Notes on: Atkinson, P and Hammersley, M.
Ethnography and Participant Observation. In
N. Denzin, and Y Lincoln, (eds)
(1994). Handbook of Qualitative Research
[1st edition]. PP 248 – 61.
Sage Publications: London
Dave Harris
We can pick out certain complementary themes to
distinguish the various approaches. Some people
see ethnography as a philosophical paradigm,
others as a method. Usually, it involves exploring
social phenomena rather than testing hypotheses
about them; a preference for unstructured data
rather than closed categories; a small number of
cases, sometimes only one; analysis that involves
'explicit interpretation of the meanings and
functions of human actions', mostly verbal rather
than statistical or quantified.
Participant observation also means different
things, participant observation might involve a
researcher playing 'an established participant
role' (248), but nonparticipating observers can
play roles as well. Options can range from
complete observer through to complete participant,
but even there it depends whether the researcher
is known to be a researcher, how much people know
about the research, what sort of activities are
engaged in, whether the orientation of the
researcher is that of an insider or outsider,
consciously or not. To some extent, all social
researcher is participant observation, so it is
not a distinct method.
The usual claim is to offer 'a uniquely
humanistic, interpretive approach', often in
opposition to scientific or positivist approaches,
although some ethnographers espouse scientific
stances. Political commitments also vary. Strands
connect to form particular schools of ethnography,
and there are connections with various different
theoretical movements. We have 'a constant process
of oppositions, of successive heterodoxies and
heresies' (249), and different positions adopted
towards a supposed mainstream. The particular
focus of the disputes can change, however, from
methodological ones to more epistemological. The
'posts-' have provided new interest.
The founding fathers included Malinowski and his
fieldwork, although there may be older roots in
German philosophy. It has been shaped by an
interest in non-Western societies. It has been
effected by historicism, and 19th-century
hermeneutics. People of the past were different,
and should be understood and not prematurely
judged. This was then applied to societies
contemporaneous with the West, and, in the 20th
century, to the study of 'one's own social
surroundings too' (250), both the discovery of
pockets of traditional culture, and the discovery
of diverse cultures in metropolitan centres.
Institutionalisation of the social sciences in
universities is also important, with its history
of regular crises and long-standing disputes, for
example between empiricist natural science and
hermeneutics. This is often seen as a tradition of
conflict between paradigms, but this is
'misleading' — there is more a diversity of ideas,
as we see by looking at actual founders.
For example, Boas, Malinowski and Radcliffe Brown
saw anthropology as a science with a central part
played by ethnography. Information must be
collected first-hand, and speculation rejected.
All admired the natural sciences, but believed
that social phenomena were different: the tension
between science and humanities was 'present from
the start'. We see that too with Chicago sociology
— disputes about methods, case study or
statistical, were seen as disputes within
interpretations of science. Kant and idiography
was 'blended with a nomothetic interest in
the discovery of sociocultural laws' (251).
Pragmatist philosophy tried to combine scientific
orientations with German idealism and historicism,
especially in Hegel. The tensions with notions of
natural sciences persist, and there is now even
more diversification and varieties of practice.
The question of scientific status 'cannot usefully
be answered simply'(251) — different sorts of
social science might be taken as paradigmatic;
there can be interpretations about the methods
used by science; they can be disagreements about
which bits of scientific method might be applied.
Much of the debate has been taken up by a
rejection of positivism, [usually as scientism],
involving rigorous testing of hypotheses by
quantitative data. The criticism is that the 'true
nature of human social behaviour' has been missed,
because artificial settings or experiments affect
the outcome, or people can say one thing and might
do another, because meanings are reduced to what
is observable, static, and because mechanical
causality is deployed. Nevertheless, quantitative
data can still be used in ethnography, although
not exclusively.
However, there is now a more radical rejection of
both science and quantification [and Lincoln is
one of those so mentioned], reflecting a general
disillusionment with natural science, seeing it as
an oppressive force, as in the writings of various
critical theorists and feminists. The objectivity
of social researchers been questioned, for example
as reflecting masculinist assumptions which affect
the whole enterprise, as in early Marxist
formulations of ideology. Similar criticisms are
found 'among advocates of black
sociology'[Hammersley cites his own
contributions]. A more fundamental question has
emerged, whether social scientific knowledge of
human activity is even possible. Accounts are
constructions reflecting particular circumstances,
and there is no universally valid knowledge.
