Notes on: DeLanda, M.(2006)
A New
Philosophy of Society.Assemblage
Theory and Social Complexity, London:
Continuum.
[important claims right at the
end]
This is an exercise in social
ontology, which is normally seen as realist—‘a
commitment to the mind – independent existence of
reality’ (1).However, it is necessary to admit that
human minds also have a role in maintaining social
entities.But
they are autonomous from the conceptions we have
of them.The
‘real history and internal dynamics’ of social
entities need to be studied adequately.However
it is clear the categories also affect behaviour
when people become aware of them, but this shows
that the referents of general conceptions can
shift—there is a whole network of organisations
and institutions which supports these categories
providing a realist context [the example is
hyperactive children and the institutional
practices that classify them, 2].These
practices and networks must be seen as conception
independent, unlike as in social constructivism.They are
assemblages, constructed by definite processes,
and ‘in which language plays an important but not
a constitutive role’(3).
Deleuze’s philosophy is the
basis of assemblage theory, even though he and
Guattari said little about it.The
concepts that might be used are dispersed
throughout the work, and the style often does not
allow ‘a straightforward interpretation’ (3).However,
there is no need to engage in excessive
hermeneutic analysis.Instead,
we can reconstruct Deleuze, providing different
definitions and arguments and ‘entirely different
theoretical resources’.If
necessary, the results might be described as
‘”neo-assemblage theory”’ (4).
The idea will be to explain how
wholes emerge that are not reducible to their
parts, while avoiding the flaws of rival
conceptions such as Hegelian totalities and other
forms of essentialism.The case
studies to be chosen involve the links between
micro and macro levels of reality, but avoiding
the reductionism of rival approaches, which
include the ‘phenomenological individualism of
social constructivism’ (4), and the
over-socialised notions of Parsons, Durkheim and
Marx.There
are even those who wish to reduce everything to an
intermediate level ‘such as praxis’ and this is
the stance of Giddens.There
are also specific analyses at different levels
between the micro and macro, where the ontological
status is unclear—assemblage theory can be used to
model them.Assemblages
can emerge from individuals, or from institutions,
from communities, from organisations, cities and
other entities.Social complexity needs to be preserved,
although the analysis is restricted to Anglo
American examples.Larger scale organisations are not meant to
be seen in the geometric sense, but as extensive
properties.The
empirical capacities of entities are also
important.The
focus on ontology is justified since normally it
is left implicit.Thus ‘philosophers…can
greatly contribute to the job of ontological
clarification’ (7). [if only!]
Chapter one.Assemblages
against totalities
The organismic metaphor is
common, but unhelpful, since it works on the basis
of analogies.Spencer, and above all Parsons, have
developed this metaphor most fully, but in
connection with functionalism which has since been
rejected. [even Mertons' much more concrete
version?]However,
a general theory still persists that suggests that
wholes displays some totality or organic unity,
and that the parts gain meaning only by their
relations to these wholes—‘relations of
interiority’ (9).Similarly, the part has no meaning on its
own detached from the whole.There
are collectivities made up of selfsubsisting parts
and relations of exteriority, but they do not
count in this approach: they are mere aggregates
etc (cf the distinction between a statistical
aggregate and a social group).
Even Giddens remains influenced
by this structure, which connects behavioural
procedures, material resources and actual practice
as integral parts rather than as a mere aggregate:
‘The end result of this is a seamless whole in
which agency and structure mutually constitute one
another dialectically' (10).
Without such internal
relations, there can be no emergent properties for
Hegel and others, but complex interactions between
parts require heterogeneous combinations.We need
to consider the relations between parts as
involving capacities to interact, which are
limitless.These
capacities are not just constitutive parts of a
whole.This
leads us to assemblages in Deleuze, 'wholes
characterised by relations of exteriority' (10).Parts
may be detached from an assemblage and plugged
into another, and the properties of wholes cannot
be reduced to those of parts, since emergent
capacities relate the parts producing an
[empirical] synthesis.
Deleuze uses examples of
symbiotic relations between plants and insects in
ecosystems, not organisms.Wasps
and orchids must form necessary relations, but
these relations are still contingent, based on
empirical issues.Elements are heterogeneous, although this
might imply different values—in this way, more
phenomena can be grasped as assemblages, including
species and organisms themselves.
Assemblages are defined along
one axis of materiality - expressivity, which can
be combined or mixed.The
second dimension is territorialization -
deterritorialization, referring to the degree of
sharpness of the boundaries of an assemblage, the
stability of its identity.Again,
this can vary over time.
Social assemblages show these
qualities in face to face conversations, in
interpersonal networks and hierarchical
organisations, especially those in cities or
nation states.They have material components such as food,
labour, buildings, machinery.The
expressive components are not just linguistic ones
but include non-verbal behaviour, and matters such
as reputation or image, or the nature of
collective behaviour, or rituals that reinforce
legitimacy of hierarchies.Territorialization
has
a literal meaning in that interactions are always
located in particular places with boundaries, but
there are also non-spatial processes which
increase internal homogeneity—social selections
and sorting for example.Deterritorialization
arises from things such as the development of
communication technology which avoids geographical
boundaries.Territorialization
is important for producing permanent articulations
of wholes [persisting across space—and time?].There
are also 'specialised expressive entities such as
genes and words' (14) which similarly synthesise
wholes.Deleuze
insists that all entities can express themselves,
but human expressions are much more complex
following the appearance of these forms of
expression.[DeLanda
insists that atoms express themselves by creating
particular patterns in radiation as in a
spectograph].
