Notes on: Bourdieu, P. (1989). Social Space and
Symbolic Power. Sociological Theory 7 (1):
14 – 25
Dave Harris
His work is 'constructivist structuralism…
Structuralist constructivism', but not in the
sense of Sausssure or Lévi-Strauss. He thinks
there are objective structures independent of
consciousness and will. And he also thinks there
is a 'twofold social genesis… of schemes of
perception, thought and action which are
constituencies of what I call habitus and… social
structures… and particularly… fields and… groups,
notably those we ordinarily call social classes'
(14). There are different emphases in different
books that he's written over time. These two are
apparently incompatible points of view,
represented by the advice to treat social facts as
things, leaving out anything that appears to be an
object of knowledge or misrecognition, and, on the
other hand seeing the social world as
representations the agents have of it, with social
science just producing accounts of the accounts.
However, the contrast is rarely expressed
radically. Even Durkheim was aware that there was
a need to use logical categories and
classifications, sometimes as mere operational
ones. Schutz represents the subjectivist vision
best where the field of social scientist is
entirely seen as a meaning and relevance structure
of the human beings in it, using common sense
constructs and thought objects to act, requiring
sociologists to work only with '"constructs of the
second degree"' (15). Science has to break with
primary representations in the first case, but is
only a continuity of it in the second. Bourdieu
intends to try to overcome this split.
He sees the objective structures constructed by
sociologists in an 'objectivist moment' by setting
aside subjective representations of agents as the
basis for 'structural constraints that bear on
interactions'. However, subjective representations
are crucial for accounting for daily struggles
which maintain or transform those structures.
Hence a 'dialectical relationship'between
objectivist and subjectivist moments. However,
even if subjectivist moments are isolated as in
interactionism or ethnomethodological analysis,
they are still grasped sociologically by relating
them to positions they occupy in a structure of
agents.
This is to depart from substantialism (Cassirer) —
where there is no other reality than that
available to direct intuition and ordinary
experience. Instead, structuralism offers a
relational mode of thinking as in modern maths and
physics, where the real is not a matter of
substance but of relations, social reality is 'an
ensemble of invisible relations' which create a
space of positions external to each other, in
relation of proximity and distance, above, below
and in the middle. Sociology as objectivist
analysis is a typology. It is this he tried to
develop in Distinction.
This space is almost certainly unnoticed by the
reader of that book despite his using diagrams and
correspondence analysis. Substantialism is easier
to adopt, and there is a problem in constructing
social space. For example the chapter in Distinction
about the fractions of the dominant class tends to
be read as description of the various lifestyles
of those fractions, but they are really 'our
analysis of locations in the space of positions of
power… The field of power', which is also a break
with the ordinary idea of a ruling class.
Social space is like geographic space except
that proximity means neighbours have common
properties and distance means social distance.
Almost everywhere there is a tendency towards
spatial segregation, and some overlap between
social and geographic space. The two are not the
same, and people distanced in social space can
find themselves neighbours in physical space, with
a particular risk of masking social structures
behind empirical interaction. This is seen in
'strategies of condescension' for example where
agents in a higher position deny social distance
between them and others, although that distance
still persists: this gives them a certain profit
by being called unaffected or whatever and
combines the advantages of distance and
propinquity. So social relations like this are not
reducible to interactions.
Objective relations should be seen as the
relations between positions, a matter of
distribution of resources, which can become
effective or active ’like aces in a game of cards’
in the competition for scarce goods (17). After
empirical investigation (NB) he identified the
fundamental powers of economic capital in its
different forms, cultural capital, social capital
and symbolic capital — ‘the form that the various
species of capital assume when they are perceived
and recognised as legitimate’. Agents occupy
places in the overall social space on the first
dimension according to the volume of capital they
possess, and on the second dimension according to
the structure of this capital, the relative
weights of the different species of capital,
economic and cultural.
It would be a misunderstanding to think that the
classes on paper are real groups. Agents in the
social spaces do occupy similar positions in
similar conditions and have ‘similar
conditionings, and therefore have every chance of
having similar dispositions and interests and…
Practices that are themselves similar’. They might
have developed what ‘Goffman callsThe “sense of
one’s place”’, and people like to keep to their
place, keep their distance, not get too familiar,
even if this is ‘perfectly unconscious’ and
appears as ‘timidity or arrogance’ indeed
‘inscribed in bodies… Into the relation to the
body, to language and to time’, so often ignored
by ‘subjectivist vision’.
