Notes on: Hammersley, M and
Traianou A (2014) An Alternative Ethics? Justic
and Care as Guiding Principles for Qualitative
Research. Sociological Research Online
19(3) DOI: 10.5153/sro.3466 [Electronic
text -- no page numbers but para numbers]
Dave Harris
Social research used to be dominated by an ethics
based on 'deontological and consequentialist
principles', but now there is an approach based on
an ethics of participation, equal relations
between researcher and researched, based on
notions of 'justice and care'
Lincoln is among those who has proposed research
that '"enables and promotes social justice,
community, diversity, civic discourse and
caring"', while others like Mertens say that
research should contribute to social justice and
human rights. There is a strong contrast made to
the '"deception-based, utilitarian IRB
{Institutional Review Board} system"' (1.1)
We can turn to the account by Denzin and Giardina
[the 2007 book Ethical Futures in Qualitative
Research…] as definitive [hereinafter D and
G] . They stress the methodology of the heart,
performance, an '"indigenous feminist
communitarian ethic that embraces an ethics of
truth grounded in love, care, hope, and
forgiveness"', a feminist communitarian model
which gives participants an equal say over what
should be studied with which methods, how findings
are to be validated and implemented (2.1)
Indigenous scholars are particularly valued with
the challenge to conventional research. Kaupapa
Maori approaches for example insist researchers
listen and participate, and for the people
themselves to be agentic and authoritative (2.2).
Research should also be evaluated in terms of
concrete experience and in a way that '"privileges
storytelling, listening, advice, and personal
performance narratives"' (2.3) aimed at enhancing
moral agency, moral discernment, a commitment to
praxis and justice, and ethic of resistance — that
is not just the production of new knowledge. This
will replace the conventional ethical problems
since subjects and researchers now collaborate.
There is no need for confidentiality,
participation is voluntary, research is
performative, and '"acting together, researchers
and subjects work to produce change in the world"'
(2.4). D and G referred to an underlying '"sacred,
existential epistemology"' which is naturally
non-competitive nonhierarchical and stresses
solidarity love and community. We need to recover
these values against the '"rational Enlightenment
science project"' (2.5). This is not only a
universal human ethic but it is also based on
'locally experienced and culturally prescribed
proto-norms', something primal representing a
notion of good based on '"universal human
solidarity"' (2.6). There are clearly social and
political consequences, based on decolonisation
and reclamation of indigenous practices,
'"healing"' and '"transformation"', politics of
possibility, of hope (2.7).
So the goal is to change the world rather than
produce knowledge as such, but any knowledge
normally produced reflects Western Enlightenment
thinking and must be replaced by respect for local
knowledges, especially that of indigenous groups.
Knowledge is to be performative rather than
propositional. Researchers and researched should
form relationships based on love, solidarity and
resistance, and particularly on participation in
central decisions governing the research —
'research must itself exemplify the form of social
relations that it should be aiming [at]' (3.2).
However, the principles are not clear and terms
are rarely explicated. Feminism, for example, has
many versions, and terms like life enhancing are
particularly unclear [they cite Nietzsche's
conceptions here!]. Care and justice are just as
difficult. The discussion often uses evaluative
terms, assumed to be self validating, while others
are taken to be obvioulsy negative. This
discourages questioning and suggests there are
just two opposed positions. However there is much
variation in complexity. Ironically, there is
'little commitment to dialogue displayed in how
this alternative account of research ethics is
often presented' (3.5)[I have myself noticed a
slide from is to ought and back again]. The
principles might contradict — for example love and
forgiveness on the one hand and resistance on the
other, which might obviously involve violence.
Feminist perspectives might clash with 'most
indigenous cultural perspectives', and indigenous
communities often display sex and age
discrimination (3.6). The strong utopian strain
distracts from practical feasibility. It is not
clear that establishing a vague solidarity will
offer the same sort of protections that the
mainstream approaches establish — informed
consent, anonymity. A fully open community devoted
to the common good simply ignores potential
divisions, and might involve repression. This
community seems attainable immediately rather than
after a revolution as in Marxism, and we can
get there through research itself (3.7).
It is not sure if ethics of care and justice
should be extended to unpleasant political or
social groups — bankers or terrorists. Why should
only sympathetic groups be studied? Participation
does not always work anyway — for example there is
often reluctance to participate, or researchers
can curb or modify participation if discussions go
into say 'sexist or racist messages' (3.8).
An emphasis on justice focuses the issues. The
notion of justice was already important in
conventional research ethics, especially that
based on medical research, but commentators have
noticed that it is still difficult. Qualitative
researchers have long been interested in
reciprocity, so that both sides gain from the
research, instead of just researchers who get data
and information and can generate research projects
which provide benefits. Perhaps the relationship
is 'intrinsically' exploitative (4.2). Against
this view, it's often argued that the people
studied do get benefits, even if only finding
someone who will listen, a kind of therapy.
Sometimes minor services like reading and writing
letters are also offered by ethnographers,
sometimes even payment.
Justice has now become a stronger principle,
perhaps, and research is indeed seen as part of a
general issue of the distribution of power. It is
another thing to argue however that researchers
should compensate for this inequality, although D
and G are close to this.
