NOTES
ON: Deleuze, G.(1988) Spinoza Practical Philosophy,
trans. Robert Hurley. San
Francisco: City Lights Books
[Hurley's
Preface is a bit odd in spotting a link
between Spinoza and deep ecologists,
especially Naess [?] -- via
understanding as interacting with things.
Hurley says Deleuze is even better with his
notion of a plane of consistency as an
'environment', with its own 'field of
forces'. Humans need to be able to reconnect
with this notion of the geophysical
environment, the connections within us of
the nonhuman and all that -- 'what
new individual do we compose when we "think
like a mountain"' (ii). Must
give that a go!]
Chapter
One Life of Spinoza
[Odd that
Deleuze should be interested in people’s
lives—aren’t individuals just conceptual
personae?This
account actually mentions social and political
forces but also Spinoza’s courage and
resourcefulness. Could be just a conventional
way in? ]
Philosophers
are supposed to be ascetic—humble, poor and
chaste—as an expression of their singularity.This
makes them able to resist attacks on personal
grounds.They
also celebrate solitude because philosophers can
not be integrated, even in to the liberal
democratic societies.Spinoza
think social life is just a matter of obeying,
and so are lots of moral categories.This
is a constraint on thought, and societies should
be sought that do not ‘subject thought to the
rule of the state, which only applies to
actions.As
long as thought is free, hence vital, nothing is
compromised’ (4) [which is both {male} heroic
and quietist].Thought should be beyond obedience and
blame, life should be beyond good and evil, as
we shall see.
Spinoza
did eventually leave the closed Jewish
subculture in which he was raised for more urban
milieux.The
Jewish community in Amsterdam already contained
different strands, including one that was
sceptical, and there were frequent excommunications,
including Spinoza who refused to repent.He
survived an assassination attempt and moved to
Leyden.Deleuze
says it was radical and sceptical trends inside
Judaism rather than the influence of any liberal
or Christian thinking.
There were
substantial splits inside the Dutch political
groups as well, and Spinoza tended to side with
the liberals the republicans and the
imperialists, a break with ‘the economic milieu
at the same time’ (7).He
broke with the family business and became a lens
maker.
Lots of
his work remained unpublished at the time, and
this scuppered a brief ‘professorial’ stage,
involving learned expositions.Spinoza
moved again to The Hague, and remained marginal.He
also remained defensive and discussed his ideas
only with friends.Mainstream opinion remained with his
political opponents, and the recent failure of
Cromwell in the UK added to Spinoza’s anxiety
about revolutions as harmful.This
led Spinoza to become interested in why people
were irrational, not interested in liberation,
and able to turn Christianity into an intolerant
belief.His
work became denounced by all sides, because he
was interested in demystification, especially of
religion, which he saw as an affect.
War and
the assassination of his political allies
produced even more problems and his Ethics
could not be published.He
declines to become professor of philosophy at
Heidelberg in favour of remaining a private
thinker and critic.Politics
continues to concern him, especially the
possibilities of liberating the multitude.
Despite
these sad circumstances, Spinoza remained as an
advocate of the positive life.He
wanted to avoid ‘that internal death, the
universal sadomasochism of the tyrant – slave’
(13), perhaps at the expense of failing to
realize the power of the negative.However,
reducing the joys of life produced both inward
humiliations like bad conscience and guilds, and
outward ones like resentment.
His method
can only be seen against the background of the
celebration of life as ‘a way of being’ (13).Spinoza
rejects satire as malicious.His
geometric method is a means of intellectual
invention, rectification, the proper connection
of causes and effects as a kind of optical
geometry.The
philosophy and the profession of lens polishing
come together. Only the thinker can develop a
properly potent life.He
only wanted to reveal his thoughts to others,
not impose them.
Chapter
two On the Difference Between the Ethics
and A Morality
Spinoza is
famous for the idea that there is a single
substance with an infinite number of attributes,
uniting God and nature.This
denies the transcendental God, and implies a
number of ‘practical theses that made Spinozism
an object of scandal’ (17).
Spinoza
was one of the few philosophers to investigate
what a body was [perhaps this had been put on
the agenda by developments in anatomy?].He saw
mind and body as existing in parallel, not one
causing the other or remaining prior in any
sense.This
had an implication for the notion of morality as
‘the domination of the passions by
consciousness’ (18).Instead,
an action in the mind is necessarily an action
in the body, or passion in the body is
necessarily a passion in the mind.Just
as the body acts in a way which is not usually
grasped in ordinary thought, so thought itself
is not contained in consciousness: the
philosopher needs to acquire an adequate
knowledge of both body and mind.In
both cases, ordinary consciousness needs to be
replaced by adequate thought.
This means
that consciousness is actually an illusion,
which merely registers effects.Actually
what is happening is that there are causes
behind these effects of which we are not aware.In
Spinoza’s case, these are the result of
relations between parts of the body and or parts
of the idea.Bodies can encounter other bodies, and
ideas other ideas.Sometimes this encounter leads to a
combination, something more powerful, and on
other occasions, one body decomposes the other
‘destroying the cohesion of its parts’ (19).Consciousness
only registers these encounters—we experience
new combinations as joy, and decomposition as
sadness.In
particular, consciousness is unable to grasp
other bodies and their relations with our own.
Because
consciousness is an illusion, ‘it is scarcely
possible to think that little children are
happy, or that the first man was perfect’
(19-20) [philosophical issues of the time,
presumably?] Most people have only consciousness
and are ‘condemned to undergo effects, they are
slaves of everything, anxious and unhappy, in
proportion to their imperfection’ (20) [I am
already hearing a hint of John Stuart Mill
here—I have long suspected that Spinoza/Deleuze
is some kind of 17th century
utilitarian on stilts]
Consciousness
operates with three illusions: (A) since it can
only grasp effects, it tends to take those
effects for causes; (B) if it grasps causes at
all these are seen as strictly limited—the most
immediate cause is the final cause of action [I
think].This
leads to the illusion that consciousness itself
is a first cause [because consciousness
registers immediate effects?]; (C) when
consciousness realizes its own limits, it
invokes a notion of God as a final cause, or the
world as a result of God’s decree.These
illusions constitute consciousness.
Consciousness
itself is driven by desire (appetite together
with consciousness of the appetite).This
consciousness itself is limited, as usual.So
desire has to be defined differently, as an
effort at self preservation or conatus.When
we encounter self preservation, we act
differently—objects emit ‘determinative
affections’ (21), which produce the usual
results, a joy or sadness, according to whether
they combine with us or decompose us.Consciousness
tends to represent this as variations of the
conatus, an awareness of the potency of objects.Nevertheless,
information about objects is still confused and
distorted.
Spinoza
interprets God's injunction to Adam not to eat
the fruit as an example of superior knowledge
that the fruit will act as a poison, decomposing
and rearranging parts of Adam’s body and
therefore compromising his essence.Adam
misinterprets this as a moral command.All
systems of morality are disguised bits of
information about the effects of bad encounters
[sounds like Bentham here].‘There
is no Good or Evil, but there is good and bad’
(22).Good
things happen when bodies combine to increase
their power, as when we eat food.Bad
things happen when our bodies’ relations are
decomposed, as when we eat poison [whose affects
are seen as breaking down the blood].So
good and bad really refer to objective effects,
but these are relative and partial, according to
whether they agree with our nature or not.
It follows
that individuals are good if they try to
increase their power and joy by searching out
the right combinations, and bad if they are
‘servile, or weak, or foolish’ (23), not
attempting to systematize the results of
experience, but often believing that they will
always be able to get away with things.This
will inevitably lead to self-destructive guilt,
or resentment towards others, spreading
powerlessness and poison.
In this
way, the Ethics also dispenses with the
notion of morality as the judgement of God.The
idea of transcendental values to judge things by
is unnecessary, an illusion just like the
illusions of consciousness.Misunderstanding
arises because people simply wait for the
effects, and they think of some kind of moral
law rather than a natural law: we establish and
obey laws only when we do not understand, just
like rote learning in arithmetic (23).This
has led to the need to be very cautious about
what’s meant by natural laws, and Spinoza
prefers to talk of 'eternal truths'.
Relying on
laws does not lead to any knowledge, and invokes
a power relation either in the name of the
tyrant, as a prelude to knowledge (Christianity)
, or to regulate those who are seen to be
incapable of knowledge.Theology
has classically confused the relation between
knowledge and law, and there is a pervasive
error in ontology where commands replace
something which needs to be understood.Law is
transcendent, but ethical knowledge and judgment
is immanent (25).
The
differences between ethics and morality have an
important consequence.Morality
has led to the emergence of people who exploit
sad passions, satirists who make fun of them,
and slaves who are the victims of them, ‘the
slave, the tyrant, and the priest…, the moralist
trinity’ (25).Spinoza argued that despots have always
used religion as a convenient mystery to
persuade people to fight for a system that
enslaves them.This shows a kind of bad connection in
sadness between the endlessness of desire, and
the confusion over what it should be aimed at.Tyrants
rely on sad spirits and vice versa—they are
united in hatred of life and resentment.The
resentful have always supported war and absolute
discipline [there is a nice sections saying that
young men who cannot bear to be disciplined by
their parents are perfectly happy to be
disciplined in the army, or in zealotry, as a
way of taking vengeance on their parents, no
matter at what price 26].
We need to
celebrate life, avoiding transcendent values,
the illusions of consciousness, the categories
of Good and Evil, and hatred including self
hatred.The
bad passions tend to accumulate—‘first, sadness
itself, then hatred, perversion, mockery, fear,
despair, morsus conscientiae [?translated
on
Wikipedia as ‘the [apparent]bite of
conscience’], pity, indignation, envy, humility,
repentance, cruelty’ (26).Even
the more active ones replicate the feelings of
slaves.Then
the bits that has been quoted as if it were
Deleuze himself, but is really Deleuze
continuing to expound Spinoza: ‘The true city
offers citizens the love of freedom instead of
the hope of rewards or even the security of
possessions; for “it is slaves, not free men,
who are given rewards for virtue”’.The
more sad passions we have, the more ‘our whole
life is a death worship’.
There is a
clear connection with the theory of affections.Individuals
are ‘a singular essence, which is to say, a
degree of power’ (27).This
essence involves relations and capacities for
being affected, being filled by affections.Animals
are only capable of certain capacities to be
affected [and this produces an ethological
categorisation, not the usual ‘moral’ one of
genera and species obeying laws].When
it comes to an ethology of man, there are two
sorts of affections—actions and passions, the
former arising from the nature of the
individual, and the latter from something else
outside.Being
acted upon is also considered as a kind of power
[in the sense of capacity?].Actions
and passions can vary, ‘in inverse ratio to one
another’.
Passions
are further subdivided.What
they do is to ‘fill our capacity for being
affected while separating us from our power of
acting’.Encountering
other bodies can mean that they oppose and
diminish or block our power of acting, and this
produces sadness, but when we relate to a body
that agrees with our nature and which compounds
ours, we are affected by joy.Joy is
still a passion because it as an external cause,
even though we feel we own it.As our
power of acting is increased, we feel we are
more ‘worthy of action, of active joys’ (28) [so
this is where the ‘automatic’ development of
human beings might fit in?].