A sense of place and affinities of habitus at the
basis of all forms of cooperation, friendship,
marriage, associations and so on, and this leads
you to think that classes on paper are real
groups. Indeed, any political movement will have a
better chance of bringing people together as
agents who are in the same sector of social space.
But we can’t just deduce actions and interactions
from the structure. That would be to produce a
theoreticist error like the one you find in Marx,
A realist error -- what is needed instead is
political work to produce social classes as
permanent groups, making social classes, exerting
a theory effect, as in EP Thompson, where the
working class is an historical artefact . Of
course, there are limits to what one can
construct, both in theory and in practice.
However, the social reality that objectivists talk
about is also an object of perception and this
must be analysed by social scientists in terms of
its reality and how it is composed of perspectives
or points of view by different agents, how it
might appear as folk theories or what he calls
‘”spontaneous sociology”(18) as well as scientific
theories, Especially as these can acquire ‘a truly
real power of construction’. Objectivist breaks
with these spontaneous sociology constructions and
ideologies is necessary if we are to do more than
just work with the phenomenal vision of the social
world. This objectivist break has to be broken
with itself by reintroducing what had to be
excluded, ‘a sociology of the perception of the
social world… The construction of visions of the
world which themselves contribute to the
construction of this world… Points of view
[which]… are views taken from a certain point… from
a determinate position within social space’. These
will be different depending on the position of the
agent in social space.
There can be no universal subject, no
transcendental ego, because constructing a vision
of the world is ‘carried out under structural
constraints’. Of course the familiar world tends
to be taken for granted and perceived as natural,
but that is because the habitus of the agents, the
dispositions, are ‘essentially the product
of the internalisation of the structures of that
world’. Perceptive dispositions ‘tend to be
adjusted to position’ and this leads all agents,
even disadvantaged ones, to perceive the world as
natural and to accept it. There are no invariant
forms of perception or of construction, because
construction is not carried out in a social
vacuum, and cognitive structures are themselves
socially structured. The construction of social
reality is also a collective enterprise. Unless
you take into account the effects of social space,
you cannot see the limits of the particular points
of view.
Representations of agents are required through
‘the lasting experience of a social position’
(19). Habitus produces practices and perceptions
and appreciation of those practices and in doing
so ‘expresses the social position in which it was
elaborated’. This means that the practices and
representations it produces are ‘available for
[objective]classification’, Once we know the
classificatory schemes we can understand the
social meaning. Habitus gives us not only the
sense of one’s own place but the sense of the
place of others [even for social agents
themselves]. When agents classify themselves, they
presuppose a classification system, assuming that
things go well together like clothes, drinks,
sports and friends and that their choice of
consumer goods, say, are ‘homologous to the
position they themselves occupy in social space’ —
‘Nothing classifies somebody more than the way he
or she classifies’. When we classify we can
perceive the relations between these practices and
positions in social space and this seems
commonsense, self-evident.
Objectively, the world does not present itself ‘as
pure chaos… totally devoid of necessity’ open to
being constructed in any way you choose. Nor is it
totally structured. There are different principles
of vision and division ‘for example economic
divisions and ethnic divisions’ and ‘economic and
cultural factors of the greatest power of
differentiation’. However, these differences are
‘never so great’ [in potency] that other
principles of division cannot be used — ‘ethnic,
religious, or national ones, for instance’ [So
maybe he really is saying that racial divisions
can predominate and produce a kind of vertical
slicing?]
However, despite this ‘potential plurality of
possible structurings’’ there is a simple
mechanism which simplifies it. The agents that
have different properties are ‘systematically
linked among themselves’, so that those with
certain tastes tend to have other tastes — so that
having a particular tasting drink or leisure
‘makes you “look” like a traditional member of the
old bourgeoisie’ (20). ‘Differences function as
distinctive signs and as signs of distinction’, in
a way beyond just deliberate conspicuous
consumption. In other words the social world is an
objective symbolic system, ‘organised according to
the logic of difference, of differential distance…
A symbolic space, a space of lifestyles and status
groups characterised by different lifestyles’.
So we have a ‘double structuring’. On the
objective side properties attributed to agents
appear in combinations that have unequal
probabilities, so that those who can master
languages are more likely to be found in
particular occupations [not his actual example].
