Brief Notes on: Deleuze, G. 'Coldness and
Cruelty', (published with Sacher-Masoch,
L. 'Venus in Furs') Both are combined
in a volume called Masochism (1991) New
York: Zone Books.
Dave Harris
I'm not going to offer full notes on this
commentary by Deleuze, but offer instead a brief
set of notes about what the main themes are, at
least for me.
Much of the early part of Deleuze's contribution
is taken up with offering criticisms of the
characteristics of masochism as offered by
Freudians, including Freud himself. One
major criticism is directed at the argument that
masochism is just the inverse of sadism, so that
we can talk about a sadomasochistic
syndrome. Deleuze makes methodological
points about this interpretation, and I pick them
up in chapter V: Deleuze says that the analysis
offered by Freudians is not concrete and empirical
enough, that the syndrome is described by
combining abstract elements which are then
supposed to be transformed into each other.
Instead, we need to look at 'the total concrete
situation, the specific world of the perversion'
(58), and to avoid preconceptions, especially in
the form of an etiology. Freudian accounts
lose their explanatory power when they are
abstracted and combined like this, for example
'modes of equivalents and translation are mistaken
for systems of transition and
transformation'. This seems to be about the
only case where Freud sanctions this kind of
combination -- perhaps because Kraft-Ebbing did it
first.
In particular, the analysis of masochism reveals
some important limitations with the whole Freudian
schema, which sees the father as playing the
dominant symbolic role in the formation of the
personality. Paternal dominance probably
dominates sadistic perversions, where fathers
enlist daughters, and mothers are rejected as
representing soft, non-virile. meek forms of
nature. By contrast, in masochism, the whole
thing turns on different mythical versions of the
mother, roughly 1. primeval prostitute, who
generates disorder and threatens manliness; 2. the
sadistic woman at the other end of history, who
allies and equates herself with man to become
vigorous and active; and then 3. the ideal woman
for Masoch, an intermediate type, cold and severe,
but also loving and gentle, 'cold-maternal-severe,
icy- sentimental-cruel' (51).
Fathers can appear to be important, but that is a
methodological artefact: abstract elements can be
combined in a number of ways. We need to
appreciate 'the total concrete situation,
the specific world of the perversion' (58).
However, we been misled because the symptoms have
already been understood, before Freud, by 'a
preconceived etiology'. By seeing things as
prematurely connected, we lose their explanatory
power, for example the specific effects of
castration and guilt. Later, Freudians were
to be misled by the emphasis on the father.
There are
some important implications for Freud and for
the Freudian notion that the father always
represents the Law or the symbolic order.
In masochism, the symbolic order is experienced
as 'intermaternal... in which the mother
represents the law' and generates the symbolism
which masochists can use. The man does
appear, but as a rather mysterious third party
in the fantasy, which will eventually have real
consequences in Venus..., In bringing
back reality as it were. It is often the
case, apparently, and this is attributed to
Lacan, that objects which have been abolished on
the symbolic plane reappear in the real, or in
hallucinatory versions of the real. Thus
the mysterious figure of the Greek man reappears
in Venus in a way which ends the
fantasy, and turns the hero toward sadism - it
is not that the masochist has reverted to
sadism, but rather that the masochistic
fantasies have been disrupted and can only be
replaced by hallucination [of the real].
Later we are told that a third party is needed
as a compound figure, so that he can idealize
and stand for the masochistic new man.
Such ambiguous figures are often required in
fantasies, Deleuze tells us, to mediate between
extremes, and this is what the masochist has to
do to mediate between primeval and sadistic
modern women as above.
We see that women here are
playing all the parts, so to speak, and the
effect is to banish the father altogether in
sexual fantasy and desire: the father is
'canceled out, and his parts and functions
distributed among the three women' (63).
The feminine is fully self-sufficient lacking
in nothing, and in the fantasy, this permits
women to play a number of roles. In
fact, real mothers are also disavowed, but in
favor of a more 'positive' and ideal
role. However, the fantasy depends on a
symbolic order in which these three women can
appear, 'the language of myths, which is
therefore essential to masochism' [and so is
the language of theatre, it might be argued].