Expression need not always be
functional [the example given here is that the
patterns produced by fingerprints have no
biological function, just an important social one,
but only once policing develops].However,
at certain thresholds, functionality increases
dramatically—the development of genetic codes; the
emergence of language.Each of
these can be seen as assemblages in their own
right, but they produce 'a second synthetic
process' (15) [also referred to as a double
articulation, 15] —coding.Social
hierarchies can be coded in various ways such as
traditional or rational.However,
‘many social assemblages [unlike biological
organisms] are not highly coded or highly
territorialized'(15).
There can also be decoding in
biology and sociology.Animal
behaviour need not be rigidly programmed, for
example in their sense of territoriality.Social
decoding can arise from informal conversations
where rules are suspended.In
neither case do codes define some essential
qualities—they are simply components among many
others.DeLanda
wants to demonstrate this by discussing language
'last and as a separate component' (16) in order
to deny its centrality.
Assemblages always exist in
populations which produce recurrent processes.Assemblages
then interact empirically with each other
producing some emergent properties.Larger
assemblages may also emerge from smaller ones
articulating together.This
implies that the macro - micro problems in
sociology can be bridged [transcended or
sidestepped really].Thus markets emerge as concrete
organisations made out of people and the goods
they exchange.Initially, they must be literally
territorialized.As urbanization intensifies, they become
articulated together into regional markets,
provincial markets and finally national markets.The
scale varies, and the articulation concerned is by
no means simple or functional [but uneven and
emergent].
Thus assemblages are made up of
self subsistent parts articulated by exterior
relations.They
have two main dimensions which help us see the
roles played by components—material or expressive,
stabilising or destabilising identity.A third
dimension can be added, involving 'processes in
which specialised expressive media intervene'
(19), which can produce flexibility or rigidity,
coding or decoding.All these are traceable to population
characteristics, and these include still further
synthetic processes.
Finally, it is important not to
reduce causality to linear causality ('same cause,
same effect, always') (19),when
speaking of the various mechanisms involved.For one
thing, social assemblages can involve reasons and
motives, and the subjective components need to be
explained.However,
it would be wrong to simply choose between
subjective notions and linear causality. Linear
causality has often been misleadingly connected
with logical implication.Instead,
causal relations are productive – this is not the
same as saying that one implies the other.Causes
can also involve complex entities, and changes in
some components can turn the entity into a cause.
Linear causality usually
involves atomistic events, but internal
organisation can produce modified effects—low
intensity ones, or amplified ones.Here
thresholds are important in producing effects.Sometimes,
they are low enough to register an effect every
time a cause operates, but there are other states
such as catalysis where different causes can lead
to the same effect.[The example is hormones stimulating growth
when applied to the tips that the plant and
inhibiting growth when applied to roots] (20).
The idea that causes always
produce the same effects can be challenged by
statistical causality.Here it
is a matter of acknowledging complex interfering
events in combination with causes, not internal
processes that modify.Together,
these processes lead us to reject the idea of the
'block universe'—'the world is a seamless web of
reciprocal action…A block of unlimited universal
interconnections' (19).
Material components usually
involve all these types of causal interactions,
while 'expressive ones typically involve
catalysis' (22).Language usually plays a catalytic role,
for example.This assumes complex serial organisations
such as the nervous system, but the catalytic role
of language is so important that special
explanations are required—reasons, motives.Weber
argued this in preserving room for both causal and
motivated action.Causal bits have been typically ignored
lately, part of the drive to see everything is a
text.However,
adequacy can involve assessments of causal
relevance—when interacting with material objects,
but also about making judgements about adequate
performance (23).Even reasons may look rather like causes in
the case of traditional actions, although other
types involved beliefs or desires.Typically,
however, both causal and meaning adequacy will be
involved, 'complex mixtures of causes, reasons and
motives' (24).Sometimes this complexity is lost in
reducing the meaning of action seen as rational—to
match means to ends clearly involves all sorts of
problem solving skills, including 'consideration
of relevant causal events' (24).Similarly,
traditional
routines may expressive congealed rational
understanding if they lead to ‘successful causal
interactions with material entities, such as
domesticated plants and soil’.
Social explanations must draw
on the full variety of causal interactions,
including the notion of thresholds to explain why
one individual might differ from another, and to
work with probabilistic notions.These
are important with human beings who may be making
intentional choices.However there are also ‘collective
unintended consequences’ producing statistical
results (24).With reasons, collective behaviour can be
explained by the affects of socialization, but
even this must be seen in a probabilistic terms:
‘the effects of socialization should always be
pictured as variable and a proper object of study
should be how this variation is distributed in a
given population’ (25).
[The same goes for capacities
though. In Intensive
Philosophy, these are seen as almost
accidental or random, necessarily in order to make
the case for emergence and haecceity. In social
assemblages it is possible to see capacities as
socially distributed though, as in Bourdieu’s
various ‘capitals’ – this bit is missing so far?.
NB DeLanda says below that Bourdieu overdoes the
point with his notion of habitus. Deciding between
them is an empirical matter of examining
variations?].