Ethnography describes this social reality best,
especially after discovering various posts [and
Denzin is singled out — the article on
post-modernism — and so is Lather].
Denzin and Richardson
have criticised Whyte's classic . The accuracy of
Whyte's account has been questioned, after more
interviews although his original account has been
defended by an actual participant. Denzin and
Richardson argue that 'all accounts are
constructions' so the whole debate about which one
is the more accurate in depicting reality 'is
meaningless' (252). Ethnography itself can be
subject to the same sort of criticisms directed at
quantitative research — it also reified social
phenomena, and claims 'illegitimate expertise over
the people studied, as being based on
relationships of hierarchy control'. It might even
be a more subtle form of control, apparently
related more closely to people. This
epistemological challenge 'is undoubtedly fruitful
in many respects', especially in demonstrating
common problems between ethnography and
quantification. In ethnography, theories are
particularly ill-defined. However, scepticism and
relativism has also emerged and 'it is not always
clear how thoroughgoing' it is: it is often
applied selectively, but without clear principles.
Embracing scepticism fully is likely to lead to
'debilitating nihilism'. We need to reject some
binaries, especially between 'a single oppressive
conception of science and some uniquely liberating
alternative'.
In the past, ethnography claim to be directed
mostly towards developing disciplinary knowledge
rather than solving practical problems,
contributing knowledge of general relevance and
value, with a diffuse impact. Usually this
involved 'marked deviation from the sort of
research, or even the sort of written
presentation, appropriate to academic work',
following the general 'enlightenment model' (253).
However, there has been an applied anthropology
movement, especially in the USA, trying to do
research aimed at the solution of practical
problems, and criticising the disciplinary model.
Sometimes anthropologists and others have engaged
in advocacy, but whether this should be integrated
into the research process is less clear: of course
any attempt to represent others involves 'ethical
and political responsibilities'. But there are
complications because the context of advocacy is
complex if a number of individuals and groups are
involved, or if the group to be supported is not
internally homogenous — they are also 'rarely
democratically organised', so it is not certain
what is in the interests of the group. There is
the danger of adopting 'ethnographic myths, such
as that Indian groups represent "islands of
culture"… or that informants speak "cultural
truths"'.
There has been an application of ethnography in
applied fields, as confidence in quantitative data
declines. Ironically, this has developed more in
commercial market research than government funded
work, but in the US even federally funded
evaluations have involved ethnographic component.
This might not be properly ethnographic, and
controversy focuses on things like condensed
fieldwork [citing the criticism of casework by
Atkinson and Delmont].
There has been more collaborative research,
sometimes involving practitioners as partners,
designed to make research more relevant and
practitioners more reflexive. Again Marxist
critical theory and feminism have encouraged these
trends as an extension of democracy, the
exemplification of commitment, an attack on
traditional hierarchies. However, there is no
reason to think that 'a single conception'(254) of
the relationship between researcher and
practitioners should dominate, especially if we
still want to produce knowledge as well as pursue
practical goals — these are 'no more worthy in
general terms of our time and effort than the
pursuit of knowledge'. We should not pursue
unachievable goals. Academic research might have
valuable long-term effects. 'Utopian attempts to
do politics by means of research are of no service
to anyone' [no wonder Denzin is upset by this].
The rhetoric of ethnographic accounts has been
receiving more attention, especially the
connections with rhetoric representation and
logic. This is more general in the human
disciplines, and enhanced by the emergence of the
posts. Ethnography has been examined as a
textual genre with characteristic argumentation.
There is no natural or neutral way to present the
natural world, and impersonal forms are
conventional. Authenticity and credibility 'is
dependent on readers' adopting shared strategies
of reading and interpretation'. There are various
conventional devices to guide portrayals of social
scenes or people, and early work has been
influential in establishing formats. As a result,
current formats still display, for example,
'direct, if implicit embodiment of the domain
assumptions of functionalist anthropology'.
Clifford and Marcus marked the major form of
departure by focusing on textual impositions and
the production of ethnographies. Geertz also
argued that anthropology could be seen as fiction
because they are crafted by their authors and
shaped by literary conventions, and he went on to
demonstrate the characteristic styles on show.
Others have identified parallels between
ethnography and travel writing (255). Atkinson has
used literary criticism to show how realism and
authenticity is a matter of drawing upon
particular conventions. The same can be said of
earlier sociological traditions in the USA and the
UK ['Booth and Rowntree have major affinities with
several literary models'], and there are community
studies. The aim is to remove 'the false
distinction between "science" and "rhetoric"' to
return to the dichotomy between humanism and
science.