Despite all the discussion, the notion of justice
is still '"an essentially contested concept"'
(4.5). D and G adopt a very broad conception, but
there are serious problems relating justice and
other principles, which may conflict and produce
serious dilemmas — eliminating them might result
in 'totalitarianism' [citing Popper] (4.6). There
are narrower definitions, perhaps turning on
equitable distribution of goods or costs, or the
notion of just deserts — 'the "economic" and
"legal" interpretations' (4.8). This connects with
Bentham or Marx, for example, while meritocrats
stress social contribution. As this shows, there
are still disagreements. Judgements are
underpinned by assumptions [and attempts to
calculate things like benefits and costs]. Actual
cases often produce discrepant views.
Applying it to research might involve either goals
or means. Taking goals first, arguing that
research should aim at justice assumes that
researchers are privileged in these debates. There
is a risk that researchers might not be able to
'warrant' their conception of justice in practice,
but mostly, they simply do not have the power to
promote justice. Just carrying out research 'is
unlikely to be the most effective strategy' (4.
10) [CF Foucault and Deleuze on the relation
between theory and revolutionary practice, or
Habermas]. It is one thing for researchers to be
motivated by the hope for a more just society, but
this is not the same as making that the very goal
of the research — that would assume considerable
[political] knowledge and it also 'increases the
danger of bias, since researchers will often be
torn between doing what they judge to be most
likely to promote justice and acting in the most
effective ways so as to produce sound knowledge'
(4. 11). False findings can promote justice. There
is an old Enlightenment view that truth and
justice are closely connected — and that 'does
need to be rejected'. There are even other ethical
principles to consider [which are usually
justified in the name of achieving sound
knowledge]. The new criteria might actually reduce
the importance of justice, especially if it does
not 'distribute [even consider] benefits and
costs… In the way that medical trials do'.
[Luckily] there are only minor costs and benefits
involved usually (4.12).
It is not always unjust to not involve
participants in research. They are not necessarily
oppressed. Not 'all role differentiation… Is
unjust'. All societies generate power differences.
Why should the power of researchers be
particularly illegitimate? Pursuing sound
knowledge as the major goal still involves
responsibility and ethical acceptability. Sharing
responsibilities can sometimes muddy the issue.
Whether participation in research helps challenge
wider injustices is also doubtful, and D and G
provide no evidence for this. Where does it stand
in terms of other struggles for justice, including
political or even military ones? What if it does
not even produce sound knowledge? The whole thing
seems to resemble Freire on conscientisation, but
this is not the same as research.
Care is another apparently general principle,
linked to the general argument that research
should produce more beneficial than harmful
results, classically in the field of health.
Caring professions can sometimes affect research.
The issue is why it should be given a major
priority.
D and G possibly draw upon feminist work here,
where it is argued that women have distinctive
'experiencing of nurturing and mothering' (5.2),
or relations are seen as somehow '"ontologically
basic"'. These will be particularistic not
universalistic concerns [see below] . Care seems
to be a general attitude or sensibility affecting
all behaviour [nevertheless]. Human beings are
seen as interdependent, researchers require
emotional sensitivity and empathy. Research should
be a process permitting growth. Consequences for
the people involved should be to the fore. This
can be particularistic [related to those with
particular needs] — children are more vulnerable,
for example.
This approach is criticised 'even by many
feminists'(5.4). It reproduces the sexual division
of labour, and here, the notion of care 'is at
odds with the principle of justice'. A form of
essentialism might be involved if caring is seen
to be innate to women — and those who do not
demonstrate caring are seen as 'not proper women'
(5.5). Broader practices involving care might be
considered instead.
Attempting to apply the ethics of care to research
has led to proposals such as the need for '"fluid
research goals''' (5.7), where researchers fully
grasp the experience of others and engage in
mutual critique and understanding. This is in
contrast to the usual 'brief, highly formalised
interchanges designed to elicit data from people'
(5.8). However, more diffuse relationships have
also been criticised as involving 'a form of
deception', where friendly relations are
cultivated for the purposes of research, just as
salesmen might simulate friendship.
This seems to be a single idealised model of the
caring relationship, whereas in practice it might
vary considerably and be connected with, sometimes
conflict with, other ethical concepts such as
reciprocity, trust or respect. We see this with
professions like nursing. Do researchers have the
same burden of care anyway? There is not even a
good argument that caring relationships 'confer
epistemological privilege' and lead inevitably to
sounder knowledge, and there is the problem of
whether we need to care for those who belong to
oppressor groups. We can see some conflicts in
cases where, for example we are researching young
people — does this compromise autonomy? Is this a
form of disguised adult control? [All these points
are referenced to other commentators].
Relationships are not egalitarian anyway, say
between parents and children, and sometimes
authority has to be used. Neither Heidegger nor
Foucault would support this notion of care.
Research subjects should not be seen as clients,
so caring need not be central. Overall, care is 'a
contested concept' (5.13). It might conflict with
a commitment to justice.
Overall, there is a 'wide range of ethical
concepts' (6.1.) involved here, some of which have
serious problems. There is a lack of clarity, and
little supporting argument. Conflicting
implications are not explored. We saw this with
just two of the principles — justice and care.
These are not the main goals of research, as
indeed is also the case with practice in some
caring professions. The main emphasis on
participatory forms actually 'reflects a broad
sociopolitical philosophy which is at odds with
that underpinning most social science' (6.2). That
latter view accepts divisions of tasks and
responsibilities and distrusts utopianism. It
looks at realist constraints on action.
Participatory enquiry does not follow
automatically from the principles anyway, and it
can contradict 'what ought to be the central
concern of all social researchers: to produce
sound knowledge' (6.2)
[There are some useful notes which extend the
arguments into secondary literature]
back to Hammersley page
|
|