Notes on : Denzin, N. (1969).
Symbolic Interactionism and Ethnomethodology: A
Proposed Synthesis. American Sociological
Review, 34(6), 922-934.
Dave Harris
There are similarities — problems of social
organisation, methodology, socialisation,
deviants, social control, face-to-face
interaction, and the analysis of science as a
social enterprise, basically 'how individuals are
shaped by and in turn create elements of social
structure' (922), with an emphasis on the
subjective side of social life. These two
perspectives may not be irreconcilable.
Investigation of both social psychological and
sociological problems is required, but approaches
have not always been successful. S I and ethno
both focus on the individual and subjective
aspects. Garfinkel and Cicourel analyse taken for
granted expectations by any member of a social
order. Scientific is distinguished from everyday
activity. Documentary analysis is the preferred
strategy. The concern is with how everyday taken
for granted meanings are linked with routine
patterns of interaction. SI focuses on individual
conduct and forms of social organisation, seeing
how selves 'emerge out of social structure and
social situations. Both suggest a link between
persons and social structure with an important
role for symbols and common meanings. There are
links with structural functionalism, although the
unit of analysis is the individual and
interaction.
Human beings are seen as capable of analysing
their own thoughts and activities thus being able
to manipulate symbols and orient their actions
towards others, often in a routine way, so that
conduct becomes a matter of 'custom, tradition,
and ritual'(923). Self-consciousness means that
some behaviours are also 'actively constructed in
a self-conscious and interpretative fashion'. The
empirical problem becomes identifying these
different modes of interpretation. There are no
perfect differences between interpretative and
non-interpretative elements. No objects in our
environment carry intrinsic meaning. All social
objects are constructs [citing Blumer]. Objects
can be anything that can be designated 'in a
unitary fashion and around which one can organise
action' so the meaning of an object lies in the
definitions brought to it, not in itself.
'Meanings typically derive from a group or
organised interactional perspective. Human life is
group life'. Joint action involves the ability of
one human to grasp the direction of the acts of
others. Consensual action implies a common
community of symbols, but there is always a
possibility of negotiation and change with
'certain objects'at least. Selves can produce
multiple interpretations and this is what gives
'group life its changing character'. Consensus
produces stable patterns of action which implies
'a series of social selves', but humans can
undertake 'self – lodging' merging their own
identity into those of 'relevant others'. Thus
Cooley argues that 'the other exists in "our
imaginations of him"' [could be Lacan!]. This
produces social bonding and reciprocal relations.
Lodging self is not the same as presenting one —
'at some point in the cycle of recurrent
interactions, the self moves from the
presentational to the lodging phase' [very
different indeed from Denzin's later work]. There
are variations on the looking glass self which
involves 'presentation, identification and
subjective interpretation', guided by pleasure or
displeasure based on interpretations of the
reactions of others, a process of continual
evaluation, not an object, especially not 'a
calculated and planned object'. We are attracted
to those areas where basic features of ourselves
have been lodged, and this is 'the basis of
motivation'and of patterns of identification.
Motivation becomes 'an interactional process'
(924) which in turn becomes grounded and
ritualised, taking on the form of 'the firm rules
of tradition and custom'.
Thus human interaction is not just rational or
cognitively developed, but also depends on 'the
affective bond between the self and its relevant
others'. Empirical 'indicators of self lodging'
include personal names, modes of dress or special
body movements. Naming, for example shows various
levels of intimacy, as does personal variations on
speech dress: these are seen as 'an attempt to
lodge certain portions of the self in the
interaction'. Involvement in conversation in terms
of time or topic is another indicator. Frequency
of utterances can be used to chart involvement.
Interactions can be judged in terms of success at
self lodging, and recognition of the attempt.
'Joint actions cannot be resolved solely into
individual lines of action'. Observed behaviour
emerges in interaction as individual lines of
action are fitted together. Such fitting includes
taking into account definitions and
interpretations of others. Plans of action may be
disparate, conflicting or incomplete, so
'interaction may have a variable career',
contingent on emerging events, such as the birth
of a child. Any rules of conduct might be too
vague to prevent conflicting points of view. New
points of view in new lines of action, changing
creative activity can emerge when old perspectives
have 'failed to provide answers' to maintain
'basic forms of thinking and acting common to that
world' [classic functionalist notion of moral
density?]. Mead was able to use this insight to
suggest that social scientists uniquely focused on
these challenges — in the dialectical process of
confrontation, analysis and resynthesis of
perspectives' (925). This anticipated later work
on the positive functions of conflict and
reintroduced conflict and challenge as an
important stage in the formation of group
perspectives. For Denzin, interaction actually
takes place as a result of a combination of rules
— civil legal codes; rules of etiquette like those
studied by Goffman; rules which 'display the
distinctive nature of enduring social
relationships', sometimes derived from the above
codes, but sometimes addressing new situations
[among them 'white-collar theft']. Sometimes mild
deviance from formal rules indicate 'reciprocal
lodging' as people relax. Any interaction will
display all three categories of rules and will
study how people actively construct their own
meanings within these standards of conduct.