C2
Assemblages against essences
Essences are introduced in
different forms, as when general categories get
reified—‘taxonomic essentialism as opposed to its
platonic variety’ (26).The
example is the classification of creatures into
genus, species and individuals, as in Aristotle.The
trick is to identify necessary differences or
natural kinds.Recent evolutionary theory shows the
contingency and fuzziness of these essential
differences.Instead, each category is best seen as an
individual entity, on different scales.The
argument can be applied to chemistry as well,
replacing the notion of ‘hydrogen in general…[with]…the
objective reality of large populations of hydrogen
atoms’ (28).
Essentialism follows a flawed
method by operating inductively.Instead,
the historical processes that produce the entities
are required.Any assemblage is produced by a specific
history of territorialization and coding, and it
is always open to destabilisation.In this
sense, assemblages are always ‘unique singular
individuals’, differing only by scale (a flat
ontology).Individual
people, communities and organisations must all be
seen as individual entities (28).
Categories above that of genus,
such as kingdom or phylum involve abstract plans
which are non-metric or topological, ‘a space of
possibilities (the space of all possible
vertebrate designs, for example)’ (29).Possibilities
structured in this way, are better seen as
possible capacities.The possibility spaces can be studied as
phase spaces and this structure described
mathematically in terms of attractors, degrees of
freedom and the rest (see Intensive
Philosophy) Possibilities
may be highly constrained, as in the case of
minimising energy.Social spaces cannot yet be defined as
formally, but they may have ‘a much more complex
distribution of topological invariants
(attractors)’ (29).Invariants can also be described as
universal singularities.Distributions
of these replace the notion of genera, while
species can be defined as individual
singularities.The two kinds are separated by historical
differentiation not logical differentiation.
Deleuze uses the notion of a
diagram as a set of universal singularities, or
the equivalent of a body plan, with possibilities
and degrees of freedom.National
markets can be seen as an articulation of regional
markets, themselves connections of local markets,
with each category as an individual singularity.
Weber’s ideal types are the
equivalent of diagrams [and the example is types
of authority].The ideal types are not essences but are
best seen as ‘three universal singularities
defining “extreme forms” that authority structures
can take’ (30). The degrees of freedom correspond
to issues like the extent to which the office is
separated from the incumbent, and the degree of
routinization of activities.
The analysis of assemblages is
not simply a logical one, following from the
discovery of necessary differences, but must
involve ‘causal interventions in reality’ (31)
[the examples given are physical damage to cells.
Maybe pseudo-causal interventions in science labs
also fit as implied in Intensive
Philosophy? ].Social analysis should discover actual
mechanisms in operation [with actualisation used
in the Deleuzian sense]. The analysis of phase
space may be one of the resources which can be
used, and quasi causal operators need to be
understood as well as productive causes.Quasi
causes will be focused on in the book at the
expense of actual causal mechanisms, but actual
mechanisms need to be understood especially if
they lead to emergence, and then to discussion of
the macro and micro levels [an example of how the
correct formulation of a problem is crucial].
In the first place, there may
be more than two levels.Micro
and macro can therefore be used relativistically
to describe components and emergence, at whatever
spatial scale [there is an interesting note on
page 127 denying the usual reified notions of
macro and micro and citing a certain D Gerstein in
support].At
each stage, the macro emerges from the micro, but
this is not methodological individualism—there are
not just reified rational individuals in
assemblage theory, but populations and
‘subpersonal components’ (32).Further,
subjectivity is emergent and can become more
complex in assemblages—for example it gets
identified with formal roles in organisations,
since ‘the emergent whole reacts back and affects
[identities]’ (32). [Sounds like Bourdieu here on
the ways in which selection processes make the
rejected believe that they never wanted to join in
the first place].
Relations between parts and
wholes are not simple.Wholes
exist at a number of different scales, and parts
can belong to different wholes.Some
networks cut across others, others combine
together for political purposes such as collective
bargaining.There
can be hybrids of interpersonal networks and
institutionalised organisation.The
populations concerned vary as do the physical
locations.
Wholes react back causally on
parts, as Bhaskar has argued [a note on page 128
says that Bhaskar’s realism is ‘very close to
Deleuze’s’, but differs from it in that Bhaskar is
an essentialist, arguing that groups possess some
real essence or nature].In this
way, wholes provide constraints and resources for
parts, and ‘opportunities and risks’ (35) [I am
still not sure that this formalist approach really
gets to the mechanisms of matters such as class
domination specifically].Even deterritorialized
assemblages can affect their parts, but with a
diminished capacity, as a ‘weak link’ [a contact
with someone outside, linked to a reference about
how to get a job] (35).DeLanda
goes on to talk about low and high degrees of
solidarity [nearly Durkheim here]. Market places
are also locations with lots of weak links, and
economic constraints.
Wholes also exercise ‘causal
capacities’ by interacting with each other, as in
forming political coalitions, which again supply
resources and constraints. These activities might
be better explained as the activities of people,
individual activists or officials?However,
there is also redundant causality, ‘many
equivalent explanations of the process in
question’ (37).In some cases, for example individualist
explanations might be unnecessary if similar
outcomes emerge in different circumstances, say if
changes in personnel fail to affect organisational
policies, so that ‘the emergent properties and
capacities’ of the organisation remain roughly the
same after such a change’ (37).This
argument applies with assemblages at larger
scales-- if changes in personnel lead to different
outcomes we are justified in using individualist
accounts, including reasons and motives.[DeLanda
assumes that this is usually not so].