The father is canceled out because
the 'good oral mother'[the intermediate stage in
myth] takes over the functions of the father, so
that the three mystical women together constitute
the whole 'symbolic order. Hence for
masochists, the mother represents the law,
generates the symbolism through which the
masochist can express himself (63). Indeed,
the father threatens to disrupt the masochistic
fantasy, involving a 'complex strategy' (65) to
protect the world of fantasy—the contract with the
female partner. Women are given full rights so
that the father can be abolished, so,
ironically, the rational contract permits the
return of mythical figures of the three mother
images. This means that when the
masochist is being beaten or humiliated, it is
actually the father that's being beaten, while the
masochist prepares for a rebirth 'in which the
father will have no part'(66) [as in he becomes a
new man?].
Apparently, there is
some 'fundamental structure of fantasy in general'
(66) which turns on playing off two opposing
series or margins. Masoch refers to his approach
as '"supersensualism"' (69), where there is a
break with more natural or animal experience,
producing pleasurable pain [like a kind of
deferral of gratification?] . The senses
become abstracted or 'theoretical'. It
becomes possible to form relationships with
statues, marble women. This is quite
different from Sade's aesthetics where
animal-type sensuality dominates and becomes a
matter of movements, often endless or repeated
movement as in pornography, something
'mechanically grounded' (70). For
masochists, there is a more detached aesthetic
[blimey! the high aesthetic as in
Bourdieu!] and this comes over as a
central place for waiting and suspense, again
not just that simple matter of experiencing
pain as pleasure as if that was all one
syndrome. Later we are
told that masochism is not unique and does not
have a specifically masochistic fantasy
(72). Here, it is the notion of the uterine
mother and the oedipal mother [the first and third
mythical variants] which helps develop the oral
mother as containing resonances [sic] from the
other two. The oral mother borrows the
sexual prostitution function from one, and the
sadistic function and interest in punishment from
the other. The good mother is a neutral
substitute [and this is referenced to some letters
written by Masoch]. In this way femininity
lacks nothing and there is no need for of the real
father - here the absence of a penis is irrelevant
to the possession of the phallus. Both
masochism and sadism involve some elements of both
conventional sexualities, but in different ways -
'the masochist is hermaphrodite and the sadist
androgynous'(68). Again this means that they
are not interchangeable as opposites.
Pain, punishment and humiliation are not pleasures
in themselves but 'necessary prerequisites to
obtaining gratification' (71). Pain makes
gratification possible, and pleasure must wait,
and this extends into a 'an indefinite awaiting of
pleasure and an intense expectation of pain'
(71). This extends again into 'waiting in
its pure form', which is itself gratifying, as
shown in the accounts in Masoch about the
pleasures of waiting for things, like having a
tooth pulled out. A masochist 'believes that he is
dreaming even when he is not', requiring a
disciplined stance towards fantasy, whereas
sadists need to believe that they're not dreaming.
Masochism is an example of '"culturism"' (76),
art, but also with a strange juridical element in
the contract. There is still an element of
naturalism, since 'it is essentially the work of
art and the contract that makes possible the
transition from a lower nature to the great
Nature, which is sentimental and self conscious',
and again there are differences with sadism: Sade
is more interested in motion and mechanism to
reveal primary nature, and institutions rather
than laws [including those of contract], including
secret societies. For sadists, the state of
immorality 'is one of perpetual unrest, resembling
the necessary state of insurrection' (78) which is
required to produce proper republicanism [there is
quite a lot of interesting stuff on how this sort
of extension works, how an interest in contract
leads to a broader support for law, and even to
the support for rituals to maintain and make
sacred the law. This is pursued in chapter
VII].
There's a certain amount of humor in masochism
[turning on this distinction between humor and
irony again. I find it difficult to grasp
because pointing out humorous unintended
consequences is irony for me. Irony for
Deleuze, however involve some appeal to a higher
order or principle that cancels out or contradicts
things that were seen as previously binding --an
example, from Wikipedia I think, although it might
be Deleuze, turns on Socrates arguing that the
virtuous obey the law, only to find that he was
expected to obey the law too and kill himself
after being found guilty]. Masochists can
attack conventional laws by twisting them, say by
carrying them to excess, observing the very letter
of the law, and pretending that therefore the law
justifies the perverse results. We see this
when masochism develops the opposite pleasures to
what might be expected, so that whipping provokes
an erection rather than preventing it, or shows
that punitive laws should be understood as leading
to entitlement to enjoy the pleasures that are
forbidden. We can now see that the 'temporal
succession' of pain and pleasure does not mean
that the one causes the other: rather, the
'contents' have been reversed, so that being
forbidden to enjoy something is taken as the need
to go ahead and enjoy it. There are other
examples of this sort of humor, including pointing
to the humorous consequences of waiting and
suspense, and 'the masochist is insolent in his
obsequiousness' (89) [and mocking the role of the
father as we shall see].