Sadness
means we are at our lowest degree of power, most
alienated, and most susceptible to superstition
and mystification, impotence.The
problem for the Ethics then turns to
considering how we might maximize joyful
passions, and therefore active feelings; how we
manage to form adequate ideas which are the
source of active feelings, and how we become
conscious of ourselves.In
each case, we are struggling against ‘our place
in nature’ and ‘our natural conditions’ (28).These
practical theses explain the point of all the
other elements of the Ethics, including
oneness, univocity, parallelism and the rest.The
implications are actually developed best in the
additional scholia, corresponding to the
more formal logical definitions and sections
[discussed more fully in Deleuze’s Essays].In
particular, there is a central notion of
immanence, which ‘is the unconscious itself, and
the conquest of the unconscious’ (29).In
this way, the development of thought also
brings joy [I think].
Chapter
three The Letters on Evil (correspondence with
Blyenbergh)
Blyenbergh
questioned Spinoza about evil in the form of
four letters (with four replies).Blyenbergh
was
a grain broker!Spinoza discusses the issues ‘as if he
were himself fascinated by the subject’ [a kind
of early indirect free speech?].Blyenbergh’s
questions really got to the heart of it, and
forced Spinoza to give examples and develop his
thoughts, especially of evil [which sounds like
a good kind of conversation after all?Shame
someone did not do this with Deleuze!].Spinoza
is going to argue that ‘being is beyond good and
evil’ (31).
The first
question was how ‘evil wills’ could be seen as
produced by God.Spinoza’s answer is one we’ve seen
already, that God was really just giving
chemical advice to Adam, not moral regulation.Bad
things disturb our nature, but what if we have a
nature that likes being disturbed?And
how can disgust actually lead to virtue?Blyenbergh
also says that we only know if something is
poisonous through experience—so is there no
other source for deciding what is evil (like
revelation or knowledge?) (32).[The
problem with all insistence that learning is
experiential].
Poisoning
for Spinoza means the decomposition of parts of
the body.However
composite bodies can have parts of different
types which can enter into different
relations—how does one relation become dominant?Why do
some individuals have blood dominated by chyle,
and some by lymph?Poison works by disrupting or decomposing
these relations, and final destruction produces
death, ‘”a different relation of motion and
rest”’ (32).This is seen in terms of a relation being
an eternal truth [see above], but having its
parts rearranged, to form a different relation,
which is no longer eternally true.Blyenbergh
apparently picked up the implication that the
soul must also disintegrate when bodies die.
Apparently,
this helped Spinoza address the usual view that
evil is nothing [it now becomes a particular
harmful form of relation—a particular relation
that does not disturb the general thesis that
relations have to agree with the natural order
(maybe}].Again,
this
secularizes [my word] the notion of evil.
However
the situation is obviously complicated.We
might have a mixture of good and bad relations.The
relations themselves might change as we grow
older, and sometimes changing relations, as in
the form of chronic illness, makes us wonder ‘if
it is the same individual that goes on living’
(34).Sometimes
we can modify parts of ourselves so as to turn
against our entire health and wellbeing [a note
on page 34 indicates Spinoza’s response to this
last problem, which Deleuze finds surprisingly
contemporary—for example in discussing
autoimmune diseases, or whether people should be
kept artificially alive].
Blyenbergh
is still not happy, [insisting that there are
external definitions of vice or evil].He
thinks the idea that there are mixtures of
relations ends in confusion and relativism,
since evil seems to exist ‘to the same degree as
good’ (35) [with a nice example—it’s just as
positive and joyful to perform the sexual
act with another man’s wife than with your own].Spinoza
develops a particular logic which even Deleuze
finds obscure, [roughly that there might be
long-term or external considerations to be
weighed up beyond the immediate act—similar
problem to Utilitarianism again].Certainly
the same act, such as beating something can be
bad if it is a human being beaten, but good if
it is a piece of iron [which is too easy,
because we can all see the argument here about
whether it compounds our own relations].A
further weasel ensues: Spinoza argues that it it
is the potential for compounding or decomposing
that matters [through some strange terminology
like whether an act ‘is associated with the
image of the thing insofar
is that thing can compound with it’ (36).Of
course, this is almost entirely definitional,
far more than just experiential. Maybe this
capacity to judge comes with adequate ideas?].So no
action can be considered as inherently good or
bad, nor do intentions matter.Instead
it is this mysterious ‘image of the thing with
which the image of the act is associated’,[which
somehow is to be judged by the actor?Or is
this some notion that if there is a good outcome
it is a good act?]. In any event evil is nothing
because evil occurs with natural relations as
well.
We move on
to an argument that we need an adequate idea to
sort this out [ah!], an idea that captures the
relations between bodies [Mill thought this
could be done using social science?] .Spinoza
apparently agreed that we could see adequate
ideas, those that refer to compounding more
easily.Evil
and bad relations remains as capable of being
grasped only by an inadequate idea [again I
assume by definition?].
What of
the essences expressed in these relations?[Essences
relating to individuals?] Are some inherently
likely to produce badness, and if so, doesn’t
this reintroduce some idea of absolute evil?Blyenbergh
thinks some individuals actually like committing
crimes.Has
Spinoza done enough to refute the idea of evil
essences, beneath or outside actual relations?Spinoza
replies
by asking what it means when something pertains
to essence, and insists that badness is a matter
of affections which are missing from some
individuals, perhaps in comparison to what they
were like before [so these are qualities that
are not essential].
Blyenbergh
insists that if you can compare two essences,
you still have difficulty in comparing two
states of the same essence [or that it is rather
too convenient to assume that states change but
essences don’t].Spinoza is forced to argue that essences
never change, and that he can analyse them
at any particular moment [and Deleuze says this
does seem to contradict his notion of how people
develop sadness, a fundamental change over
time].Spinoza
is then forced to argue that particular states
somehow do express essences, and also contain a
capacity to change, to develop joy or sadness.Deleuze
says that what this means is that variation is
only empirical, and can only effect empirical
states [empirical is my word].Something
can emerge from relations between empirical
states, such as an increased power of action,
which can escalate to help us produce adequate
ideas.In
this sense, ‘the external state [is] compounded
by a happiness that depends on us alone’ (40)
[the automaton again].
Existence
is a test, but in the sense of an experiment.We do
not need God's judgment to decide what is Good
and Evil.We
only judge ourselves and our particular states.This
is the basis of ethics, not moral judgment.Essences
are eternal and singular, but they coexist with
empirical existence [handy!].We
recognize this ourselves when we think we have
an intense part, expressing some eternal truths,
and a set of extensive parts that happen to
belong to us empirically.If we
can compose these parts and increase our power
of action, this somehow helps the emergence of
affections from the intense part, but if we
destroy or decompose, this restricts the number
of affections from within.
A good man
is able to exist fully and intensely, ‘so that
death, always extensive, always external, is of
little significance to him’ (41).We use
our ethical tests to confirm our actions‘here and
now’ whether or not we have the correct relation
between essences and states—it does not depend
on final judgment nor on rewards and
punishments, simply whether we have the right
‘chemical composition (the test of gold or
clay)’ (41).
So we
actually have three components—a singular
eternal essence; characteristic relations and
capacities ‘which are also eternal truths’;
extensive parts relating to our empirical
existence, which are able to realize our
relations.Badness only exists in the last stratum,
and it depends how we use external factors.If we
destroy or decompose, we are simply not
realizing our eternal capacities.Badness
does come from outside and it is necessary
[always?], and takes the form of accidents or
death which can interrupt realization.None
of these concern our eternal relations or
essences.The
Ethics talks a lot about self
destruction, where external parts appear to
behave like foreign bodies inside, as in
autoimmune diseases [ a current example,of
course], or suicide—both are taken as examples
of Spinoza’s underlying general model of
poisoning.
So
external parts are related to essences, but do
not constitute them.External
affections can exist, and they can limit our
processes of realizing relations and
essences, as in the analyses of sadness or joy.Only
joy is internal though, an aspect of our
essence, helping us become autonomous.So
there are different relations with essences for
joy and sadness.We need external relations, however to
become conscious of ourselves and of other
things, both within and without [the former
apparently includes a ‘third kind of knowledge,
intuition’, 43].In this way, by focusing on joy we can
reduce evil to something which is at least
‘almost nothing’ in terms of our essences.
Chapter
four Index of the Main Concepts of the Ethics
[Blimey!Deleuze
has invented the ‘key concepts’ format, complete
with alphabetical order!As
always, though the alphabetical order means that
the sequences are a bit random.For
example, the very first concept ‘absolute’ does
not make a great deal of sense until you get on
to ‘attribute’.So I’m going to alter the alphabetical
order a bit in a way that makes more sense to
me.If
you like alphabetical order, you will have to
cut and paste and rearrange.I was
tempted to borrow a technique from a writer that
both Deleuze and Foucault like a lot—Roussel.He
would take a sentence, and then add comments on
each word inside a bracket, and then add further
brackets for each of those words and so on.If we
did that, we would fit in all the concepts, into
one enormous paragraph, with a large number of
nested parentheses—fun, but not very helpful.We can
only be grateful that Deleuze did not think of
this first.If I had the time, I would go back to my
days as an educational technologist, and try to
reorganise these concepts in a net—I’m tempted
to say a two dimensional rhizome.What
you do is to count the number of times a concept
gets mentioned.Those that get the most mentions appear
in the centre of the net, then you draw all the
connections to the other concepts. I suppose
WORDLE would do it as well.]
[The first
few entries in particular explain the notion of
the 'spiritual automaton' that Deleuze refers to
as a form of automatic learning, especially in Cinema 2 -- this
notion helps Badiou convict him of a highly
non-personal and non-anarchistic machinism. The
whole section is very non-humanist. Elsewhere,
hints of the notions of the virtual, the
multiplicity and the singularity leapt out at
me, behind all the C17th philosophical
terminology. Who knows if this is all 'really'
in Spinoza or just the result of Deleuze's
buggery of the old chap?]
[Overall,
this was a hard slog that took days. I have put
arguments in my own homely terms, but not
précised them very much because I have not read
Spinoza before. It might be some small gain in
knowledge, or it might be one of Deleuze's
strategies, but I think the discusion gets more
critical towards the end, when we discuss things
like MIND-BODY or NATURE]
ABSOLUTE.Absolute
substances
have all the attributes.There
are still a bit mysterious though because each
attribute is infinite in its kind, yet they
still all refer to ‘the same, ontologically
unary [sic] Being’ (44).Deleuze
refers to this as a technique of displacement to
infer Being.The
absolute also refers to the powers of God, who
both acts and thinks [and these are important
powers that human beings know about—the powers
of God exceeds human powers though].
ATTRIBUTES
[out of alphabetical order, but more helpful if
it comes next?].These are what human beings attach to
substances when they try to establish essences.These
are not just simple perceptions, which
arconfined just to what is; they are not some
additional qualities emanating from substances,
because there is only one substance.Attributes
express essences [so this is where
Deleuze gets this dubiously ambiguous notion of
‘expression’ from, which enables him to go on to
say that things express themselves, not just
humans, part of the project to dethrone human
subjectivity].The intellect perceives this expression.The
essences ultimately belong to absolute substance
as above.
Attributes,
however are ‘distinct in reality’ (51), and self
sufficient.Spinoza identifies a substance for each
attribute as a form of possibility, but human
beings actually know only two—thought and
extension, simply because we are mind and body.However,
God must be capable of contributing lots more
attributes.