Whole schools of thoughts can be understood as
combining various textual devices to construct
their scholarly accounts, and there might be
subtypes according to different regions and
preoccupations. Van Maanen has contrasted realist
and confessional accounts, part of a more general
problem of managing the personal and the
impersonal. These conventions were not always
apparent in earlier work, because authors and
readers used devices that seemed familiar and
natural, partly explaining the success of classics
such as Whyte's. [No Clough on familiar narrative
devices?]. Atkinson has shown how 'narrative forms
are used to convey accounts of social action and
causation' or how characters or actors are
solidified from various fragments. He also looks
at various figures of speech 'such as metaphor,
irony, and synecdoche' (256). This does not
invalidate ethnography, but it should make us
aware that we cannot use techniques innocently:
there is no necessary reason to find alternative
literary forms, although some anthropologists have
done so [looks like a useful set of references
page 256].
For some, these discoveries raise ethical and
political implications, since it is both the
author and the other who is being textually
represented. More general cultural criticism such
as Said or Spivak can be deployed. A paradox
results — the ethnographer is committed to their
hosts, and a shared social world, ostensibly based
on surrendering to the other and establishing
reciprocity of perspectives. This egalitarian
rhetoric based on a shared humanity goes along
with 'a radical distinction between Author and
Other', and a realist technique that endows the
narrator with a privileged gaze and privileged
voice organising the actors. Moves towards more
dialogic or multiple voiced forms have ensued.
Feminists have echoed these concerns by describing
privileged Western masculine observers. They have
experimented with styles to subvert these formats
— Kristeva using a '"stream of consciousness"
style. There is a general feminist interest in
treating textual forms as problematic, and a
feminist standpoint that links together
'epistemological and ethical, personal and
professional' concerns.
There is also a post-modern tendency to explore
'discontinuities, paradoxes and inconsistencies',
a more fragmentary representation of social life,
not brought under a single point of view.
Participant observation gives way to dialogue.
There are also radical textual alternatives, based
on evoking rather than representing the social
world [lots of lovely references, including one to
Dorst who apparently shows how a particular suburb
creates itself 'through various forms of
representation and acts of identification (not
least identification with and through the
paintings of Andrew Wyeth)' (257). Rose has an
even more extreme version, juxtaposing different
collections of materials and styles of writing.
Realist ethnography remains, but there will be
more experiments with textual styles and formats.
At least this will focus attention on the
conventional character of most ethnographic work.
Different forms will be self-consciously
recognised and explored as 'part of the craft
knowledge of ethnographic authors' (257).
The recent emphasis on the poetics of ethnography
raises the 'danger of undue attention to these
literary and aesthetic issues. Problems of logic
and inference have been obscured'. The rhetorical
has been privileged over the scientific or
rational. We should really be paying attention to
strategies of reading and writing 'primarily in
order to evaluate the quality of arguments and the
use of evidence', even if much of it is implicit.
Textual elements should be critically addressed in
order to 'evaluate the quality of the arguments'.
So, there is no simple rationale or definition, no
consensus. It's doubtful even if we can identify
'different types of "qualitative research."' There
are different positions based on theory and
epistemology, some common threads, but a lot of
attempts to 'define their activities in terms of
what they are not — in opposition to less
preferred perspectives — rather than in a positive
way'. There are generalisations and assumptions —
that Chicago's sociology was dominated by
ethnographic fieldwork, similar to recent
approaches, and predicated on symbolic
interactionism, itself 'largely a subsequent
codification of presuppositions'. The same goes
with debates about ethnomethodology, whether it is
uniquely fundamental, or another perspective,
again, there are restricted views of what counts
as the field, too much reliance on spoken
interaction, which limits the material. The same
can be said about discourse analysis: neither
substitutes for ethnographic enquiry. The textual
metaphor is important, for example in Geertz's
thick description, and here it does help reduce
reductionism. However, there is still a paradox
between relativism and claims that ethnographers
can interpret cultures, despite increased
attention to the poetics, metaphors and tropes of
cultures themselves. There is no 'one-to-one
relationship' between ethnography and any
theoretical perspective, no single epistemological
orthodoxies, rather a set of different appeals to
different disciplines and tendencies.
[The notes and references are excellent].
back to Hammersley page
|
|