Thus organisations have causal
effects, and use people ‘as a medium of
interaction’ (38), sometimes as networks or
smaller organisations.Again,
causal redundancy can help sort out the importance
of different components—if urban resources affect
the conduct of a war more than the activities of
the professional military, for example, urban
centres become the agents, and the military the
medium.
Emergence also has to be
considered.It
is not just the original emergence historically,
but the process that maintains identity, a
constant struggle for territorialization against
deterritorialization.The
tendency of populations to produce assemblages
might not describe the specific historical
process—most new organizations recruit from
earlier organisations, so that there are already
organisations in existence.Also
existing assemblages can produce new parts as they
attempt to maintain themselves—so that networks
and organisations can emerge from existing cities
as well as the other way around.[A brave
attempt to avoid formalism, but there is much
empirical complexity and possibly some social
patterns here that require explanation, unless we
are just picking up on some possibilities].
Finally, explanations can
operate in different spatial scales, and the
Napoleonic revolution in warfare [discussed in his
book on the war machine] is an example, since it
transformed local limited battles into national
ones.There
were many causes, including political reforms,
technological ones, Napoleon’s own genius and his
influential networks.
So each entity is best
considered as an individual, even large
assemblages.They all have an ‘objective existence
independently of our minds’, but without invoking
a notion of essence (40).There is
a need to carefully explain relations of parts to
wholes.Wholes
are autonomous to the extent that they can
causally affect parts and interact with each
other.This
autonomy is limited by the distribution of
universal singularities, however, the diagram at
the virtual level.
There are also temporal scales
to consider.We might investigate these by asking
whether, for example, organisations take longer to
change than people, or rural ones longer than
urban.Some
changes may be set by interactions between
assemblages, such as the slow emergence of
rational bureaucracies, not explained by
‘decisions by individual persons’, for DeLanda
(41), which are therefore causally redundant.Even
strategic planning can operate in a different
temporal scale to individual decision-making,
since a large amount of resources have to be
mobilised first, and different sorts of inertia
overcome, requiring large networks and alliances
of people: the commitment to change must exceed
that of particular individuals.There
are also external pressures such as technological
change, which can have an uneven impact on
departments inside organisations, and produce
resistance or negotiation, which will itself
depend on authority structures—so even if
individuals are committed to change, it might not
happen on an individual timescale. There are lags.
There are also discretionary powers among agencies
[this reminds me very much of Colebatch on the
difficulties faced by national policies when
implemented].Again, this is seen in terms of normal
processes of adjusting objectives to political
realities.
There is also the problem of
social order [rendered here as the persistence of
institutions beyond a human life].Do
assemblages have some natural life span of their
own, and is this affected by size?DeLanda
thinks there is no simple relation.Some
networks do not endure after the people comprising
them die off, while some communities can survive a
change of personnel.Some organisations are short lived [the
example given is restaurants!, 44], while cities
are typically long lived.However
‘most social assemblages larger than people do
tend to outlive them on average’ (44).This can
arise from overlapping generations and
recruitment, and also semantic information through
language—‘specialised media of expression’,
special assemblages (44).
Such assemblages are special
because they can offer ‘variable replication’,
featuring ‘populations of replicators’, which
produce learning, and the capacity to operate at
different spatial scales simultaneously [actually
the examples are best when they refer to genes,
44-45].However,
these special assemblages should not give rise to
some essentialist argument, as when language
mediates all experience [and DeLanda specifically
mentions social constructivism here, 45, with a
reference to Berger and Luckmann].This is
a reification of linguistic categories, despite
the constructivist argument that general
categories are really stereotypes: there is still
an ‘ontological assumption that only the contents
of experience really exist’ (46).
C3 Persons
and networks
[A real eye opener for me,
raising all sorts of questions about the origins
of subjectivity that I had not thought about since
reading JS Mill years ago.Unfortunately,
this one involves a diversion into the works of
Hume, which I have not yet read]
Actual persons are best
understood as assemblages, with sub personal
components.We
need to investigate these in order to fully
develop an ontological model, although much will
remain to be explained.[At this
point, Delanda seems to have begun the usual drift
into theoreticism.The point now is to find a theory that will
agree with an assemblage approach—‘a plausible
model of the subject which meets the constraints
of assemblage theory, that is, a model in which
the subject emerges as relations of exteriority
are established among the contents of experience’
(47).Before,
the point was to explore ways in which assemblage
theories might fit social sciences, but now we’re
looking for approaches that will support
assemblage theory, which is now not to be tested
but to be taken for granted].
This will require us examining
empiricism, the argument that sense experience is
the basis of all knowledge.Deleuze
read Hume slightly differently, as an account of
subjectivity, one which precedes the linguistic
and transcendental arguments of Kant.What we
need is a collection of distinct sense
impressions.Ideas derived from these, in Hume, are
replicas of impressions, with lower intensity.Impressions
can be classified as visual, oral, olfactory and
tactile, and so can the passions ‘from pride and
humiliation to love and hatred’ (48).These
are separate and heterogeneous and have to be
articulated.It is a different approach from that which
sees impressions as examples of general
[linguistic] categories.