There is an implicit criticism of contract
theories of law and social relations as well,
since laws exceed contracts between 2 individuals,
and extend rights to others. They are
indeterminate. We see the dilemmas in
Masoch's actual contracts [examples of which are
given in an appendix] which become increasingly
strict, almost anticipating that the law will
dilute them. Again we see a caricature, an
'excess of zeal, the humorous acceleration of the
clauses, and a complete reversal of the respective
contractual status of man and woman' (92), a
demystification of the contract that gives the
woman ultimate power, even though it has been
initiated by the victim. This carried over
into Masoch's politics, with a 'humorous attitude'
to the revolutions of 1848 that suggested that a
new Tsarina, a supreme female leader, should be
installed by contract.
The victim gains from this contract, by excluding
the father and giving the job of exercising the
law to the mother. This produces a reversal
of the normal threat of castration. When
associated with mothers, 'it then makes incest
possible and ensures its success' (93) [strange
argument here which I do not entirely follow,
apparently, the threat of castration by mothers
involves the notion of a second birth which
dispenses with the father's role altogether.
It also apparently explains the masochistic liking
for '"interrupted love"'. Certainly, the
fantasy permits sexual activity as incest,
in fantasy anyway, and somehow as second birth --
as a non-Oedipal man? ]
It's easy to see how this will lead to ritual, as
a part of fantasy [but not solidaristic ones as I
had thought --they may have this Durkheimian role,
of course]. Three kinds of rites appear in
particular in Masoch's novels, associated with
hunting, agriculture, and regeneration and
rebirth, and these are tied to more specific
elements: the fur is a trophy of the hunt, the
sentimentality and fecundity links to agriculture,
and rigor is associated with a regeneration [I'm
probably missing something here because I have not
read the actual novels, which are cited in
support, 94 -97. They seem to make this link
in particular between pain and regeneration and
rebirth, and how men need to be made through
torture and ritual. We're told later that
interrupted love represents castration, [a much
kinder representation] and far from being an
obstacle to or punishment for incest, actually
acts as a precondition of it, 100.
Apparently rebirth deprives sexuality of its
genitality --so reborn as an exponent of the high
aesthetic, almost reborn as a BwO -- hence the
discussion of masochism in A Thousand Plateaus,
of course].
Overall, masochism is a phenomenon of the senses
in material terms, and a function of feeling or
sentiment in moral terms. There's also 'the
superpersonal element' (101) which is about the
triumphs of the oral mother, the abolition of the
father, and the birth of the new man. These
themes appear not just in bodily masochism but in
'formal masochism' or 'dramatic masochism',
which might emphasize particular aspects, material
or sentimental for example. Overall, 'the
symbolic order of masochism' remains and specific
contracts are contained within it. Indeed,
this modern form of sexuality 'corresponds to the
oldest rites once enacted in the swamps and the
steppes'(102).
Chapter IX consists of a detailed critical
discussion of Freud's theories, especially on the
connections between sadism and masochism.
Roughly, for Freud masochism arises when
aggression against the father is turned upon the
self, sometimes, involving either infantile fear,
or feelings of guilt once the superego is
formed. However, this does not apply very
well, since the involvement of the superego
actually involves desexualization of aggression,
as in the ideal resolution [sublimation?] of the
Oedipus complex. If anything, the superego
is aggressive towards the ego, but this is not
masochism. Masochism resexualizes the ego,
avoiding feeling guilty, but still wanting to be
punished, as a means to achieving sexual
gratification. We also have to remember that
masochistic pleasures resolve guilt but as a
preparation for sexual pleasure. We need
some further material connection between erotic
arousal and the particular link with pain.
Again this is not the same as sadistic interest in
pain. There's a necessary 'mechanism of
projection through which an external agent is made
to assume the role of the subject' (106), and this
enables resexualization. Freudian accounts
would see masochists as wanting to identify with
mothers and become sexual images for fathers,
seeing that this would also involve necessary
castration, so being beaten is an acceptable
alternative. The role of the mother is a
kind of repressed homosexual choice.
However, these processes of projection
actually point to differences between
masochists and sadists, even for Freudians.