Attributes
establish the essences of substance, and also
the essences of MODE [one of several mentions of
this concept, so I’m going to discuss it
immediately below].This
seems to be arguing that human and divine
attributes, say of extension, have the same form
[but different modes?].This
sort of direct connection, helped Spinoza reject
other notions of the linking of the empirical to
the divine—including ‘immanence, equivocity, and
analogy’ (52) [so this is very similar to
Deleuze’s rejection of conventional thinking in
Difference and
Repetition].It is
the notion of[non divine]immanence
that is being developed here, where ‘the same
attributes are affirmed of the substance they
compose and of the modes they contain’ (52).These
modes are going to help us explain cause and
necessity.
MODE.Relates
to a form of being which appears in something
else [Spinoza apparently calls it “the
affections of a substance” (91)]. [This seems to
include bodies, actual beings or actual people
as in POWER below, with humans not given any
special status of course]. This is
contrasted to something which is being in
itself, or substance.Substances
and modes are related in the same way that
essences and properties, and causes and
effects[a running problem -- see NATURE].All
arise through immanence ( so existing things are
just modes of universal substance, it dawned on
me eventually].There are epistemological implications as
well.For
example, essences have properties, but it would
be wrong to think that the intellect alone can
explain substances in terms of their essences
and properties.Instead, the substance explains itself,
‘expressing itself in the intellect’, and
allowing the intellect to infer the essence
through the properties that it expresses.Modes
are different from substances and essences, and
yet they are produced as attributes that
constitute the essence of substance [this
delightful {!} ambiguity and weaselling
between difference and similarity runs through
an awful lot of Deleuze—see my despairing notes
on his commentary on
Foucault for example].
Again, God
produces an infinity of things and an infinity
of modes, and some of them might appear
empirically as cause and effect.This
makes [causes and?] effects things but of
a rather fishy kind -- ‘real beings which
have an essence and existence of their own, but
do not exist and have no being apart from the
attributes in which they are produced’ (91) [so
we’ve still kept the idea of a univocal Being
with its attributes, despite noticing causes and
effects which appear to be different
categories?].
Modes are
not just produced by reason, as fictions [see
below], but are original in their own right.What
makes them specific is ‘the type of infinite
that corresponds to [them]’ (92).There
is an ‘immediate infinite mode’, which is an
‘infinite intellect in the case of thought,
motion and rest in the case of extension’ (92),
and what makes this infinite is that it is
composed of an infinity of actual parts, such as
actual ideas as part of intellect, bodies as
elementary forces as parts of extensionThe
‘mediate infinite mode is…All
the relations of motion and rest governing the
determinations of the modes as existing [or in
thought] the ideal relations governing the
determinations of ideas’ (92).Therefore
finite or specific modes are not separate in
essence from all the other essences in the
immediate infinite mode above; do not exist
separately from all the other existing modes as
in the media infinite mode above; are not
separate from the infinity of extensive parts
that each existing mode possesses. [ I find this
all pretty puzzling but I think it means you can
consider modes as infinite multiplicities or as
the more actualized singularities that are
produced]
[Back to
alphabetical order]
ABSTRACTIONS.These
are different from common notions [see below].Common
notions refer to things which bodies
have in common, which allow them to affect each
other.Abstract
ideas arise when we have to imagine rather than
actually comprehend, when we know we are being
affected in a way that exceeds the capacity to
understand.We have to rely on ‘an extrinsic sign, a
variable perceptible characteristic that strikes
our imagination, and that we set up as an
essential trait while disregarding the others
(man as an animal of erect stature, or as an
animal that laughs…etc.)’
(45) [pretty much a theory of ideology here].Instead
of understanding the unity of the composition,
we rely on perceptible similarities and
differences [as in positivism!] and we establish
our own continuities and discontinuities, for
example as ‘arbitrary analogies in Nature’.
Thus
abstraction is a form of fiction, explaining
things through images.Similarly,
‘fiction presupposes abstraction’.Inadequate
ideas
combine abstraction and fiction.For
example,fictitious
abstractions include categories like ‘classes,
species, and kinds’, where we attribute some
generic characteristic to classify animals.Spinoza
suggests that we should categorize beings
instead by their ‘capacity for being affected’
[see above], a classification of beings
according to their power.This
will help us understand the relations between,
say animals and human beings—animals which we
eat, and animals which we use, depending on
their capacity to be affected.
Secondly,
number is an abstract idea, since it presupposes
classes, kinds and species.It is
a useful fiction, however, but it does not tell
us much about existing substance or modes.In
particular, it is inadequate to graspthe infinity
of nature and the infinity of parts in bodies.The
third set of abstractions are the
transcendental, where a particular
characteristic is assumed to be transcendental,
and is usually opposed to some characteristic of
less value—‘(being/non being, unity/plurality,
true/false…)’ (47).We’ve
already seen that, for example Good and Evil are
really just abstracts of specific good and bad
effects.
Spinoza
specifically discusses ‘geometric beings’.These
are clearly abstract, found only in reason,
measurable in order to aid thought, and also
implying ‘a non being’ (47).However,
geometric beings are unusual in that they can be
produced by actions [I think—for example we can
produce a circle by fixing one end of the line
and moving the other].No
actual circles in nature are produced like this,
though, so there is no essence being expressed.Even
when ideas do match the way in which real things
are produced, this is no guarantee of the truth
of ideas—truth refers to the power of thinking
alone.However,
thinking about geometric objects does develop
our powers of comprehension, and even thought
about the possible power of God, who might
ultimately be responsible for them.At the
divine level, there is no need for fiction or
abstraction, and ideas do correspond to real
things.Thinking
of the geometric methods does help us see what
COMMON NOTIONS might look like, and how they are
related to the imagination.
[So let’s
look at...]
COMMON
NOTIONS ‘represent[s] something common to bodies
[not minds]’ (54).This makes them general not abstract [so
immediately heading in the wrong direction for
Deleuze].There
is a connection here with the idea of a
composition between two bodies, so a common
notion represents some real combination between
bodies: ‘Its meaning is more biological than
mathematical’ (54), and the idea in the mind is
secondary—only arising once bodies have been
affected.
However,
all bodies have in common ‘extension, motion and
rest’ (55), and can be combined from the point
of view of the mediate infinite mode above.However,
differences and oppositions can also be formed
[presumably because bodies also have things
where they disagree, in the finite?].
Common
notions are therefore adequate, emerging from
the real process of composition.The
problem is how we might form them.Spinoza
seems to suggest at first that : we start
with the most general and head to the least
general, in order to understand the disagreement
at less general levels.Here,
the assumption is that common notions are given.However,
we can also form them by encountering other
bodies, but initially inadequately, since we
mostly experience joy or sadness not
knowledge as such.Indeed, only joy motivates us to explore
common notions—‘it is an occasional cause of the
common notion’ (55).
Therefore,
man is not born rational but can become
rational.Following
reason means first trying to organize good
encounters to achieve joy, and second trying to
develop common notions, and then further notions
that follow from them, to become active in
seeking experiences.We
have to avoid sadness.
This is
why the first common notions are usually the
least general ones, the reverse of the
suggestion above, the ones arising from specific
encounters. These
can produce joy which in turn encourages a more
active exploration.Then
we develop more general notions, which can
encompass relations with other bodies even where
they do not produce joy.This
then produces a [higher] kind of active joy
[some sort of intellectual joy or mastery type
joy?].This
second approach is developed in the Ethics,
and offers a new basis for adequate ideas, not
abstract or fictional geometric ideas but the
experiences of the real.
Common
notions do not extend to grasping essences.As
adequate ideas, however, which must ultimately
belong to God, they can give us an idea of God.Ultimately,
God is what all modes have in common.Like
all common notions, God produces affects in the
form of religious feeling.However,
God is more than just a common notion, but an
essence, uniting the different modes.By
following the implications, we get to the stage
where we are beginning to understand the essence
of God and the connection with essences of real
beings.This
does involve going beyond rationality as such
and developing ‘the intuitive intellect as a
system of essential truths (sometimes called
CONSCIOUSNESS [of God and the divine?])’ (58).There
is an element of imagination too in moving from
specific notions to general ones—we recognize
the images of bodies.The
images are not adequate ideas in themselves, but
need to be explained through common notions.However,
without
images, imagination, we would not subsequently
develop common notions.
CONSCIOUSNESS.This
is where we duplicate ideas, develop ‘the idea
of the idea’ (59).Ideas represent objective attributes, but
become attributes themselves so they can be
represented by another idea.Consciousness
therefore has three aspects: (A) reflection, but
defined rather oddly as ‘the reflection of the
idea in the mind’ [nothing to do with individual
thinking subjects] (59); (B) consciousness is
derived from ideas and can only work with what
the idea gives them; (C) ideas of ideas relate
to ideas in the same way that ideas relate to
objects.
Consciousness
‘is completely immersed in the unconscious’.We
only become conscious of ideas in particular
conditions, and we can never become as conscious
as God is—it all depends on empirical encounters
with external bodies first.We
don’t only think with ideas, but conatus too[defined here as an aspect of POWER, an
appetite which can ‘persevere in existing’].This
is revealed through
affects but also modes of thinking [some kind of
persisting pattern that forces itself into
thought?].These affections enable us to reflect
back on the idea.The conatus when it becomes
conscious, produces desire: becoming conscious
of the conatus is motivated by the
affections it produces [see POWER below].
Consciousness
naturally deals with inadequate ideas, and this
produces two illusions—the illusion of freedom,
where consciousness imagines it is free rather
than an effect, and that it exercises power over
the body;’ the theological illusion of
finality’, where consciousness grasps the ideas
of affections as primary, ultimately the result
of a provident God.Apart
from anything else, this last one produces the
illusion that ‘the desire appears to be
secondary in relation to the idea of the thing
judged good’ (60).
Actually,
consciousness has no power by itself [the
example is the perception of the sun as a small
object close to—in this way, inadequate ideas
can still generate something that appear as a
positive].Spinoza seems to be suggesting that it is
these inadequate ideas that can lead
nevertheless to further inquiry and the pursuit
of adequate ideas, a proper understanding of
ideas and their relations to attributes, and
thus the dispelling of illusions.This
in turn permits us to be more active, and
eventually to become conscious of God and one’s
self.The
final result will be ‘to make these ideas
reflect themselves in us just as they are in
God’ (61). [the 3 stages of the spiritual
automaton]
POWER.God’s
power is not potestas [roughly,naked
power to force people] as with earthly rulers.Nor
does God think up possibilities which he then
realizes through his will.Instead,
all consequences follow from God’s essence, from
what he comprehends.God’s
essence is not potestas but potentia,
something active.Divine power is a power to exist and
produce things, and also to comprehend, as in
the two parts of the ABSOLUTE.This
is not the same as the more empirical forms of
extension and thought [which we can just about
deduce from the above].
Thus power
is inseparable from a capacity to be affected.This
capacity is always realized by and in
affections.There is therefore a kind of implicit potestas
in potentia after all.Modes
[actual beings -- see above] are essentially
degrees of power.Human power is part of God’s infinite
power, and in the same way, modes come into
existence in the form of an infinite collection
of extensive parts.It is
this process that produces conatus or
appetite—because modes retain in their essences
something which does not immediately pass into
existence. In this sense, a mode perseveres, or
endures. [clear
hints of the idea of a multiplicity or
singularity then?]