On the subjective dimension schemes of perception
and appreciation especially those in language
express relations of symbolic power for example in
pairs of adjectives which organise taste [his
examples are ‘heavy/light, bright/dull’] In
various domains. There are always indeterminacy
and vagueness and ‘semantic elasticity’ always
statistical connections and ‘variations in time… objective
elements of uncertainty’ and thus a plurality of
visions of the world. This also provides ‘a base
for symbolic struggles over the power to produce
and to impose the legitimate vision of the world’
[he thinks symbolic struggle is at a maximum in
the United States, and it is this that has been
exposed particularly well by Goffman].
Symbolic struggles can take an objective form, for
example where a group acts to make itself more
visible and powerful, Or, more individually,with
the strategies of presentation of self in Goffman,
designed to improve self-image and also ‘the image
of one’s position in social space’ which Bourdieu
thinks that Goffman ‘overlooked’. On the
subjective side there are efforts to transform
categories of perception and appreciation,
different forms of classification words and names,
different principles of vision and division,
different examples of the theory effect [slightly
obscure examples at first relating to insults
among the Kabylia].(21) Political efforts to
revalorise the past would be an example. The
symbolic efforts are connected to economic and
cultural capital, since ‘symbolic capital is
nothing other than economic or cultural capital’,
and legitimation of the social world is not just
deliberate propaganda or imposition, but rather
‘structures of perception and appreciation… which
tend to picture the world as evident’. ‘Objective
relations of power tend to reproduce themselves in
the relations of symbolic power’, over the
production of common sense, the monopoly of
legitimate naming, titles of nobility. Again
subjectivism does not grasp this well, since it is
not a case of just adding individual orders
together, because there is a hierarchy, and some
people have more power to impose values, some even
hold a monopoly, some symbols are officially
sanctioned. Credentials fit here as ‘a piece of
universally recognised and guaranteed symbolic
capital, good on all markets’
The state and the legal system can consecrate
particular kinds of symbolic capital and confer
‘an absolute universal value’ (22). Official
discourse diagnoses first, asserting what a
personal thing is, for every person, ‘thus
objectively’ it follows that there are directives
about what people have to do, and finally
interpretations of what people actually have done
as in official records. Official discourse
therefore ‘imposes a point of view, that of
institution’, and claims it as legitimate which
everyone has to recognise. The state engages
centrally in these processes of codification,
producing transcendent points of view overcoming
particular points of view, as Weber noticed,
although we can extend his formulation to include
monopolising‘ legitimate symbolic violence’. Even
so, they never achieve absolute monopoly and
conflicts between symbolic powers remain [rather
confusing bit here referring to archaic societies
which feature persisting dualist oppositions
between masculine and feminine, high and low and
so on. Also a hint that the world is never finally
made, so contradictions are continually emerging?]
Symbolic power has a ‘form par excellence… the
power to make groups’ (23) either consecrating
those that are already established, or bringing
some into being, as with Marxism. It has to be
based on the possession of symbolic capital which
conveys social authority as a form of credit.
Authority can often come only after ‘a long
process of institutionalisation’ which ends in a
representative structure for the group. Symbolic
efficacy also depends on the links between the
vision and reality — that is ‘the objective
affinities between the agents who have to be
brought together’ as in the theory effect.
Symbolic power only works with words, but it also
has to be ‘adequate to things, a matter of
‘consecration or revelation’, selecting or
designating a group or a region or a nation, for
example. Classification is a fundamental dimension
of class struggle, political power is precisely
about making ‘visible and explicit social
divisions that are implicit’, Making groups to
manipulate the structure of society as a
performative power, a collective agent.
How does a spokesperson come to be invested with
the power to act in the name of the group ‘which
he or she produces by the magic of the slogan, the
watchword or the command… As an incarnation of the
collective?’. They must somehow personify ‘a
social fiction to which they give life’ (24), even
if only by the fact of speaking publicly or
officially and being recognised is entitled to do
so.
[Finally, a plea for complexity]. ‘Complexity lies
within social reality and not in a somewhat
decadent desire to say complicated things’ (24)
questioning of simple ideas is needed in the
social sciences because we can’t ‘satisfy
ourselves with the commonplaces supplied to us by
a commonsense experience or by a familiarity with
a scholarly tradition’
|
|