A unity between the impressions
and ideas arise through association.DeLanda
intends that these should be seen as exterior in
the same sense as the actions of causes.Association
between ideas can then be understood as the
actions of particular operators—grouping by
contiguity, relations of resemblance, constant
conjunction (‘the habitual pairing of causes and
effects (48)).These operators produce wholes with
emergent properties.They are also genuinely exterior, not
defined in terms of the properties of the ideas
themselves.They
are shared among all humans according to Hume,
again not in an essentialist way but as a series
of species properties.These
only look natural because they are slow to change,
or identified with an isolated species in
reproduction terms.
This formal model leaves out
contents, though, such as the actual choice of
ends and the role of passions or habits.Nevertheless,
the human subject is seen as a pragmatic one.Subjectivity
has been explained as emergent, and as both in
terms of causes and personal motives or meanings.As with
all assemblages, there are material/expressive and
territorialization/deterritorialization processes
of work.[DeLanda
seems to be searching round rather for examples,
and following rather formalist procedures.It seems
driven by the need to find examples to fit the
models rather than the other way about.For
example the material aspect means bodily
mechanisms including neurological ones, labour in
producing associated links.Like all
discussions of the body, I’m not sure if there’s a
strong case here involving biological determinism,
or just the routine acknowledgement that humans
have bodies.]
The expressive aspects include the non
linguistic and linguistic components, remembering
that linguistically represented ideas are in fact
expressions of impressions.Territorialization
is done through habit—‘for Hume…A more
powerful force sustaining the association of ideas
than conscious reflection’ (50) and various habits
or routines to maintain personal identity.Identity
can be destabilised by things such as madness,
sensory deprivation and so on].
There is also a positive aspect
of changing identity through acquiring capacities
and skills.These
permit new assemblages, like those with machines
that one has learned to master.These
skills are more flexible and adaptive that might
be seen with a rigid linear causality (but not if
we allow non linear causes).Linguistic
components
are important, but not all-constituting.After
all, all languages are relatively late
developments with humans [highly debatable here].Other
animals may also possess the ability to match
means and ends without language.Language
is best seen as augmenting these prior forms of
intelligent behaviour.Only
language makes possible complex combinations and
therefore complex ideas [in other words most of
the things that distinguish humans?] DeLanda
thinks that this is still compatible with the need
for exterior relations, because of the
characteristics of language, especially if its
grammar can also be traced to non linguistic forms
[and there is a reference to Harris, and to his
own discussion in Nonlinear History].
In particular, language shapes
beliefs, a process of bringing idea ‘closer to…Impressions’
(51).This
adds to their intensity.Again,
particularly important characteristics of language
are denied by this definition of intensity: it is
the intensity of belief that motivates people not
semantic content, as seen in desires [no
particularly Deleuzian definition here?].
There are still problems, but
at least we have given a compatible account of
empirical subjectivity.Nevertheless,
interactions between people are also very
important—‘ephemeral assemblages’ especially face
to face conversations (52).Goffman
has done much to show how for example additional
layers of identity such as public faces emerge in
conversations.Goffman apparently has an exterior notion
that has non linguistic aspects such as glances
and gestures as unintended expressions of states
of mind and body [supported with a reference to
interaction ritual].Goffman’s discussion of embarrassment also
show the limits of linguistic management—the
situation has a momentum and intensity of its own
requiring repair.
There is an attempt to fit the
two axes to conversations—material resources in
copresence [the argument gets a bit stretched
because attention and involvement are also seen as
material resources, 54].There
also technological inventions in communication
[still seen as resources compared to some
fundamental face to face encounter].Words
are clearly important, but so are non-verbals,
especially if one is deliberately constructing an
image [the universalisation of American middle
class man].Physical
borders in space and time territorialize, and
there are special places where people are agreed
to converse.Deterritorialization can be produced by
anything, including embarrassment, a special
interest for Goffman.Technology
is effective only in ‘forcing participants to
compensate for the lack of copresence in a variety
of other ways’ (54)—DeLanda needs to read Deleuze
on cinema!].
The language going on there
should be seen as both semantic and pragmatic.The
latter is arguably the more important for Goffman.At least
it will be useful to distinguish conversations
where the semantic content is the most important
from those where it is of little consequence
[shades of Schutz’s ideal types here?] The
semantic dimensions do offer more potential for
puffing an identity.
Interpersonal networks emerge
from routinized conversations.Again
these are best understood in terms of exterior
relations, including patterns of links and how
links are given properties by factors such as
gender or race.There are also emergent properties in any
network, however, with properties such as
frequency and reciprocity.Densities
are particularly important—a densely connected
network ‘has the capacity to store local
reputations and…to deter potential cheaters’ (56).The
stability of a network can also indicates its
emergent and non personal qualities.This
produces the solidarity of communities, expressed
as personal reasons and motives such as ‘altruism…[or]…strict
calculations of reciprocity’ (57).[Getting
a bit Parsonian here? Can the pattern variables be
far?]
Relationships have a material
basis as well, involving expenditure of time &
resources and also physical relations like looking
after other people’s kids.There
also various non linguistic activities which build
solidarity and trust.As usual
‘actions speak louder than words’ (57) [this seems
to be the way in which DeLanda weasels around the
issue of the importance of language: he simply
treats non verbal communication as not language?].Interpersonal
networks may be (de)territorialized and conflicts
can sharpen boundaries and develop community
identity.Solidarity
can therefore lead to exclusion limits on members’
autonomy [Durkheim needed here].Social
mobility and secularisation go the other way.So do
communication technologies that enable dispersal
[all very formalist].