This also
implies a capacity to be affected, a further
implication of the term conatus.With substances,
active affections fill this capacity, [where
affections are the images of affects?], produced
by other modes.This makes the conatus ‘determined to do
this or that by an affection…that
occurs to it’ (99), through the development of
consciousness.The conatus is an essential component of
the mode, a determination to maintain existence.At one
level, this can be understood since the essence
of modes are parts of divine power.But at
the more concrete level there is an interaction
between modes, composition and decomposition as
above.
Thus
existing modes can develop ‘a struggle of
powers’ (100), which is inherent in nature, and
death can arise from that exposure to the
exterior and the possibility of composition and
decomposition.However, when the modes die, they are
only lose their extensive parts, not their
unrealized essence [their virtual bits] Indeed,
we cannot get to essences simply by looking at
how long things have persevered [and apparently
vice versa].This implies that the intensive parts of
the mode agree with the other modes, but not
their extensive parts.
[The
possible combinations produce joy and sadness
and all that as before].In
sadness, our whole power as conatus is aimed at
destroying the object, reacting to it.The
conatus generally wants to experience joy and
increase its power of acting.This
is what unites the various definitions of
conatus—something that wants to preserve itself,
something dynamic that wishes to increase its
powers, something dialectical that opposes that
which will oppose it.
However,
considerable variations in actually existing
relations are inevitable.Again,
the powers are being affected can vary, for
example, as we age.Nevertheless
existing
modes have a right to survive and expand,
although individuals have different powers: both
rational and foolish people strive to persevere,
but they have different powers.In
this way, the conatus can be realized in
different actions—sometimes we have to persevere
in existing by taking risks, or destroy things
which threaten our joy, and this can compromise
the joys we feel.There is always the risk of encountering
something more powerful that will destroy us, or
more hostile modes.Reason
can guide us in actively pursuing adequate ideas
that will produce joy.This
is Virtue, even if it does end in death.Only
Reason leads to virtue, not imagination
So the
mode also has a two fold power, of existing and
thinking.Seeking
experiences and encounters produces a more
capable mind, but our powers limit our options.Nevertheless,
we can ‘become causes of our own affects and
masters of our adequate perceptions’ (104) [this
is how the automaton works] [very like JS Mill
again?].When
we maximize our powers, we become aware of the
absolute power of God, an awareness that ‘the
mode's power is a part of God’s power…Insofar
as God’s essence is explained by the mode's
essence’ (104).
In this way, the whole of
the Ethics is really about power, as
opposed to morality.
CAUSE.Spinoza
begins by discussing the notion of ‘cause of
itself’.Deleuze
tells us the usual way of proceeding was to see
analogies between different types of causes,
especially cause of itself and ‘efficient
causality’, a more specific cause associated
with a distinct effect.Spinoza
wants to see the general kind as ‘the archetype
of all causality’ (53).
With
efficient causes, causes are separate from
effects, having both difference essences and
existences.The only thing causes have in common with
the effects is ‘the attribute, in which the
effect is produced and by which the cause acts’.God
produces these attributes, which expresses
essence, and so God is the cause of all things
as well as himself: ‘he produces in the same way
that he exists’, which preserves the university
of attributes and their relation to substances.This
is how a general cause is the cause of
everything else. Finite things can relate to
other finite things as a cause, but they do not
relate separately or vertically to God—God is
involved from the start.In
this sense, ‘the cause is essentially immanent;
that is, it remains in itself in order to
produce’ (54). [This is the bit Althusser liked
as a way of weaselling round the issue of
economic determinism?]
AFFECTIONS,
AFFECTS.Affections
are modes of substance or its attributes, and
are necessarily active, since they emanate from
God as adequate cause as above.They
also designate modifications of the mode, ‘the
effects of other modes on it’, acting as ‘images
or corporeal traces first of all’ (48).The
ideas of them, in the form of imagination
initially, however, refer to both the affected
body and the affecting external body. Once we
have formed these ideas, we can progress—‘we
pass to a greater or lesser perfection’.We
also experience durations.Durations
or variations of perfection ‘are called
“affects”, or feelings’ (49).
It looks
like affections refer to bodies, while affects
refer to minds, but there are other
differences—the imaginary relation links both
bodies and ideas, while affects act on bodies
and minds alike.The real difference is that affection
refers to the state of the affected body,
implying an external body acting on it, while
affects refer to [arise from?] ‘the
passage from one state to another’ (49).Affections
are associated with image or idea, and affects
with feelings of increased or diminished power,
which can then be represented by ideas or
affections [!]. [Maybe what this is saying is
that we feel affects first, but they are not
just feelings?]
Affects
can be recognized in a confused form, as in ‘a
passion of the mind’, a simple affirmation of
increase or decrease of force.Proper
affects are ‘not indicative or representative’,
since they require a transition or duration,
grasping differences.This
is not an intellectual grasping, not a
comparison of ideas, but a greater or lesser
involvement in reality (49).[What the fuck is
that then --something beyond mere ideas or
feeble imaginations? Naive realism?]
Modes vary
in their capacity to be affected, and can
undergo good and bad encounters, which lead to
greater or lesser perfection.[There
is almost a simple arithmetic here, where the
power of modes can be added or subtracted].We
know already that this is experienced as ‘an
affect, or feeling’ (50) of joy or sadness. But these
affects have external causes, mediated through
the capacity to be affected.
If
feelings or affects are recognized as coming
from external encounters, we can explain them. They do
not come from us, so they can be called
‘passions, since we are not their adequate
cause’ (50).[seems to describe the way in which
passions are commonly seen to overwhelm us,
affect us despite our will, arising from
somewhere outside?].Joy is
a passion in this sense.In the
process, we recognize that we already have
inadequate ideas of both the external and our
own bodies [as in being forced to think?]If we
do not understand this, we are still passive.
However,
the link between the passion of joy and action
is more productive than for sadness as we saw. This can
help us develop adequate ideas instead of
confused images, as long as we recognize what is
going on [grasping the essence of bodies and God
ultimately].Such development means we can fully
understand the power of what is happening, and
achieve the state of blessedness [full powers,
unity with God, = recognition of the
multiplicity, the joy for Deleuze?].
METHOD.Method
is about understanding how we know things,
becoming conscious of this power, being able to
develop ‘an idea of the idea’ as we saw above.This
still requires us to try and develop true ideas
in the first place, and ‘it matters little which
idea; it can be an idea that involves a fiction,
such as that of a geometric being’ (83).
As this
implies, Spinoza’s method starts with geometry.Geometric
ideas are fictional, that is they do not
represent anything in nature.We can
also begin with substances, in Spinoza’s later
work, and develop common notions as we saw—these
are not fictional.We then attempt to form ideas of these
ideas.However,
these metaideas [I am going to call them] have
an inner content which is not just a
representative [or induced] content, since they
are also produced by the power of knowing
itself.This
power acts as a kind of cause again.It is
this that makes metaideas adequate [I’m reminded
of Weber’s two kinds of adequacy here, one
relating to the objects, and the other to social
theories].
This leads
Spinoza to argue that geometric beings have
causal or genetic definitions which determine
all the properties, and, later, to develop the
notion of a single substance from the ideas of
particular substances each with its attribute.As
usual, we go from knowledge of the thing to
knowledge of its cause.However,
a further step is required, not just some
[empirical, inductive] collection of the
properties of things, but a view of an essence
as the reason for all the knowable properties.The
point is to get as quickly as possible to this
essence.In
Spinoza’s terminology, of course, it is the idea
of God.
Getting to
this essential level involves a considerable
change.Once
there, we can leave behind fictions, and we can
also leave behind ‘the
synthetic method’ [the way of combining
particular attributes to try and get to some
underlying essence?].Once
we get to God, we can pursue by contrast
‘a progressive deduction in which all ideas
connect with one another starting from the idea
of God’ (85). The procedure is like the
development of common notions, except that the
essence is not itself a common notion.Once
we have achieved the level of thought required,
however, we have no need to generalize
[empirically, inductively] , but instead can
trace explanatory paths ‘from the essence of God
to the essences of things as real singular
beings’ (85).[Philosophy beats empirical studies. Get
up to the multiplicity then back down again].
This is
also a way of avoiding classifying things by
what they represent: instead there is some
‘autonomous order’ connecting things together
[arrived at by a form of transcendental
deduction -- or abduction?].This
escalation of ways of thinking, from induction
to working ideas to philosophizing [from
‘reflexive – formal aspects’, and ‘expressive –
material aspects’ to an overall ‘progressive –
synthetic’ method, 85] explains why Spinoza
thinks the mind operates as a spiritual
automaton—‘since by unfolding the autonomous
order of its own ideas it unfolds the order of
things represented’ (85) [I’m still not
convinced.The whole thing seems to depend on some
underlying drive to knowledge or search for joy
I suppose.
Why else would we unfold? Does this
affect everyone or just philosophers?].
The early
work on the geometric method helps us get to the
first two levels.At the first level, the fictional
character of geometric beings gives us a bit
more freedom to get to genetic definitions [I
think]. At the next level, common notions can
develop a ‘deep affinity’ with geometric beings
[I am not at all sure why, except that geometric
shapes can be seen in real life, and even used
in practical skills?].This
is why Spinoza calls his method a geometrical
one, since it leads particularly to the second
level of knowledge and the common notions.However,
at the third stage, there might be a problem.Common
notions have to be surpassed, and apparently,
Spinoza suggests how this might happen through
an argument that ‘likens demonstrations to “eyes
of the mind”’ (86).[geometrical
definitions as proofs?These
transcend commonsense reasoning?].In any
event, geometric methods apparently can reach
this third level [possibly by encouraging the
development in the intellect which ‘imparts to
the geometric methods sufficient force to go
beyond its ordinary limits, ridding it of the
fictions and even the generalities that
accompany its restricted use’ (86).It is
certainly true that Euclidean geometry did lead
to far more philosophical geometries, as DeLanda
explains].
SUBSTANCE.Something
of
which the concept does not require another
concept.Something
that is in itself and is conceived through
itself.This
rules out multiple substances which could be
conceived or understood in some other ways
above, forming common notions and the rest of
it.Even
numerical distinctions are not real.It
follows from this that substance also confers
‘unicity, self causality, infinity, and
necessary existence on each qualified substance’
(109), in other words, producing different
attributes in different substances [empirical or
actual substances, that is] the real connection
between substance and its various actual
manifestations is best understood as ‘the
qualitative multiplicity or a formal – real
distinction’ (109).
Since
Spinoza is unhappy about numerical distinctions,
he refers to a substance as ‘absolutely
singular’ [rather than as One] , possessing all
the distinct attributes, and the infinite
essences which are expressed by these
attributes.The distinction between the formal and
the real should not be seen as denying the
absolute ontological unity of substance ‘on the
contrary it constitutes that unity’ (109).
SIGN.Signs
are produced by the apparent separation of
effects from causes.When
something causes an effect on us, we do not
experience it at the level of essences, but
rather ‘in terms of a momentary state of our
variable constitution and the simple presence of
the thing whose nature we do not know’ (105).We
recognize an indicative sign [indicative of this
cause and effect].Signs are always effects of mixtures,
indicating the state of our body, and the
presence of an external body as a secondary
stage.This
is the origin of conventional signs and
language. The system of signs is equivocal
because signs can take on variable meanings
according to the chains in which they are
embedded [I think, 106].
