
but even Hegel knew that this was a problem
because effects turn into causes of their own].
All of these are challenged by 'nature's queer
performances' (45) like the example she has given
— oh and human beings and their 'practices,
identities, and species being' [but they are not
subject to conventional causality because of
culture and language — it is not the same
indeterminacy as with the activities of a
dinoflagellate].
We have seen 'uncanny communicative abilities' and
'queer causal relatings' which are inexplicable if
we stick with independent entities or discrete
agents with an external environment. In each of
the cases considered we have a challenge to a
conception of time as '"homogenous flow of self
identical moments, in which are caused by
definition proceeds its effect"' [Schrader 2010].
Instead we need a quantum ontology, 'an agential
realist ontology' based on the existence of
phenomena as 'performative entanglements of
spacetimemattering', and only they can account for
the performances considered. These findings do not
just apply to the microscopic, although there have
been several attempts to domesticate nature's
queerness by Barad's critics. But queerness is
always threatening to leak out and contaminate
normal life. Instead we should appreciate it
'across divisions of scale and familiarity' as we
did with what looks like an everyday macroscopic
phenomenon like lightning — it 'nonetheless
exhibits the kinds of queer behaviours that atoms
do in the microcosmic domain' [well, she has
decided they can both be described as queer, which
is itself variously described as relating to
indeterminacy or apparent inexplicability in terms
of classic theories]. She thinks that more 'closet
indeterminacies might be lurking in the presumably
straightforward classification of micro and macro'
[once she applies her terminology even more
widely].
She is particularly interested in deconstruction,
via Kirby and Schrader which permit Derrida to
engage with these queer behaviours. She insists
that there is now 'the possibility of empirical
support for deconstructive ideas like différance'.
She does not agree with those who argue that
deconstruction has itself deconstructed empiricism
— this is a 'common mis/understanding' (46). There
are materialist readings of deconstruction that
'open up the empirical to reworkings' away from
conventional understandings [so what is the
empirical exxactly?] . Empirical claims should not
be ruled out but are indeed understood to be
'particular intelligible articulations of the
world (with all due regard to all the various
qualifications required to make good sense of this
claim)'[very evasive]. We should not see them as
relating to individual existing entities but to
'phenomena – in – their – becoming' [another type
of phenomena?]. Empirical claims here refer to
'radically open relatingness of the world worlding
itself' [repetitive and circular]. Of course,
'agential realism is not a straight read of
physics' but refers instead to 'a diffractive
investigation of differences that matter' arising
from reading physics, poststructuralist and
deconstructive theories 'through one another'[note
58, page 51, refers the notion of diffraction as a
methodology back to chapter 2 of her book, and
says it is 'indebted to Haraway 1997'. It's not
the same as 'social constructivist critique
because 'it doesn't presume to take a position
outside of science but rather constructively and
deconstructively engages with science from the
inside (not uncritically but not as critique)'
focusing on 'ontology, epistemology, and ethics as
well as methodology' — there are the usual
problems about which of these is the most
important, and whether or not extending out from
methodology confuses the issue or not. So
diffraction might be acceptable as an ontology,
but not as a methodology, or a methodology not as
an ethics?]
Physics 'wonderfully deconstructs itself,
reopening and re-figuring foundational issues'
[note 59 says this makes Derrida's point that
'deconstruction is not a method but what texts
do'].
Focusing on the key ethical issues, 'Derrida's
notions of "justice – to – come" and différance
haunt this essay'. Agential realism means that
differentiation is not just about cutting apart,
but also cutting together, in one move, 'a matter
of entanglement'. And entanglements are not just
intertwinings but are 'irreducible relations of
responsibility', removing especially lines between
self and other, past and present, here and now,
all cause and effect. Just like quantum
dis/continuity, agential cuts do not offer
absolute separation but also a '"holding together"
of the disparate itself' without defacing
heterogeneity, 'offering some unity before
'"synthetic"' junctions, conjunctions and
disjunctions [all of this referring back to
Derrida]. Agential separability is both
differentiating and entangling as one move, not a
sequential process. Agential cuts rework relations
of joining and disjoining. Separability means
'irreducible heterogeneity that is not undermined
by the relations of inheritance that hold together
the disparate without reducing difference to
sameness' [largely definitional matter again?].
The very notion of differentiating is queered and
rethought, requiring a new accountability not
based on some fixed identity or fixed intervals or
origin, indeed an 'ac/counting' [why this split?],
looking at what materialises and what is excluded.
There can be no simple calculation based on the
notion that individual identities can be added to
or equated with each other, we should not identify
individual causal factors or assign blame to
particular causes. Causality is itself 'an
altogether queer matter'. As a result
'accountability is an ethico- onto –
epistemological commitment to understand how
different cuts matter in the processes of worlding
and the entanglements of spacetimematterings'
(47). We should be accountable, but not from some
external position only by operating agential
separability, differences within. The can be no
mathematics of identity with simple substitutions
or transitivities among individual elements.