Different collectivities will not always agree on
these relational rules. [No preference at this
stage for subversive or challenging resistance
etc]
Interactionism basically 'endeavours to
relate covert symbolic behaviour with overt
patterns of interaction', involving an interest in
unfolding meaning during interaction. The usual
strategy is to start with overt behaviours and
then work back to meanings attached to them.
Behavioural analysis is not sufficient, nor is
just an analysis of meanings or definitions
without looking at application in interaction.
There is a need to identify different phases of
interpretation as the reaction of others become
important, and as agreement replaces negotiation.
It is the self that becomes the object, meaning
that behaviour is to be studied from the
perspective of those being studied. This includes
occasions of ritual encounter 'where the basic
activity lies above the self, or in the
interaction process' such as social gains, routine
work, participation in religious ceremony. By
studying selves, we can soon see what is taken for
granted and what is problematic, and this helps us
'escaped the fallacy of objectivism' (926) where
the scientist perspective substitutes for the
perspective of those actually involved. We take
'the role of the acting other'. This involves us
also linking symbols and meanings to social
circles and relationships, 'Unless meanings are
linked to larger social perspectives, analysis
remains largely psychological'. We also have to
consider the '"situated aspects" of human
conduct', where social situations and their
meaning can influence subsequent behaviour. There
may be components like whether the interact as
part objects, the concrete setting, the meanings
brought into the situation and the time taken for
the interaction. Variations in behaviour can be
produced by different definitions of others and
objects '(e.g. furniture, lighting)'. 'The
situation as an intrusive variable cannot be
ignored' — new people, the failure of mechanical
equipment, shifts in levels of involvement can all
affect interaction. Both stability and change must
be studied, however, observations also become
'subject to personal bias and even ideological
preference': concepts are sensitising, only
operationalised once situated meanings have been
discovered. Standard methods of observation and
other methods can be used, in the process of
triangulation, since 'each method has
restrictions, and if several different methods are
combined in the same study, the restrictions of
wine are often the strength of another' [naive,
and eventually replaced by his idea of the
triangle as a diverging crystal]. We also need 'a
series of common databases; reliable sampling
model… A series of empirical indicators for each
database; a series of hypotheses; and a continual
reciprocation between data and hypotheses'. Theory
is still the common goal, and 'propositions with
the greatest universal relevance are sought those
', assuming universal interactional processes. We
should end with 'soundly grounded empirical
propositions of an all-inclusive universal
nature', although interactionism has not yet
achieved this goal and is a perspective rather
than theory.
Ethnomethodologists ask how social order is
possible and for Garfinkel there is both a concern
for large collective representations as in
Durkheim with an interactionist conception of
rules norms and meanings (927). Such rules include
an assumption that interaction flows in the
temporal sequence, that many topics will only be
tacitly recognised, that background and conditions
are taken for granted, that definitions hold for
the duration of the encounter, that 'any object
present in the situation is what it is presented
as being', that meanings on one occasion will hold
for future occasions, that standard terms, symbols
and labels are used to attach meaning, that
discrepancies with personal biography and
experience are held in abeyance for the duration
leading to 'conflict between their public and
private definitions'. These rules have to be
uncovered by penetrating normal situations,
sometimes by disrupting normal social events, in
Garfinkel's case through 'quasiexperimental field
studies' which appear naturalistic and which
challenge existing definitions: students pretend
to be boarders in their own home, or pay different
amounts for objects purchased, or to violate the
usual rules of a simple game. It becomes difficult
to challenge these routine rules and sometimes
engenders 'distrust, hostility, anger,
frustration, and persecution', partially resolved
by adopting an experimenter attitude. Garfinkel
says that the notion of trust has been infringed,
an assumption that everyone shares the same
expectations and definitions and everyone agrees
to work by them. Without such trust, joint action
becomes more difficult. Ethnomethodologists have
also studied routine production of persons in
social organisations, mental clinics, hospitals,
courts, suicide prevention centres and so on. This
is to study the special perspectives that members
have to deal with comments. So far, studies have
suggested that organisations even 'perpetuate
themselves through time by generating fictitious
records' (928); that comparable organisations
assign different meanings to the same events; that
the production of organisational records is
basically an interactional process and includes
many subjective elements [Cicourel]; it is common
for members to rely 'on open-ended categories to
classify cases' — this is the '"et cetera clause"'
where events are fitted into a pattern to confirm
ongoing action.