Linguistic components proper
include shared stories and categories, with
reference to an historical sociologist Tilly.Narratives
simplify the solidaristic processes, leaving out
long-term or hidden aspects, including those
related to unintended consequences.Solidaristic
stories
have particular roles at the margins of
communities.
Political activity in
occupations can produce political alliances such
as social movements.Since these involve a struggle, ‘a movement
typically breeds a counter movement, both of which
should be considered component parts of the
overall assemblage’ (59).[The
danger of the banalities of conflict theory, or
the notions of the functional nature of conflict
lurk here]. Tilly does a lot of work, especially
on the ways in which conflict resolution developed
in Britain, involving claims to legitimacy.Successful
claims also involved material aspects such as the
ability to organize mass rallies, or to
effectively control them.Enduring
organisations emerge, ‘specialised association’
(61).However,
there are also ‘protest cycles’, for Tilly, as new
opportunities and threats emerge.Sometimes
these lead to effective polarisation and
revolutionary change.Much of
the struggle is over categorisation and
classification, principally because these attract
different rights and obligations [in other words,
there is a material basis to social constructions,
62].Classifications
are about material resources as well as semantics.
Social classes are even larger
assemblages, which arise following differential
access to resources and constraint.There
are social processes which rank groups.Tilly
again has his own take, denying any basic
divisions and seeing classes as political groups
[parties for Weber].Bourdieu is seen as offering an excellent
example, based on cultural as well as economic
resources, a distinction which ‘corresponds,
roughly to the one between material and expressive
resources in assemblage theory’ (63).Distinction
is dynamic, and proximity is an important issue.These
are seen as relations of exteriority, and Bourdieu
undertakes statistical analysis to connect
material position and lifestyle.‘Dispositions’
look compatible with assemblage theory on
subjectivity, but Bourdieu then introduces the
notion of habitus which is almost automatic, and
which minimises all the differences between the
motivations, reasons and causes of behaviour.Habitus
ensures an unthinking submission to order, as
punters make a virtue out of necessity.The
habitus even controls who may make conscious
choices, and thus becomes an underlying master
process.
This is where DeLanda
disagrees, and says there is no need for a master
process, and the submission to order cannot be
taken for granted but must be explained ‘in terms
of specific enforcement mechanisms’ (65).These
may include a density of networks, or modern
practices of compliance.Bourdieu
sees economic and cultural capital structuring
social space in general, but DeLanda argues for
analysis of concrete social entities [in a very
abstract way!].Resources are emergent, and there are also
genuinely external ones such as technological or
natural resources.Bourdieu makes his mistake because he
believes in ‘the linguisticality of experience’
(65) [with a reference to Language and
Symbolic Power].Tilly
and DeLanda insist that groups are real not just
phenomenological, based on actual concrete
practices [Bourdieu too surely?A bit of
erratic scholarship from Delanda here? I think the
quote he cites from Language
( p.105)... derives from an introduction to a
section on the phenomenal subjective perception of
categories, which are then explained by
differential resources in the naming of the worlds
etc, just as DeLanda himself does]. They arise
when categories gain economic significance,
sometimes through a self fulfilling prophecy.Nevertheless,
boundaries are ‘contingent and precarious’ (67)
threatened by social mobility, or technological
innovation [idealism here, and Bourdieu is needed
to see how cultural qualities define and regulate
these threats].We also need a good account of political
organization and governments.
[DeLanda’s notes referring to
the habitus suggest that an assemblage reading
sees the habitus as a topological space including
habits and routines that make up individuals, ‘the
space of possibilities for different combinations
of habits and skills’ (133).But
surely the point is that this habitus is already
deeply structured by social class and social
reproduction, that class is the main attractor.Other
possibilities might exist in principle, and this
is surely discussed by Bourdieu, or implied at
least when he refers to dominant culture as
‘arbitrary’.Nevertheless, thinking of other
combinations might be a very useful thing to do.]
C4
Organisations and governments
This concerns those
organisations with authority structures.As
before, they have to have resources to enforce
obedience, and components to develop their
legitimacy.Weber’s
three ideal types are useful, as long as we
remember that actual organizations may be a
mixture of the three.Rational
legal forms have come to dominate in modern
states.A
particular feature of them is that they acquire
behaviours independently of the people holding the
office in question, thereby qualifying as actors
in their own right as argued before.
The usual expressive roles are
available, based on individuals or symbols.DeLanda
acknowledges that the very rationality claimed by
an organisation could be ceremonial, especially
where outcomes are complex [the examples are
mental health clinics, legal agencies and
schools].Mostly,
this is acknowledged in acts of obedience, but
disobedience must also be occasionally dealt with
by punishment.This leads to Foucault on the regulation of
bodies, their dispersal in space and time, the way
they are monitored, ceaseless inspection and
recording and so on.