There can be no '"acts against nature"' because
this entails absolute exteriority again. But there
is no outside of nature. Thinking and language use
are themselves acts of nature. This 'is not to
reduce culture to nature, but to reject the notion
that nature is inherently inadequate and in
particular lacking in value and meaning, and so
requires culture as its supplement (Kirby)' [this
is entirely an ethical point then? We might want
to argue about hierarchies, but it is absurd to
say that culture does nothing to add value or
meaning to human actions]. We might understand
'culture as something nature does' [note 60 quotes
Böhr as arguing that humans are part of that
nature they wish to understand, and recommends
Kirby on the nature/culture divide, understanding
Derrida that there is no outside of the text as
'"there is no outside of nature"' — which surely
is the opposite of what Derrida is arguing?]. If
we rework these binaries, this 'frees up space for
moral outrage directed at specific acts of
violence against humans and nonhumans' and how
they are differentiated or equated [idealist
challenging of the binaries will produce a new
tolerance].
Entanglements are not just interconnections but
'specific material relations of the ongoing
differentiating of the world'. They are also
'relations of obligation — being bound to the
other — enfolded traces of othering'. Others are
'irreducibly and materially bound to, threaded
through the "self" — a diffraction/dispersion of
identity'. This entangled relation is the same as
Derrida's différance.
So there is an ethics of entanglement which means
we can and must rework 'the material effects of
the past and the future' there is no absolute
redemption but we can productively reconfigure and
rework im/possibilities. If we change the past, we
do not erase marks on bodies which are sedimented
material effects 'written into the flesh of the
world' [so what's the point? No easy
redemptions?]. We do have debt 'to those who are
already dead and those who are not yet born' and
this 'cannot be disentangled from who we are'
[massive guilt must ensue]. We should realise that
differentiating is a material act, that is not
about radical separation but really 'about making
connections and commitments' [which seems to
justify any kind of identity politics you fancy —
by insisting that men are different from women you
are really making connections with and commitments
to them?]
The summary, rather perversely right at the end,
says that she wants to develop queerness as a
radical questioning of identity and binaries to
make all sorts of impossibilities possible.
Queerness lies in the very heart of spacetimeetc.
She sees moralism as based on a nature culture
divide and human exceptionalism and this 'causes
injury to humans and nonhumans alike, is a genetic
carrier of genocidal hatred and undermines
ecologies of diversity necessary for flourishing'.
There are loads of notes apart from the ones I
mentioned. Note 5 says that after initial
ambiguity, there is now an acceptable
classification for social amoeba — quoting a
Wikipedia entry [ontological indeterminacy didn't
last long then?] She notes (6) that in a
particular article, notions of language or
morality are found regularly in literature on
social amoeba. Note 7 likes 'social amoeba'as a
provocation to human exceptionalism. Note 8
provides a definite '"amoebic morality"' avoiding
colonial moves to cover humans, and leading to
questions about what the other can teach us and
who we speak for. Note 12 offers definitions of
natural and unnatural from the Online
Dictionary. Note 13 subdivides bestial acts
into those that might include acting as if one
were nonhuman, and the law gets into trouble here.
She knows she is being 'playful ironic' in her use
of 'as if', and notes that moral authorities do
not use the term, as when Himmler said that Jews
just are the same as lice, reflecting the long
tradition to equate Jews with animals, especially
parasites. She argues that we need to disrupt
binaries in order to disrupt 'the calculus of
exterminism and killability', where a binary
involves a radical difference of esteem. Note 14
says that queerness does not entail desire, that
this is human exceptionalism, and the other forms
of desire might exist. Note 17 tributes the
'important ethics notion of "making killable"' to
Haraway 2008. Note 22 says that the abjection of
the other does not necessarily mean a hierarchy,
because 'equivalence relations can be effectively
enrolled'. Note 28 says that phenomena 'are
ontologically primitive relations — relations
without pre-existing relata', where there is a
mutual ontological dependence of relata and
relation, 'the result of specific intra-actions' —
lovely circular and self propping terms. Note 30
says that diffraction in the usual sense, 'as a
physical phenomenon' entails the
entanglement/superposition of different times and
spaces', and refers to the elusive Barad 1993.
Note 34 says that Haraway has insisted that we do
animal studies and eco-criticism, the result of
challenging the boundary between the animate and
the inanimate. Similarly the biological tends to
be preferred over the physical in academic
disciplines [ a bit of inter-faculty micropolitics
here?] . Note 43 supports the argument that queer
identity should be seen 'as an empty placeholder
for an identity that is still in progress and has
as yet to be fully realised' [citing Halperin].
Queer politics should not become referential or
positive or concrete, but see queerness 'as a
resistant relation rather than as an oppositional
substance'. Note 56 acknowledges that classical
physics can still be used to explain certain
behaviours of these identities, lightning for
example, but so can quantum physics. Quantum
physics cannot be just accepted as perfectly
applicable but only to a micro domain. Questions
of scale are not simple.
Barad page
|
|