Signs can
be causes, in another sense, where the proper
relation between cause and effect is not
understood.Back to the example of God’s advice to
Adam, leading Adam to see the moral law as or
cause, and God’s intervention as a sign.This
is a typical example of how a moral law actually
arises from confused understandings, and, once
established as a law, limits further
understandings.Laws are seen as limit on power instead
of an opportunity to develop them [unlike
geometric proofs].Eternal truths become imperatives.A
whole additional class of signs
emerges—‘imperative signs, or effects of
revelation; they have no other meaning than to
make us obey’ (106).Theology
is complicit in confusing obeying and knowing.
Signs can
also be external guarantees for these mystified
moral laws, as when prophets see events as
signs, indicating communications from God.These
are ‘interpretive’ signs—for Spinoza ‘effects of
superstition’ (107).
Together,
signs can form an ‘essentially equivocal
language of imagination’, to be contrasted with
the ‘natural language of philosophy, composed of
univocal expressions’ (107).Overall,
signs are inadequate ideas, requiring
interpretation by the imagination.They’re
not ‘expressions amenable
to explications by the lively intellect’ (107).
SOCIETY.[So
far, the missing dimension.Up
until now, when Spinoza and Deleuze talk about
bodies interacting, they presumably mean as a
dyad?There
is no discussion of what might be seen as social
pressures on consciousness, merely a language of
error, and an implicit elitism where
philosophers congratulate themselves for
developing adequate ideas.Actually,
we start, as might have been anticipated with
naive functionalism].A
group of men combine their respective powers to
produce a ‘more powerful whole’ (107).The
state can also defend individuals against the
risk of encountering destructive forces.The
state ‘resembles the state of reason, and yet it
only resembles it, prepares for it, or takes its
place’ (107).According to Reason, men should compose
groups themselves using ‘intrinsic relations…common
notions…and
the active feelings that follow from them (in
particular, freedom, firmness, generosity [piety
and religiosity])’ (107).[more
like an idealized market then, or a utilitarian
civil society?].
In actual
states, there is also an ‘extrinsic order,
determined by passive feelings of hope and fear’
(107), where hope and fear are defined as fear
of remaining in a state of nature and hope of
emerging from it.In the state of Reason, law, as an
eternal truth, can be the natural guide for the
development of each individual.In the
civil state, or law restrains and limits
individuals, acting as a moral law as above.
Nevertheless,
civil states have to preserve natural rights,
both as a form of legitimacy, and also because
it is affections and passions that provide
social solidarity, not common notions.In
particular, it is common affections like the
hope of rewards and fear of punishment [and they need
regulation?]. However, these can
determine natural rights, through the conatus
[very convenient] and establish some kind of
collective existence [we move from primeval war
of all against all to some kind of regulation] .In
other words, Spinoza has a contract theory,
working in two stages: (A) men give up their
individual powers for the benefit of the whole
which they agree to let regulate conduct in the
interests of hope and fear; (B), this power then
gets transferred to a state: in democracy, this
tends to see the main affection of reason as the
love of freedom rather than the old fears and
hopes [despite all his excellent reasoning
elsewhere, he reproduces the banality of a
contract view!! I wonder if this also inspired
Deleuze's oscillations between total control and
anarchism?]
[Might
as well round up the rest. Sorry this is
taking so long...]
DEFINITION,
DEMONSTRATION.The definition is a statement about what
is distinctive about a thing in itself.This
must be a matter of the essence of the thing.There
are both nominal and real definitions: the first
ones use abstractions or PROPRIA, or formal
definitions like geometric ones relating to
circles.These
are all extrinsic, but real ones are genetic,
‘they state the cause of the thing, or its
genetic elements’ (61).So
Spinoza defines desire as appetite and
consciousness, but proceeds to the real level by
adding the cause of this consciousness, the
affections.Even God can have a genetic definition
because he is the cause of himself.
In the
case of God, the real definition is a priori,
but most [all?] real definitions are a
posteriori, using bodily capacity
to define something after the event. Although
capacity and power are essential, we only know
what they’re like once we have experienced
affections.There are some things that have real and
nominal definitions such as geometric figures,
which are abstract ideas formed from common
notions.
Once we
have a definition, we can proceed to
demonstration [argument?] by deducing the
properties of the thing defined.This
necessarily involves other objects and external
things and their relations.With
real definitions, we can capture essential
movements internal to the thing, independently
of these external relations.‘It is
the thing that “explains itself” in the
intellect, and not the intellect that explains
the thing’ (62).
DURATION.Existing
modes
have duration, that is they exist over time from
the beginning.The essence of things is that they have a
tendency to persevere, but no end can be
assigned to a thing in advance either by
essences or causes—so duration is indefinite
continuation.Death is a form of external relation as
we saw.Duration
‘is made up of the lived transitions that define
its affects, constant passages to greater or
lesser perfections, continual variations of the
existing mode’s power of acting’ (63).Eternity
is not indefinite duration, because eternity has
no beginning [and there is a suggestion that the
relation with duration is like the natural
difference between parts that exist in bodies
and parts that express their essence].
EMINENCE.People
attribute to God properties that really belong
to human consciousness, and assume that God must
possess them in some perfect form—infinite
justice, infinite understanding and so on.Apart from
other problems, this makes the attributes
equivocal [some are seen as divine and some
not?].However,
attributes must be univocal for Spinoza.The
attributes in God are the same form as the
attributes in the modes, but the essence of God
is not the essence of the modes.We
need this distinction to explain substance as it
appears in the modes, yet retains its unity.The
notion of eminence is anthropomorphic, extrinsic
[as is consciousness] and imaginary, based on
equivocal signs [Deleuze sees exactly the same
arguments being made against analogy—no doubt
because eminence involves one between humans and
God]
ESSENCE.Something
which
is so integral to a thing, that the thing not be
conceived without it, and vice versa.This
means that the same attribute cannot have
several different substances, each of which
would be capable of conceiving of the thing.The
essence is not the same in substance and in a
mode, since substance can be conceived without
modes, but not vice versa.Attributes
constitute the essence of substance, but not the
essence of modes, ‘which merely involve the
attributes’ (64).
Even modes
that do not exist are still comprehended in the
idea of God, equally with those that do exist,
so they are ‘themselves real and actual beings’
(65)[reminiscent of Deleuze's own rejection of
the notion of possibilities, although he also
cites Leibniz?] .
The
essence of substance happens to include the
property of existence.The
same very interesting and convenient
characteristic links substance to attributes.Attributes
necessarily express existence as the essence of
substance: ‘the attributes are so many forces of
existing and acting, while essence is an
absolutely infinite power of existing and
acting’ (65).Modal essences are different.They
are singular, even though they are also a part
of God’s power.Modal essences ‘are simple and eternal’,
but these essences are not just logical
possibilities nor geometric structures, but
‘parts of power, unlike intensive quantities
that are composed of smaller quantities.They
are all compatible with one another without
limit, because all are included in the
production of each one, but each one corresponds
to a specific degree of power different from all
the others’ (65) [such a weaselly definition
that you can explain any correspondence and any
difference between two modes, without in the
least contradicting your self!]
ETERNITY.That
part of existence ‘involved by essence’ (65), an
eternal part of existence, not like duration,
which relates to the non essential parts of the
mode.However,
modes do have essences, and so they do have ‘a
certain form of eternity’, because they exist
through God [the immediate infinite mode as
above].Even
mediate infinite modes can be considered as
eternal because they are produced by eternal
rules of composition and decomposition, and each
relation is an eternal truth in this sense.In
particular, the mind can be eternal because it
partakes of this form of eternity as a body, but
also because it manages to grasp something more
in the form of common notions, eternal
relations.
The relations
that produce duration are themselves eternal,
not subject to duration.Apparently,
and rather conveniently again, our minds are
able to grasp the eternity of an essence somehow
directly, intensively, whereas we understand
duration as something that only temporarily
relates to a substance.[Well
we would, wouldn’t be, because we’ve just
defined it that way!It is
a marvel how the operations of the mind just
happen to reflect what goes on in reality and in
Spinoza's philosophy!]
[Apparently,
Spinoza is responsible for the term sub species
aeternitas, usually translated as ‘from
the perspective of eternity’].The
term species
refers to a concept or a knowledge, while it is
an idea that operates from the perspective of
eternity, to grasp the essence of a body or the
truth of things.Essences and eternal truths are eternal
‘through their cause and not through themselves…‘
(67), so they must be conceived through this
cause [that is through an idea of the cause?].Of
course, we might expect the usual ambiguity:
‘therefore species
[also actually] signifies form and idea, form
and conception, indissolubly’ (67).
EXISTENCE.Given
all the weaselling above, it is not surprising
to find that essence and existence cannot be
separated [since they implicate each other so
tightly] except as a form of reason, when we
wish to distinguish ‘the thing affirmed from its
affirmation’ (67) [and when on earth might we
wish to do this?Only most of the time, I would have
thought, but not when we are philosophizing].
However, there is a difference it seems:‘modal
essences do not involve existence’, but once in
existence, modes affect each other finitely.However
this is not a real distinction between essence
and existence, since it only operates with modes
[silly me, valuing the empirical again].
As far as
finite modes are concerned, they exist when they
have existing external causes; when they have an
infinity of extensive parts which produce
specific combinations as a result of outside
causes; when they endure or persevere, by
maintaining the specific combinations.This
implies that the infinity of expressive parts,
which are managed by specific combinations, can
be seen as the essence of the mode, including
the mind [I can only understand this rhubarb in
terms of the multiplicity again—singular modes
are affected in their actual existence by nice
concrete material forces, but they also have
infinite other parts which have not yet been
actualized, but which are still real.Focus
on the singularity and you get existence, focus
on the multiplicity and you get essences and
eternity?].This is why there is no real difference
between essence and existence, since both exist
necessarily [as a formal—real relation as
above?].
EXPLAIN –
IMPLY (EXPLICARE,
IMPLICARE).We have to remember that for Spinoza ,
explanation arises from the thing having an
effect on the intellect.So
explication is always self explication, an
unfolding: ‘the thing explains itself’ (68).It
seems a nicely circular process—substance is
explained in the attributes, the attributes
explain substance in turn, and they are
explained in the modes which also explain them.We can
also join together implication and explication
since ‘that which explains thereby implies’
(68).Since
everything is comprehended by everything else,
it’s not surprising that explication and
implication are identical, and Spinoza suggests
that we might see this as some sort of proof of
God—he complicates [explicates?] all
things, while 'each thing explains and implies
God’ (68)
There is
one exception, the inadequate idea, which we can
comprehend, but which does not itself result
from comprehension, is not explained by it [and
is a poor guide to understanding comprehension?]
.Inadequate
ideas always operate with mixtures of things,
and can never get to the level of comprehending
causes.Building
on the ambiguity of comprehension, which can
also mean comprising or containing, Deleuze goes
on to say that the intellect comprehends the
attributes and the modes, and the adequate idea
comprehends the nature of the thing.Thus,
happily ‘”what is contained objectively in the
intellect must necessarily be in nature”’ (69),
so that grasping something in the intellect is
to match thought to existence, not to conceive
of possibilities.