We can see these studies as a contribution to
labelling as in Becker, and ethnomethodologists
clearly share interactionist's concerns with the
social organisation dimensions of deviance. There
is another possible convergence where
interactionists study the informal structure of
organisations, including a moral hierarchy [citing
Hughes or Strauss], although interactionists tend
to place more emphasis on the formal structure as
a factor. Ethnomethodologists suggests that
sociologists are concerned with depicting taken
for granted affairs of actors, which involves
necessary decisions about the relation between
sociological concept and observations. Invariably,
'unclassifiable instances appear' to stretch
coding schemes or statistical tests, and when
sociologist decide whether or not an observation
fits that category, they make use of the
documentary method of analysis, perhaps
unconsciously. So every classification rests on
'assumptions of daily interaction' — some
statements are placed in the temporal sequence,
some ignored, some common vocabulary is assumed,
interactions take place between researchers and
actors. The latter is often seen as a good thing
when rap or is established, but 'this hypothesis
is problematic' and disguises the necessary
collaboration by the subject as well as the
sociologist — we need to look at 'the routine
meanings held by subjects' as well (929).
The assumptions taken from Schutz are important,
including the idea of 'an impenetrable barrier
between the scientific and the everyday
conceptions of reality', and the denial that
scientists can ever accurately enter the world of
everyday man. The solution is to construct ideal
types as rational constructs. Both Garfinkel and
Cicourel have constructed models of everyday life
based on 'a social game perspective' to grasp the
rationality of analysing everyday action.
We need to look at the criticisms of both
interactionism and ethno. Theoretically, there are
problems with the dramaturgical view, for example,
because that overemphasises the project to 'win
support for a presented self'. Other conceptions
of the self are too vague to ground any empirical
observations, and interactionist themselves seem
to disagree about the causal status of the self as
concept. Generally too few concrete hypotheses
have been produced [denied by Hammersley of
course]. Interactionism might fail to adequately
grasp the larger forms of social organisation,
although the sociology of work and organisational
settings associated with Hughes might be cited in
defence, and collective behaviour can help us
grasp 'mass society' [citing among others Blumer
1957 — I don't know it]. Ethno and its
'phenomenological bias'also presents problems for
looking at individuals in larger social units. Its
demonstration of how taken for granted assumptions
actually operate is unclear, and so is its
discussion of the documentary method.
Both perspectives failed to 'clearly indicate the
source of meanings and definitions' for Denzin
[those in politics?]. They offer no way to measure
the interaction process. They do offer a way to
grasp 'the complex role of interaction in shaping
activity'. There are some experimental strategies
in Garfinkel, and there are contributions to the
sociology of knowledge, as with Garfinkel's
analysis of scientific rationalities.
Ethnomethodologists's argument that sociological
methods are produced in the same way as the
meanings of everyday life 'echoes the concern of
Mead and others' on the differences between
science and everyday activities.
The proposed synthesis is possible on
the convergence between the two in terms of the
'meanings given to social objects'(930). Take the
'movement of objects from interpretative to
non-interpretative rules'. We can suggest that any
event challenging normal interpretation will bring
that event into the flow of interaction, perhaps
after an initial frustration or groping for
meaning. There can be a quick resolution for less
important objects, such as when mechanical
equipment breaks down at a meeting. However
fundamental objects will require further
negotiation by being accorded 'explicit
interpretative status'. These are as important to
study as taken for granted elements. There is no
way to classify objects into these two categories
a priori. The self may be the most significant
object for interpretation, but we need to add
'meanings brought into the situation and perhaps
the situation as well', even though concrete
situations are 'likely to contain the greatest
proportion of non-problematic objects'. Meaning
can be treated as 'an element of the covert
symbolic act' studied by self-reports and
expectations: these might include assumptions
about who was going to be present how long it
would take, the types of cells to be presented,
the degree of knowledge and the types of objects.
As interaction develops, overt activities can be
linked in to shifts in meaning to study
constructions. The extent of interaction can be
'measured by the frequency of joined actions'.