There can be boundary disputes
over jurisdiction.There can also be crises of succession,
producing phenomena such as the routinization of
charisma.Written
records are important, but mostly in terms of
logistics ‘not the type of writing that lends
itself to endless rounds of hermeneutic
interpretation’ (74) [this is a further
demarcation of ‘straightforward language…The
material form of writing documenting relatively
simple facts’, which permits the anti linguistic
case]. Group beliefs are also important, sometimes
integrated as a discourse, again with a reference
to Foucault.
How do such organisations
interact and form hierarchies and networks?Assemblage
theory uses the same techniques allowing for
differences of scale—so that ‘the collective
unintended consequences of intentional action
becomes more prominent at larger scales’ (75).The
resources required involve specific transactions
of exchange, for example and these may be
asymmetrical.Much dependence on the size of the resource
and its particular importance—scarcity, the extent
to which it can be substituted by another
resource, the extent to which it can be controlled
and how.Such
control offers a material basis for hierarchy,
even if legitimate authority is absent [making
linguistic resources secondary again].
Organisations can cope or
resist dependency by vertical integration,
producing large self sufficient organisations, as
in U.S. car manufacturers.They can
also network via interlocking directorships.Small
companies can agglomerate, sometimes by locating
in regions where there are accumulations of
skilled labour or other resources.Firms
and suppliers can cooperate via consultation.Often,
companies display mixtures, but there are some
extreme cases.Silicon Valley is an example of a region
featuring agglomeration, while the Route 128
region in Boston has competing integrated
corporations.Both forms of relationship feature
expressive and material qualities.Again,
communication between firms may be ‘not a matter
of semantics…but assessments of strategic significance
or importance’ (80) [a further restriction of
linguistic to mean semantic—this seems similar to
Weber, where purely rational action requires no
interpretation and so on.There
may also be a lurking problem with the idea that
bureaucracies are actors in their own right—if so,
who is the speaker in the expressive activities? Lower
down, page 80, he says that decision-making also
raises the problem of just how linguistic
expressive behaviour of organisations is. Here,
DeLanda seems to be talking about economic
pressure as a form of communication.] Competition
and corporation need to be managed in order to
avoid threats to common resources—thus a certain
amount of solidarity between organisations is
important.
Decision-making does involve
attitudes and beliefs about the activities of
others, but implementing strategies depends on
resources, and often requires causal understanding
of material processes.Understanding
flows of money can also be important.
Territorialization issues
include the role of local geographies in
constraining mobility.Territorialization
also has an internal dimension and this depends on
the size and autonomy of the firm.Associations
between similar firms in an industry can also be
important, as can professional and worker
associations.Turbulent environments can
deterritorialize, including rates of innovation,
organisational inertia, adaptability, and who is
affected.Contracts
can be important, and firms may switch between
sales and employment contracts when dealing with
other firms. There are also different contractual
forms.Contracts
further require the legal system and government
organizations.
There are additional problems
in applying assemblage theory.There
are many forms of organisations.It is
convenient to focus on the federalist form as in
the USA.As
before, reified generalities are not useful,
including the term ‘the state’—we need to
distinguish between formulation and implementation
of policies, for example, and these two wings may
have a complex relationship.Similarly,
there is a need to distinguish the democratic and
bureaucratic organizations, and a further
separation between politics and administration.Again
there are problems of relationships here,
sometimes arising from ‘expertise asymmetries’
(86).Expertise
can also shift between bureaucracies and
regulators.There
is a further distinction needed between
territorial entities and specific hierarchies:
changes in government might not affect all the
relationships between cities regions and provinces
[however it is complex DeLanda tells us since
political agencies commonly do administer
territories].
It is also necessary to isolate
assemblages from populations
or coalitions, on the basis of endurance.Relationships
between organisations need not change the
identities involved.Hierarchical assemblages need an expressive
role to legitimate authority and the material role
focuses on enforcement.Voting
systems as material components can also have
effects of their own, which can include ceremonial
rather than technical effects.Bureaucracies
depend instead on technical legitimacy,
‘disinterested expertise’ (89).There is
also a need to regulate experts in the interests
of fairness—by appointing key personnel,
controlling resources or altering constitutions to
include monitoring.Professionalisation of personnel is an
important source of autonomy.
Crises of various kinds can
produce deterritorialization, such as coups
d’état, or succession crises, or splits
within one governing body.Linguistic
resources include the use of unambiguous wordings,
written constitutions and laws, and the extent of
codification.
Interactions between
hierarchical assemblages can be disrupted by a
situation such as war.These
require mobilisation of the population,
negotiation with critics inside and outside,
concessions to citizens.There is
also the need for symbolic expressive activities
to increase legitimacy and links civilians and
armed forces.These can vary according to their populism.Threats
of war can territorialize and increase solidarity.Civil
wars and revolutions do the opposite.A
revolutionary assemblage requires a population
with rising expectations followed by deprivation;
a struggle between dominant groups and challenges;
a display of vulnerability by government, as in
the inability to deal with a crisis (93, drawing
on an obscure source).Governments,
by contrast with populations, tend to be concerned
with issues such as sovereignty over particular
territories, and this introduces spatial aspects
affecting assemblages.
C5
Cities and nations
Some assemblages are bound to a
definite spatial location, like cities or nation
states.This
helps us understand the role of geographical
space, both as constraining and as permitting the
expression of important differences, such as the
ones between city and country.[You
have to admire DeLanda here, for bringing in all
sorts of trendy new links with sociology].