FREEDOM.Freedom
is traditionally seen as related to the will and
to being able to choose or create, or carry
something into effect.This
gives problems when thinking of God’s
freedom—who must therefore be some sort of
legislator, something fickle who can choose
something else, or someone who can only carry
out something that already exists.For
Spinoza, the will can never be a cause on its
own, since it is always determined by another
cause [the JS Mill bit above].Indeed,
neither the intellect nor the will are free
causes, in the sense that they do not exist in a
necessarily self sufficient state.Only
God does, which makes him the source of all the
other kinds of causes, and which gives him alone
freedom, as a necessity arising from his
essence.
Only
essences provide real freedom, and so modes are
never free because they must always refer to
something else.Ordinary consciousness can provide an
illusory sense of freedom by misunderstanding
this, as we saw above.The
poor old mode can either form a common notion,
necessarily involving a relation with the other
modes, or can insist on an essence which then
must agree with the essence of God and all other
essences.These
are the only adequate ideas, and they do provide
a form of freedom, or at least liberation, as we
saw.Thus
human beings can only become free by freeing
themselves from the flaws of ordinary
consciousness, and pursuing adequate ideas which
produce joy.In this sense, human beings discover
their own essences.Thus
‘Freedom is always linked to essence’ (71) [This
comes very close to Badiou’s
critique of Deleuze as being fatalistic, trying
only to find the way in which nature works and
submitting to it, and that only after a massive
effort to develop adequate ideas].
GOOD –
BAD.These
are clearly related together, and also related
to specific modes.They reflect the variation of the powers
discussed above, so that everything that
increases our power is good and so on.Alternatively,
‘what is good is what is useful, what is bad is
what is harmful’ (71)— Deleuze says this as an
original contribution of what counts as useful
and harmful.
Thus good
and bad arises from actual encounters between
existing modes.Death is an encounter that decomposes my
body, Adam misunderstood God, poison
is the kind of underlying model for evil.When I
act maliciously ‘I join the image of an action
to the image of an object that cannot bear this
action without losing its constitutive relation’
[I imagine a priest masturbating?] (72).
Spinoza
undertook a constant struggle against sadness,
which puts him in the same lineage as Nietzsche.Even
remorse and guilt, even hope and security should
be dismissed because they signify powerlessness
[philosophers as heroes again] .Knowledge
of our powers of acting is the greatest good,
and this is what makes reason good: once we have
developed sufficient reason, we can move away
from thinking of immediate good and bad to think
instead of potency and virtue.It is
a mistake to try instead to seek some all
purpose Good, the ‘finalist illusion’ (73).The
absolute values of good and evil are
meaningless, produced by imagination as a
misinterpretation of social signs of reward and
punishment.
IDEA.This
is a way of thinking related to other modes of
thinking, for example, an idea of a state of
things which has affects attached to it.Ideas
represent.We have ideas, but we are also an idea
ourselves, founded in God.Mostly,
ideas represent what happens to our body, and
‘are necessarily inadequate’ (73).Images
are ‘traces
of an external body of our body’ and the ideas
we have are therefore ideas of images or of
feelings.In
this way, ideas are signs, indicating states,
indicating the presence of bodies and their
relations.
We can
connect these ideas together, though.First
of all in terms of memory or habit, where one
idea helps us to recollect another one.If our
encounters with other bodies are inconstant, so
will be our ideas.The imagination constructs fictions, and
also dubious abstractions like that of species
and kind [which are formed in a kind of
primitive positivism, relating surface
appearances?].
Adequate
ideas however are different, true, the same for
us as for God.They do not represent states of things,
but relate to ‘what we are and…what
things are’ (74).They are more systematically organized
around the idea of ourselves, the idea of God,
and the idea of other things.They
arise from our power of knowing and
comprehending from our essence, as a formal
cause. They are connected autonomously in
thought, and ‘this connection…which
unites form and material is an order of the
intellect that constitutes the mind as a spiritual
automaton’ (74).
Ideas have
internal properties, a logical power not a
psychological consciousness.We
want to generate ideas which express rather than
represent.Thought operates through explication,
expression, the notions of formal and material
causes, and logical power.The
autonomy of thoughts is linked to ‘the
automatism of the mind that thinks’ (75) [I
never noticed the connection between autonomy
and automatism before!The
mind achieves autonomy by silencing the
inadequate efforts of consciousness, and letting
matter impact on it and generate ideas
automatically?].
So
inadequate ideas are not formally laid out and
explained, especially the premises for them, the
causes.They
arise as a result of ‘fortuitous encounters’ not
systematic connections (75).They
do have something positive about them though, as
we saw with the example of perception of the sun
above—the inadequate idea ‘involves the lowest
degree of the power of understanding, without
being explained by it, and indicate its own
cause without expressing it’ (75).So
imagination is fine insofar as it goes, but it
needs to be developed into an idea—for example
it is quite possible to imagine nonexistent
things like winged horses.
So how to
obtain adequate ideas?Through
common notions first.However
ideas are always followed by ‘feelings –
affects’.In
this terminology, ideas cause feelings and
affects [which guide us towards further
knowledge and towards virtue, as we saw].With
adequate ideas, we can ourselves be ‘the
adequate cause of the feelings that result, and
that consequently are active…On the
contrary, insofar as we have inadequate ideas,
we are the inadequate cause of our feelings,
which are passions’ (76).
INDIVIDUAL.Sometimes
this
means a unity between ideas and objects.However,
normally there is more complexity in the way
modes are organized.Modes
have essences which relate to the degree of
power is.Essences
are expressed in relation towards existing
things, such as motion and rest in extension.Modes
take on actual existence by being able to
organize an infinity of extensive parts in the
form of particular relations.Apparently,
this works ‘through the operation of an external
determinism’ (76).Modes cease to exist when they encounter
relations that make their parts incompatible.At the
essential level, the powers of the modes agree
with each other, but they ‘necessarily come into
conflict in existence’ (77).
The
individual is composed of actualizations of an
infinity of extensive parts [which I think of as
the multiplicity again].The
parts themselves have no essence but are
entirely empirical and extensive [which is what
I think ‘defined solely by their exterior
determinism’ means].They
are found in infinite sets, which vary in size
[I think each part varies in size from greater
to a lesser?].When modes relate, their parts can
combine or decompose each other.We can
also consider nature as an individual, although
one which possesses all the relations and all
the intensive parts.
Thus,
‘individuation is always quantitative, according
to Spinoza’ (77), when we think of it as being
produced in a mode.However,
essences can also produce a kind of
individuation, ‘defined by their singularity of
each degree of power as a simple intensive
part’.This
is matched by the actually existing bits which
have a set of extensive parts that temporarily
actualize modal essences.[I
don’t think Deleuze ever satisfactorily explains
how this actualization arises, even in
difference and repetition, where we ramble
endlessly around individuation, explication,
involution and various other processes that
really just support each other by using
different expressions and metaphors].
INFINITE.There
are three kinds.There is a natural infinite relating to
the necessary eternity of the properties of
being. Secondly,
things which are unlimited because of their
cause as in the immediate infinite mode [see
above]—when we abstract, we make particular
attributes limited and external, and we also
limit duration and existence [so when we
abstract, we are in effect actualizing, about
the only example which is clear,and,maybe, the
hidden anthropomorphic basis for all the
non-human processes?].Thirdly,
the infinite refers to number, to a notion of
minimum and maximum, found in finite existing
modes and relating to their power.However,
modes also possess an infinity of extensive
parts, in the sense that they cannot be numbered
in advance [because in practice, some modes will
possess a higher degree of power than others,
based on their ability to marshal more extensive
parts from the infinity—I think, 79].Again
we can perform the process of abstraction,
assessing matters of existence, [extensive
dimensions], permitting us to measure, count and
so on, proceeding from ‘an arbitrarily
determined number of parts’ (79).
[And some
puzzling gnomic thoughts to end this section:
‘there is no indefinite that is not abstractly
conceived.Every infinite is actual’ (79).I can
grasp this in terms of the multiplicity again.It is
the multiplicity that produces a certain lack of
definition or indefiniteness in actual objects.The
last sentence makes no sense to me.If it
were that every infinite is real, I could see
that that would conform to the usual view that
the virtual is also real.But
does ‘every infinite is actual’ mean that every
multiplicity is capable of actualization?That
every multiplicity always has an actual
dimension?].
INTELLECT
(INFINITE INTELLECT, IDEA OF God).The
intellect is only a mode of the attribute of
thought, and cannot be any guide to what the
essence of God might be, any more than will.It is
anthropomorphic to suggest otherwise, and leaves
people with a difficulty in explaining just how
God is different—more of an intellect, perhaps,
or one that came first?This
involves analogy again, and ‘equivocal language’
(79) [the example refers to the ambiguity of
words with different referents—presumably, the
equivocity in this case arises from using the
same words to refer to the human and the
divine?]
God is not
a legislator with a divine intellect or will.God’s
intellect reflects his essence—he must
understand himself since he produces all forms
including those with which we and he understand.Deleuze
says this also implies that ‘the possible does
not exist, that all that is possible is
necessary’ (79), since God does not operate with
contingencies: he has no need because he must
understand everything that follows from his own
essences, including himself and the things he
does.However,
Spinoza introduces some inconsistency here.[I am
not at all sure I understand these arguments.One is
that there seems to be a problem with thinking
about the infinite intellect as producing
everything, and at the same time, existing as a
modal being—the problem seems to be that there’s
no reason for God/substance to undergo
actualization at all, which I think is a problem
with Deleuze as well.What
produces forms?The only answer we get is that they seem
to arise as an attribute of thought—‘the idea of
God is the idea in its objective being, and the
infinite intellect is the same idea considered
in its formal being’ (80)—in other words, the
virtual and the actual are the same thing, and
it’s no good Spinoza/Deleuze constantly
asserting that they are not].
The same
problem arises if we consider human intellect as
an integral part of the divine intellect/nature
of substance.It has to be both the same and different
[to use the terminology for the problems I’ve
been raising throughout].It has
to be the same because we want to link the two
sorts of intellect, as a guarantee for an
adequate idea.However, when it comes to knowing God,
the idea of adequacy changes, because we can
never know as much as God knows/all the
attributes of substance.We
have to operationalize, but this is the
definition of an inadequate idea [I’m using
almost entirely my own terminology here to
translate a really dense bit on page 81].The
only way we can move above this is by [the
transcendental deduction], trying to
‘objectively comprehend the corresponding
attributes as they are formally’ (81).Deleuze
seems to be arguing that this is the only way to
get the spiritual automaton going—first by
seeing God in inadequate terms, gradually developing
common notions of him, but then having to
consider him ‘according to its own being insofar
as we are a part of it’ (81).[I am
not scholar enough to do this, but I reckon if
you read either Spinoza or Deleuze carefully
enough, you would find the problems of the same
and the different, reconciling the two levels
following the strategies originally identified
by Hindess and Hirst
in Marxism.You either have to be dogmatic or
incoherent.Lots of my specific notes on lumps of
Deleuze certainly suggest both].
KNOWLEDGE
(KINDS OF -).Knowledge is ‘the affirmation of the idea
in the mind’, remembering that is the thing that
reveal something of itself in us.Once
the idea has arisen, knowledge is a matter of
affirming it, developing it or explaining it,
not just registering it in consciousness, or
noting its resulting affects.Knowledge
transforms our whole capacity for being
affected, as we saw.