There is a methodological criticism of Freudian
theory here when it tries to reconcile the stories
of sadists with those of masochists, which only
produces a third story which is inadequate to
explain either (108). Another key difference
in masochism is its formal and dramatic nature,
and again this is a gap unexplained by Freudian
synthesis.
Chapter X continues with a discussion of Freud on
the death instinct. It is preceded by
considerable praise for Freud and his
'masterpiece' Beyond the Pleasure Principle.
For Freud, there are no exceptions to the pleasure
principle, but there is something which falls
outside it, something beyond it.
Philosophically speaking, we can argue that
principles govern particular fields, but to argue
that involves 'a second order principle, which
accounts for the necessary compliance of the field
with the empirical principle' (112). That is
implied necessarily in the claim that empirical
life is dominated by pleasure and pain, but the
normal pleasure principle cannot act as this
transcendental one, cannot explain its own
foundations. Freud wants to invent some
general notion of the 'binding of excitation' that
takes particular forms, both an energetic and a
biological component. This sort of binding
can be generalized into the pleasure principle,
but, if so, it clearly involves the notion of
repetition. This repetition only involves
the problem of foundation or ground again, however
– how did it emerge? What happened before
the instant of the binding? In a way, the
notion of repetition points to something that
eliminates it [something 'eternal', outside it or
before it?]. Freud suggested something
groundless preceded the ground, Thanatos, the
[energetic] eliminator. This is
confused in Freud's writing, however in its
complexity, seeing repetition as both beneficial
and demonic, eros and thanatos both as combined
and as qualitatively separate (114). Freud
eventually develops a transcendental motion of
synthesis to include what is before during and
after a repetition. In actual experience,
repetition follows the principle, and we repeat
what we found to be pleasurable or anticipate to
be pleasurable. At the philosophical level,
however eros is always linked with thanatos, with
thanatos supplying energy and eros binding
it.
This helps explain the important argument about
the 'defusion of the instincts'(116) in Freud: how
the ego and the superego connect in different ways
to manage or desexualize. This can bring
about two results, one dominated by the
narcissistic ego, a form of 'functional
disturbances' the second demonstrating 'the power
of thought in the superego', producing
sublimation. Both involve a certain
liberation of erotic energy. However, there
might be a further alternative, Deleuze thinks,
operating with a permanent split between ego and
superego, and this is what Freud called the
perversions. They cannot be explained in
terms of a simple functional disturbance.
Here there is considerable desexualization first,
followed by resexualization, not sublimation, with
sexual energy preserved in a different form.
The first process involves a necessary coldness,
the apathy of the sadist or the fantasy of the
masochist, with the latter as far more creative,
involving even things like property or
money. The connection between pain and
pleasure had never been understood before, and had
been seen as some sort of pleasure for the gods,
or as enjoyable to a particular person who
inflicts it or the one who suffers it, but this
downplays the importance of the actual process of
resexualization, whether this is ceaseless
activity and accumulation in sadism, or suspense
and freezing in masochism. The pain should
be understood as a manifest content of the
perversion only, with far deeper pleasures like
reiteration and destruction for Sade.
Repetition in Sade takes on a pleasure of its own,
as an ideal in its own right, more important than
just gaining pleasure in the conventional
way. Coldness is linked to comfort, but the
connection with pain has to be thought out: pain
'has no sexual significance at all' (120) but
represents the desexualization stage, liberating
repetition, and leading to a resexualization of
the pleasures of repetition. 'In sadism no
less than in masochism there is no direct relation
to pain: pain should be regarded as an effect
only' (121).
Freudian accounts argue that the superego of the
sadist is particularly weak, so it acts on others, but the
overwhelming superego in masochism turns
it against the ego and not against the
other. However, if we actually look at
masochism it's clear that the ego is 'only
apparently crushed by the superego' (124).
Masochism actually involves 'insolence and
humor… Irrepressible defiance and ultimate
triumph'. The masochist uses an apparently
weak ego to manipulate the female partner into
playing the role. It is probably the
superego that is weak, and has to be projected
onto the woman, externalized - but this is done
only to make it derisory. It is sadists that
have overwhelming superegos that are so strong
that they dominate identity, and have to find
external egos, running wild, expelling the
person's own ego. This is ironic in that
deleuzian sense, because it is really his own ego
which is projected outwards. This explains
the 'pseudo masochism' which we find in sadism and
which offers superficial similarities.