Emergent effects can be 'represented by the
frequency of disrupted plans of action' and
emergent qualities can be studied in terms of the
extent to which they involve explicit
interpretation.
Thinking of deviance and labelling, we can
redefine Garfinkel on trust. If actors assume the
other will abide by decisions mutually agreed on,
then 'violations of trust become violations of
those agreements'. Examples might include not keeping
secrets or pretending to interact consensually. We
might see the betrayal of trust especially clearly
with relations between normals and the mentally
ill. We could suggest that continued violations of
trust creates strains which in turn 'culminate in
attributions of deviants directed towards the
trust violator', but this will happen only with
certain breakdowns, where more violations of the
codes occurred. At the organisational level,
members in social control agencies might have to
work to validate a deviant label, and again the
'degree of trust violation' (931) will be
important, although there is an additional
requirement to meet 'collective organisational
needs'. We will find more labelling where these
needs converge with attributions of deviants —
sometimes organisational needs will even dominate,
and sometimes labelling will take place without an
organisational backing — labelling can become 'a
political and ideological issue with members of
the social control agencies responding more to
political demands'.
There may be conflicting definitions of the
relevant objects in the environment, including
objects that are taken for granted by some
participants but the subject of interaction by
others. A sense of dissatisfaction with
interactional partners can produce 'reciprocal
alienation' and then 'deviance attribution'. We
need to study the language of interaction, both
'silent' and 'vocal'. The first turns on things
like gestures and bodily controls and often
reflect background expectations. The second
concerns matters such as 'proper address, naming,
tone of voice, and choice of vocabulary' we can
take these as an expression of 'the salient
features of the silent dialogue' [citing Goffman
on behaviour in public places]. interaction
involves both languages. We need to see how rules,
including implicit ones are taught in
socialisation, and how silent languages can be
sanctioned. Both perspectives suggest that
'socialisation is never ending… an [sic]
ubiquitous feature of all interactions'. The
success of socialisation can be measured by 'the
ability of persons to fit lines of action
together' (932).
Together, both perspectives would help us do
organisational analysis. Organisations depend on
'complex spoken and unspoken languages'
representing their concerns and prescriptions for
action, even where these run counter to formal
goals. Each role position might have a special
language requiring special socialisation
strategies to be tested and reaffirmed within
special social orders. These might compete. We
need to break organisations down into
interactional units of this special kind rather
than think of one organisation. An organisation
needs to be held together 'if at all' by a few
salient symbols [the examples of both universities
and mental hospitals] — and the name of the
organisation might be the only one agreed.
We can also use both to understand scientific
conduct including the development of sociological
methodology. Scientists especially are
'self-consciously interpretative' and this
produces developments in science. Mead partially
anticipated Kuhn on paradigms. Mead and Garfinkel
examine scientific rationality and contrasted it
to Merton and Parsons. Scientific conduct is
'imbued with elements from everyday life' although
this can lead to unfavourable judgement, hence
Merton's 'four norms of universalism, communism,
disinterestedness and organised scepticism',
although other professional organisations also
share these. We can now have a better discussion
of the 'value free problem'. Science does not
avoid values. Scientific norms of rationality,
such as official neutrality towards meaning, the
disinterest in the real world, and indifference to
chronological time, perfect communication,
standards of publicity can never be realised
fully. Nor can they be in modern sociology.
Garfinkel suggests that pursuing these norms leads
further away from 'the world of social events…
Concrete behavioural analyses of face-to-face
interaction'. Sociologists typically overlook
irrational elements in their own conduct when they
make observations code documents or conduct
interviews. But these can never be ignored, and
interactionism and ethno can even suggest
corrective action. Thus we need multiple observers
and multiple methods to overcome individual
'restrictive biases', and this implies that
triangulation produces more reliable and valid
data. The scientists own unique interpretations
must be moderated [but we are not told how
different interpretations are reconciled].
Interactions between observers and subjects can
affect the data, for example in emergent
interaction. Some may be taken for granted. The
researcher needs to record interactions carefully
'with a special eye to events they judge to be
unique' (933). there might be additional
implications [Denzin calls them hypotheses].
Finally, both use documentary method and this can
be linked with analytic induction sensitising
concepts role taking and 'the strategies of
linking individual perspectives with the larger
social units'. Garfinkel's quasi-experiments could
become a model for more rigourous studies,
especially if we acknowledge experimenter effects
and subject perceptions.
back to social theory
|
|