Spinoza
uses different terms in the discussion of
knowledge, such as indicative signs of various
kinds, and then the common notions and the
subsequent efforts of reason to go beyond them.The
common notions are still generalizations, rather
than ‘knowledge of the singular essence’ (82)
and we only get that when we develop to the
level of essences [and unravel the whole
business of the actual as a manifestation of the
virtual etc].As before, it is the idea of
God/substance that drives the whole thing and
which ‘forces us’ (83) to develop to the third
level, of essences.However,
it is also true that the inadequacies of the
common notions, and maybe their inability to
develop the active search for joy, act as a kind
of cause in their own right.Common
notions are still contaminated with images,
however.
MIND AND
BODY (PARALLELISM).Spinoza
replaces the term ‘soul’ with the term ‘mind’,
to avoid excessive theological prejudice [and so
he explains soul- body relations in the terms of
the discussion of mind – matter relations?].Bodies
exist as modes in extension, minds as modes of
thinking.Minds
have ideas, including an idea of the
corresponding body, and thus of other bodies and
extension itself.This also contributes to the ‘automatism
of thinking…[which is like the automatic]…mechanism
of the body capable of astonishing us’ (86).All
things have bodies and minds, things and ideas,
and it is this that means we can represent
things by ideas.
We start
with ideas about what is happening to our body
and how we feel about it, producing a strong
link between the affects and ideas, as we have
seen.This
link is not a physical one, since bodies are not
the same as minds, but they do correspond,
ultimately because God made sure that things
belong to the same order [by definition?Or is
this just a reassertion that all substances
share the same qualities of substance despite
specific modal differences?I’ve
just realised why Spinoza calls everything a
mode—it is to preserve this notion of shared
substance underneath appearances].Lots
of people have identified this same order of
ideal correspondence, between say passions of
the soul and actions of the body.Leibniz
used the term ‘parallelism’, to weasel round the
idea of whether one causes the other.Spinoza
doesn’t use the term, but it seems to describe
his notion nevertheless.
There is
an identity of order between bodies and minds,
an isomorphism, and also some idea of
connection, ‘an equal valence, and equality of
principle between extension and thought, and
between what occurs in one and in the other’
(88) [we will be bleating about elective
affinities next].The fundamental equality arises because
no attribute is eminent, there is no hierarchy
of attributes, so there can only be one sort of
connection.[The final sort of link arises from the
point about ideas making themselves apparent to
our minds]: when one attribute, say in the body,
is modified, so is the attribute of thought in
the mind.It
follows that ‘action in the body is also action
in the mind, and all that is passion in the mind
is also passion in the body’ (88).
This is an
example of a ‘general epistemological
parallelism’ between ideas and objects.This
is what enables Spinoza to say that we only
properly know an effect once we know its cause.It
also explains how ideas can have causes, even
for God who is his own cause, and how adequate
ideas must always relate to some thing.So
far, we have only seen this general parallelism
being implied in the discussion of attributes
and human knowledge.Spinoza
wants
to go on to demonstrate ‘an ontological
parallelism between [all] modes under all the
attributes’ (88).
This would
involve seeing all modes as forming the same
[form or type of] modification.This
is a different cognitive operation from the ones
we’ve been describing, which see modification
only when essences become extensive.This
produces a number of specific ideas.But
ideas can also be redoubled, since our ideas
take on a formal character of their own in
thought, and can even be the subject of
[metaideas as above].Fully
developed thought, comprehension, sees ideas in
themselves as only one mode of thought.It all
turns in the end on how all these qualities and
operations are unified in God as we saw.[specifically,
I think the ontological argument is that the
original modification or actualization of God
that ended in the production of the world
produced specific attributes, but these still
all emanated from the essence of God].
However at
the epistemological level, it is different:
minds and bodies have equal powers.However
again,
God unites the epistemological and the
ontological, because only he ‘authorises the
transfer of unity from substance to the modes’
(90) [in other words he also creates the equal
powers between minds and bodies?].For
Deleuze, the theme of unity is the important
one, and he reads Spinoza as sometimes confusing
the issue by, for example, suggesting that the
mixtures of bodies controls minds on the one
hand, and suggesting that mind is able to become
autonomous and liberate itself from bodies on
the other. This
is not inconsistent [!], because Spinoza was
referring to different parts of the mind—a
bodily perishable bit and a pure mind
respectively, a part dealing with common
notions, and are part dealing with essences [but
how are these two connected?].The
apparent domination of bodies is also a mistake,
because the idea is to see how bodies work in
order to explore how the mind works.We
explore and discover the powers of both bodies
and minds.So is the apparent escape of the mind
from the body, since Spinoza wants to reject
idealism and argues that even ideas have a
cause, even those that express essences.[This
looks a bit like Deleuzian repair work, and I’m
not sure it is an escape from inconsistency so
much as an assertion first of one element then
the other, or even arguing that both positions
are inconsistent in the first place]
NATURE.Nature
is both substance and mode, both cause and
effect, since it is immanent to each term.Nature
is thus univocal when it comes to attributes
[which also enjoy this dual nature following
from their relation to the virtual].Nature
is both naturing and naturated, and this
produces ‘the univocity of modality’ as well.These
properties of nature explain correspondences
between attributes’; how things are connected in
attributes, including the different kinds of
infinite and finite modes; the agreement of
essences as part of divine power; the ways in
which specific combinations of relations and
powers operate according to eternal laws
nevertheless; the ways in which modes relate to
each other externally according to an extrinsic
order, the ‘”common order of Nature”’ (93),
which involves a determined contingency. [All
this is pretty circular really.We can
start with this definition of nature without
having to ‘discover’ it in the apparently
unmotivated analyses of how modes or essences
relate to each other.The
more specific analyses are merely an obsessional
reworking of this basic argument contained
here?]
NECESSARY.What
exists must be necessary, the result of causes
or through itself.This is another kind of univocity, this
time of one mode of existence.Substances
exist
if their essences require them to; as one of an
infinite number of modes produced by substance,
which possess relevant attributes; insofar as
motion and rest produce existence; when existing
modes produce existence as an effect of their
interrelation [I am not at all sure I have
understood any of this so far].
‘The
categories of possible and contingent are
illusions’ (94), and they are based on qualities
of the essence of the mode, not all of which
exists [Deleuze replaces notions of the possible
and the compossible etc. in the same way, as
seeing them all as aspects of the multiplicity,
not all of which have been actualized].The
notion of the possible also relates to the ways
in which external determinants work [they do not
always produce the same effect or work in the
same way every time].Neither
of these serve to reject the idea of underlying
determinants: ‘contingency and possibility only
express our ignorance’ (94) [Deleuze himself
weasels around the idea of contingency by saying
that it is indeed part of the virtual in the
first place, as in the throws of the dice
metaphor].So nothing is just possible, and nothing
is contingent, ultimately because both imply
something strange about God's intellect and
will, as above.[although I have been trying to read God
as a nature or substance throughout, some of the
argument does seem to turn on God being a person
after all.For example in the sentence above, it
would seem strange to refer to nature's
intellect and will.I know
Spinoza had to refer to theology, as Deleuze’s lectures on Spinoza
indicate, so is he doing this only to tease
theologians?What would the sentence look like if we
made it refer to nature? Could conceal a hidden
anthropomorphism of Nature, as suggested
above?].
NEGATION.Spinoza
wants
to do without the term, seeing it as an
abstraction and fiction.Instead,
he wants to talk about positive distinctions and
negative determinations.
The
argument goes that the attributes are always
distinct and infinite.They
relate, but do not always oppose each other, and
nor does the definition of them imply negation:
each has ‘an independent positive essence' (95).The
positivity takes the form of 'affirmation as
necessary existence', a shared quality rooted in
their participation in substance.When
we try and introduce distinctions, we're really
talking about ‘coessential positivities and
coexistent affirmations'.
Turning to
the finite, we encounter limited determinations.These
are found in the essences of finite modes and in
actual existence.These limits can be seen as negative, but
only in the abstract, abstracting from the
actual characteristics of the mode and its
relations with what causes it.It is
a degree of power which lies at the essence of
the mode, and this is not limited or defined by
negation—the powers in principle add up to form
an infinite set.Empirically, modes can oppose other
modes, and develop more or less degrees of
power, but these characteristics come from the
infinity of parts [the multiplicity] attached to
each mode.So the empirical conflict cannot be seen
as the essence of the mode—it arises from the
essence, but does not constitute the essence
itself, which persists beyond empirical
existence.The essence affirms existence by managing
some of its parts.
When modes
conflict, it is better to see this as a form of
affirmation of whatever powers a mode possesses,
affirmation of a force.Modes
consist of a whole mixture of variable
affirmations and bits of realized essences, 'a
system of multiple positivities' (96): they do
not lack anything in themselves.The
concept of negation is therefore another
inadequate idea, when we group things together
and compare them against some 'fictitious
ideal'.It
is pointless to do this.No
specific nature can be seen as lacking compared
to another nature, since each is 'as perfect as
it can be in terms of what constitutes its
essence' (96), even natures dominated by sadness
[doesn't this contradict what was said earlier
about the formation of proper ideas leading to a
way out of sadness?Maybe
it is that things are as perfect as they can be
at any one specific time, until inadequate ideas
are pushed a bit, forced to develop].It is
pointless to call something lacking a negation,
since something is always lacking.We can
rethink what's lacking by thinking of 'the type
of infinite that corresponds to it' [that is the
multiplicity again].
Spinoza
insists that nothingness is not a part of
nature, is not required by nature, partly
because '"the nature of the thing cannot require
anything unless it exists"' (97).All
the significant characteristics of what other
people have called the negative are dealt with
in Spinoza's discussion of sadness.
PROPRIA.Something
different
from essence and what follows from it in the
form of properties or effects.A
'modality of the essence itself' (104) [a
correctly-grasped one].Apparently
there are three sorts of propria of God:
different modalities of the divine essence, used
to describe attributes like cause and the
eternal; something that qualifies God by
referring to its products as causes of all
things; ‘extrinsic determinations that indicate
the way in which we imagine him, failing to
comprehend his nature, and that serve as rules
of conduct and principles of obedience' (105).
The
propria are the genuine modification of God's
essence, as compared to those produced by human
ignorance and anthropomorphism as above.'This
is theology’s basic error, which is compromise
the whole of philosophy'.At
best, theology only can consider propria in the
form of imagination as above.The
whole approach is based on the flawed eminences
and analogies as above.[Not
really my concern, but how the fuck do we get to
proper propria? We
just assert them dogmatically, or infer them
through transcendental deduction?].
Chapter
five Spinoza’s Evolution (On the Non
completion of the Treatise on the
Intellect).
Spinoza
does offer different relations between God,
nature and substance in his different works.In the
Treatise, God equalled nature, and this
implied that it was not substance but being
which underpinned all substances.The
shift in the Ethics making God equal
substance revalues substance, as demonstrating
an identity [Deleuze calls this ‘pantheism’
(111)].
The Treatise
explicitly saw God as the beginning of
everything, but the Ethics discusses
more of a ‘method of continuous development’
which need not begin with God.However
he gets to God ‘”as quickly as possible”’ [with
a minimum of logical steps].Arriving
at God rather than starting with him tells us
something about Spinoza’s method.It is
all a matter of speed, slowness and haste, ‘the
Ethics is a river that sometimes flows
faster and sometimes slowly’ (112) [see the
essay on Spinoza in Deleuze 1995].