Masochism is different: the superego remains but
appears derisory. In practice it has been
disavowed. Again the father is disavowed
representing 'both genital sexuality and the
superego as an agent of repression' (125).
This is humor for Deleuze, making the superego
appear as a precondition, but really
reflecting 'a triumphant ego' (126). Again
this can appear as a 'pseudosadism'.
The superego is still needed in sadism to keep
destroying something outside of itself
repetitively, somehow adding them up in order to
'transcendent towards an Idea of pure
negation'(127), and this is precisely like the
'cold purity of thought in the superego',
desexualization. This is seen in the
constant mixture of description of sexual activity
with various speculative speeches and political
statements in Sade. In masochism disavowal
leads instead to suspense directed at the
'incarnation of the ideal'. The ego is not
destroyed but suspended: its imagination remains
and indeed is liberated instead of the negation of
the sadist. The superego is challenged, and
urged to give birth to an ideal ego, one that's
timeless and liberated from superego.
Castration is seen as important and relevant in
this process. However, disavowal like this
is not just the form of imagination, but 'nothing
less than the foundation of imagination, which
suspends reality and establishes the ideal in the
suspended world' (128). What disavowal does
is to desexualize in masochism. Even the
phallus is desexualized, by being transferred to
the mother and becoming something that operates a
neutral energy. Rebirth here involves a
'"new Man devoid of sexual love"'.
Overall, masochism offers a story about how the
superego was destroyed and what happened
afterwards. The story is not always
complete. In full, it starts with three women in
myth and the triumph of the oral woman. The
individual himself intervenes by making a contract
with a woman. Father is rejected, especially
his sexuality and his repressive authority, in
favor of the contract. Instead of an
established superego, 'the institutional
superego'(130), there is a contract between the
ego and the oral mother. Death is reimagined
as second birth, parthenogenesis. In the
narcissistic ego proper, the mother stands for
death more straightforwardly: there are also
connections with Biblical stories about Eve and
Cain, Jesus and the virgin Mary, so there's
also a notion of the death of god here. In
the masochistic variant, this leads to a
resexualization so that pleasures can continue to
be enjoyed. Sadism's story is different, relating
how the ego is beaten and expelled, how the
superego is therefore unrestrained and models
itself on the father, how this activity of the
superego does not lead to a moral character, but
is turned up on the external victims who represent
the rejected ego. Elements of the thinking
superego persist as in the writings of Sade
himself. Death assumes the notion of
'fearful thought'.
There are a number of ways therefore to link
violence and cruelty to sexual behavior, but one
syndrome cannot be transformed into another.
In order to argue that both sadism and masochism
are the same, we have to miss out some of the
components, or even ignore differences between
superego and ego, for example. Common
symptoms are identified, often using analogy and
approximation. Instead, symptoms should be
treated as indications of several possible
diseases. In particular, 'it's necessary to
read Masoch' (133). Instead of offering an
etiology, 'the scientific or experimental side of
medicine', we should be doing symptomatology, 'its
literary artistic aspect'[compare with the notion
of a symptomatic reading in Althusser]. We
must avoid 'splitting the semiological unity of a
disturbance, or uniting very different
disturbances under a misbegotten name, in a whole
arbitrarily defined by non specific
causes'(133-4). Thus sadomasochism is 'a
semiological howler'(134).
The argument is summarized on page 134 as 11
propositions. If we follow these we can see
both a clinical and literary differences
between Sade and Masoch:
(1) sadism is
speculative - demonstrative, masochism
dialectical - imaginative; (2) sadism operates
with the negative and pure negation, masochism
with disavowal and suspension; (3) sadism
operates by means of quantitative reiteration,
masochism by means of qualitative suspense;
(4) there is a masochism specific to the
sadist and equally a sadism specific to the
masochist, the one never combining with the
other; (5) sadism negates the mother and
inflates the father, masochism disavows the
mother and abolishes the father; (6) the role
and significance of the fetish and the
function of the fantasy are totally different
in each case; (7) there is an aesthticism in
masochism, while sadism is hostile to the
aesthetic attitude; (8) sadism is
institutional, masochism contractual; (9) in
sadism the superego and the process of
identification play the primary role,
masochism gives primacy to the ego and to the
process of idealization; (10) sadism and
masochism exhibit totally different forms of
desexualization and resexualization; (11)
finally, summing up all these differences,
there is the most radical difference between
sadistic apathy and masochistic coldness.
back to Deleuze page
|
|