Giddens tries to understand the
effects of space, physical territories, but he
does overdo the determinism: spaces also need
expressive components to territorialize them, and
human beings do have some choice in how they
respond to spaces.Nevertheless spaces, and buildings, often
survive particular human occupants, and this alone
provides constraint in the form of routine.
Buildings constrain
interactions through offering different kinds of
connectivity.Technological
changes alter connectivity, for example, the
design of skyscrapers around metal frames.[DeLanda
says there is an obvious connection between the
development of vertical office blocks and
stratified bureaucracies, and the height of your
office reflected your status in new ways].Clearly
buildings also offer symbolic forms of expression
to split sacred and profane, for example
[Bourdieu’s work on the Kabylian interior springs
to mind here].Normally, traditions endure, but when
fashion develops, frequent change occurs.DeLanda
thinks that fashion is impelled by the need to
preserve class distinctions around the
aristocracy—quite Bourdieusian (98), with no
preservation of open possibilities? New
disciplinary regimes have affected distributions
of people in particular buildings, as in Foucault
on the prison.
Buildings exist in
collectivities, larger assemblages, such as
neighbourhoods or city zones.Underground
infrastructures also connect buildings.Exteriors
become expressive, and again private forms are
driven by ‘ inter-class competition’ (100).Town
planning can attempt deliberate forms of
connectivity [as in social mixing in Milton
Keynes].Occupational
specialisation can also territorialize, and the
opposite for institutionalised segregation.Here,
rates of geographical mobility and economic
factors such as land rent [or rateable values in
the UK] can have effects [including changes in the
use of buildings, as in gentrification], as can
increased transport networks which permit the
growth of suburbia.Early urban sociology developed notions of
city zones, although the concentric ring model did
not fit traditional European cities or changes.There
can be, for example, several city centres or
cores.There
have been various influences on the location of
retail sectors as well
Discussions of changing land
use imply a larger assemblages—populations.An early
difference between town and country was important.This
boundary has changed with population growth, and
with patterns of shifting populations, including
people who live in both.Characteristic
activities in rural areas require different sorts
of resources, such as more land per individual,
while cities usually dominate the countryside
economically.Concentration of resources can be
responsible for a dynamic of urban growth.There
are also geographical regions, providing a ‘range
of objective opportunities and risks’ (105).The
technological characteristics of forms of
transport had an effect, for example the building
of railroad tracks influencing the development of
bead-like suburbs around stations. The decoration
or silhouette of buildings can have an expressive
effect, as ‘kind of visual signature’ (15), and
this is sometimes deliberately modified, for
example for tourists.
Population growth and
characteristics clearly affect the development of
settlements, including the density of cities.More
generally, assemblages like cities display
‘symmetry breaking events, as each town confronts
centripetal processes, like the capture of
population…and
other resources, as well as centrifugal ones, like
congestion, pollution, traffic’ (108).There
may be a single optimal state, but usually rapid
sequential change is apparent.
For some geographers, central
places are the important elements of urban
hierarchies – market places or churches, regional
markets based on towns, jails or schools, the more
specialist services found in the larger centres.These
hierarchies are based on resource dependencies.
Ports and their connections have been particularly
important in developing connections between cities
of equal status, in a network, and responding to
economic changes and specialisation.Ports
often make up for their own resource limits by
trading, often over long distances in the only
practicable way.These contacts added to the
cosmopolitanism. Expressive elements vary in terms
of increasing complexity for land-locked cities as
well, until we get to metropolitan centres which
are also culturally very diverse.
Territorial states and nations
can simply be seen as larger scale assemblages,
but they are also integrated differently.Initially,
cities resisted national integration, but some
particularly large ones formed the nucleus of the
nation and eventually became capital cities.National
integration often involved military intervention
as well, and this also has the effect of implying
concentration of resources and tight boundaries.Increased
warfare finally ended autonomous city states, and
permitted the application of new notions of
sovereignty.The physical location of nation states has
always had military implications.
Nation states come to
specialise in new activities such as public
finance and economic growth, including the
development of national debt and credit.But
resources clearly play a part including natural
resources, which can also affect the growth of
national markets based on transport.Various
kinds of national controls can then be expressed,
including the development of national building
styles, sometimes in symbolic architecture such as
the European ‘Grand Manner’—e.g. ‘uniform facades
acting as frames for sweeping vistas culminated
with an obelisk, triumphal arch, or statue’ [Think
central Paris] (115).Standard
languages are also required, with a consequent
national education system. There are physical
controls, including objects such as the Maginot
line.
Nations are deterritorialized
by migration and trade, and internal factors such
as remnants of independent city states or
colonies.Maritime
networks also resist integration, as in the
relative autonomy of Amsterdam.Such
links across borders can produce transnational
states, or at least world economies—there is still
some doubt about their internal coherence, and
this is certainly enough to question Marxist
reductionist processes such as world systems
theory.It
is necessary instead to see world trade as sets of
assemblages
There are no seamless
totalities, but assemblages that retain a certain
‘relative autonomy’ and ‘ontological independence’
(119).This
resists reductionism into micro and macro levels.It also
permits different social science contributions to
be valued, from understandings of face to face to
those of international trade.The
different conceptions are best seen as ‘a chorus
that does not harmonise its different components
but interlocks them while respecting their
heterogeneity’ (119).