Effects do
follow causes, but this order cannot be followed
immediately, since one usually starts with
knowledge of an effect.All is
well if we deduce causes from effects, but
Spinoza is more interested in synthesis or
genesis, developing ‘a sufficient reason that
also enables us to know other things’ (113).The
former is quicker, the latter more roundabout.The
Treatise began with a given true idea to
get to God as the source of all ideas, but in
the Ethics, we start with substantial
attributes to get to substance which contains
all the attributes, and then back to things.The
Treatise begins with geometric beings as
examples of the true idea, and from there we can
get to God as a genetic element, producing
geometric relations from his own superior power
of thinking.In the Ethics, we have to proceed
through common notions and then finally
synthetic explanations [of essences] and then
God.
Common
notions do not appear in Spinoza’s earlier
works.Common
notions refer to ideas of composition of
relations.We do not get access to essences
immediately, but rather grasp first the
commonalities between things, such as that they
have extension.Common notions have different ranges,
from specific ideas about two bodies to general
ideas about all bodies.These
notions appear as ‘an order of Nature’ (115).Common
notions are seen as fully grounded, not partly
fictional like geometric ideas: they have
physical, chemical or biological components.Now,
geometric concepts can be seen as themselves
grounded on common notions, as abstractions from
them, permitting the play of autonomous reason,
but not starting with abstractions: this is how
geometric concepts now become adequate.
Common
notions are adequate ideas, not just beliefs or
inferences based on abstraction.This
provides a new explanation of how the highest
kind of knowledge emerges [a problem,
apparently, in the Treatise].It is
the very adequacy of common notions [their
empirical applicability] that is the basis for
the development of the second and third levels.Ideas
at the second level are still diverse, resulting
both from reason and from empirical
investigations [such as early biological
analyses of the composition of animals]: a
common interest in real beings is what unifies
ideas here.Ideas at the third level relate to
essences rather than relations between
attributes [whose essences are not investigated
at the second level].
However,
thinking about attributes means ‘one is
necessarily led to knowledge of the essences’
(118).The
notion of adequacy itself leads to the idea of
God, and it is the idea of God that bridges the
second and third levels ‘because it has one side
facing the common notions and one side facing
the essences’ (118) [which apparently follows
because God creates material things but also
shows an ability to invest his divine love in
them -- so it really does depend on
anthropomorphism? Deleuze has to have the
universe itself realizing itself etc].
There is
still a problem with common notions since
immediate experience displays effects but not
relations.However, the affects of sadness and joy
are important—the experience of joy ‘induces us
to form a common notion of these two bodies’
(118-19) [induces philosophers to do so?] Enough
dyadic relations producing joy means
apprehension of a more general level of
commonality [very much like American pragmatism
here -- did Peirce and Dewey read Spinoza?].Common
notions develop from least to most universal,
although it is more common in theoretical
exposition to go the other way, and Spinoza
feels he has to deal with theoretical exposition
first.Exposition
concerns only ideas, but common notions are more
practical and concern the power to generate
affects—through ‘organizing good encounters,
composing actual relations, forming powers,
experimenting’ (119).Apart
from anything else, this grounds in practice the
Ethics.
So why did
Spinoza not finish the Treatise?Deleuze
thinks that it is because Spinoza saw the
potential of the newly conceived common notions.The Treatise
apparently hints at the emergence of the common
notions towards the end.Common
notions were discovered too late to be
incorporated into the Treatise which had
already argued for the importance of geometric
ideas and developed some implications [no doubt
rigorously] , so a rewrite would have been
necessary, and Spinoza preferred to begin again,
instead of writing a new Treatise on the
origin of common notions.
Chapter
six Spinoza and Us
We should
begin in the middle, not with the first
principle of one substance, but progressing to
the other principles about bodies and
individuals, including the idea that nature ‘is
itself an individual varying in an infinite
number of ways’ (122).This
would lead us to see the importance of ‘the
common plane of immanence on which all bodies,
all minds, and all individuals are situated’,
conceived as a diagram [the translator notes
that the French word plan
means both plan {diagram} and plane].We can
relate to Spinoza by installing ourselves on
this plane, and this would help us ‘live in a
Spinozist manner’ (123) [and presumably in a
Deleuzian manner as well, so this is how we
‘apply’ both of them?].If we
do, ‘one finds one is a Spinozist before having
understood why’ [ie bits of it agree with common
sense or flatter our notions of ourselves?]
[A full
translation into Deleuzian terms seems to
ensue].The
body is an infinite number of particles related
by motion and rest, speed and slowness, and
these make it an individual body.Bodies
affect other bodies and are affected, also
producing individuality.It is
not a matter of form or functions—these also
depend on relations of speed and slowness.We
need to see life, including individual life as
‘a complex relation between differential
velocities, between deceleration and
acceleration of particles’ (123), producing a
composition on the plane of immanence [the
example is musical form as a relation between
the speeds of sound particles]. [For
what it’s worth, I think this idea of speed also
accounts for different quantities—lots of things
are gathered together at the same time at higher
speeds, the connections move along quickly etc].
Capacities
for affecting and being affected are more
important than form, ‘organs or functions’, or
definitions based on ‘substance or a subject’.Spinoza
uses the term modes to avoid the last two.The
mode is again a relation of speed and slowness
in bodies and in thoughts, and a capacity for
affecting or being affected.This
changed the definition has important
consequences—and one of them is in understanding
Little Hans [!], who describes horses in terms
of the list of their affects [repeated in Thousand Plateaus].We also know
that the same animal is quite different if it is
a plough horse or a racehorse.Subsequent
biologists have also defined animal worlds in
terms of their capacities for affecting and
being affected, including a certain J von
Uexkűll who are described the tick in terms of
its affects—climb towards the light, smell a
passing mammal, seek out a piece of bare skin
using thermal detection [another example used in
later works].These three aspects define the entire
world of the tick, and this is apparently a
formative piece of work in what became known as
ethology.
On the
plane of immanence, there is no distinction
between the natural and the artificial.Humans
and animals alike can be described by their
affects, because we are not fully in control of
our own capacities at first.We
need to carry on experimentation and develop
wisdom, and this itself ‘implies the
construction of a plane of immanence or
consistency’ (125) [this ambiguity has struck me
before—is the plane of immanence a human or
philosophical construct imposed on the chaos of
the universe?In the sentence above, it looks as if it
somehow emerges from chaos by itself].
Spinoza’s
ethics are based on this ethology, not on a
morality.The
implication is that we only know what we can do
in particular encounters and arrangements.Ethology
looks at relations of speed and slowness,
capacities for affecting and being affected.We can
discuss for each thing the amplitude of these
capacities, the thresholds, ‘variations or
transformations that are peculiar to them’.Ethologists
also study how things select what affects them,
how animals react to the world, how [symbiotic]
relations between animals arise [no sign yet of
the wasp and orchid example].We
cannot separate individual animals from
relations with the world because ‘The interior
is only a selected exterior, and the exterior, a
projected interior’ [makes a lot more sense
after reading Deleuze on
Foucault, especially the bit on the fold].
Relations
of speed and slowness can be affected by
circumstances as they are realized—for example,
the same relations can sometimes increase and
sometimes decrease capacities to be affected
[food can also be poisonous—really?]. Ethology
can also study constructive compounding of
bodies to produce either new extensive
relations, or more intensive capacities or
power.This
helps ethology study not just [individual]
‘utilisations or captures, but…sociabilities
and communities’ (126).[So we
have a kind of all purpose philosophical
anthropology replacing sociology?Again
it is interesting to see that JS Mill used the
term ethology in his own methodological
individualism].This can lead us to ask about the
different types of sociability, including ‘the
difference between the society of human beings
and the community of rational beings’.However,
overall, we should concern ourselves with the
whole of nature, the composition of a whole
world, and how its ‘powers, speeds and
slownesses compose features of it. In this way,
Nature ‘is the fullest and most intense
Individual’, with infinite parts.Old
Uexkűll developed analysis beginning with
individual things and then moving towards some
‘immanent higher unity’, and he also saw this in
terms of the musical analogy, in the form of the
symphony.
We can
reread the Ethics as entirely about
‘changing relative velocities until the absolute
velocity of thought is reached in the third kind
of knowledge’ (127).There
is a major difference between the propositions
and the scholia and the speed at which they
progress and combine, again like a musical
composition.
Spinoza
also can be understood as describing substance
in terms of its longitude and latitude, terms
from the Middle Ages as well as from geography. [Introduced
without comment in Thousand Plateaus
-- as is the stuff on speeds etc] Longitude
of the body refers to the relations of speed and
slowness, motion and rest between the particles
that compose it [which are themselves seen as
‘unformed elements’, something infinitely small,
lacking form unlike composite bodies].Latitude
refers to sets of affects, the intensive states
of the anonymous force for existing or being
affected etc.These affects occupy bodies at each
moment.Together
this helps construct the map of the body.Together
they constitute nature and the plane of
imminence or consistency.Here,
this plane is ‘always variable and is constantly
being altered, composed and recomposed,
by individuals and collectivities’ (128) [which
implies that any active body, not just
philosophers, can produce a plane of immanence].
Plan(e)s
themselves vary.They can be theological planes if they
operate with a transcendental hierarchy, and
this includes hierarchical concepts of nature or
societies.Such a plan can be structural, genetic,
or both at the same time.The
plan produces forms and subjects, so it is a
‘plan of organization or development’.Any
plan that produces forms and subjects and that
stays hidden itself must be a transcendental one
‘that can only be divined, induced, inferred
from what it gives’ (128).By
contrast, a plane of imminence does not have a
supplementary level, and is a plane of
composition rather than organization.There
are no forms, only relations of velocity between
particles.There are no subjects, but only
‘individuating affective states of an anonymous
force’ (128).The plan covers only motion and rest and
dynamic aspects.We perceive it only with ‘that which
makes it perceptible’.A true
Spinozist resists any attempt to subordinate
this plane to a transcendental one.
Artists
can find that they are Spinozists, which is even
more likely than philosophers discovering that
they are.Spinoza
has this quality or ‘privilege’ that his
elaborate conceptual apparatus can nevertheless
be grasped by ‘a non philosopher, or even
someone without any formal education [who] can
receive a sudden elimination from him, a“flash”’
(129).[And
then, as an apparently supporting example,
Deleuze cites Nietzsche who suddenly discovered
Spinoza to his surprise: apparently, Nietzsche
'is not speaking only as a philosopher’.A
certain Delbos, a historian of philosophy, and
so entirely normal, also was struck by Spinoza.However,
there is the example of a poor Jew who bought
Spinoza’s book and found it gripping, according
to Malamud].It is because you can read Spinoza either
systematically as a philosopher, or experience
him through an ‘an affective reading, without
any idea of the whole, where one is carried
along or set down, put in motion or rest, shaken
or calmed according to the velocity of this or
that part’.Such readers can also see themselves as
Spinozan.
Spinoza
also teaches philosophers how to become a non
philosopher, especially in Part V apparently,
where a concept and affect co-occur.Lots
of people develop a passion for Spinoza, they
love him, they talk of the effect of reading him
as encountering a wind, a calm wind and a
whirlwind together, the cold logic of the
sections, and the more passionate bits of the
scholia.Spinoza’s
Part V offers the maximum connection between
concepts and life, but it is the interweaving in
the earlier sections that also makes it very
attractive.