Notes on: Hammersley, M. (1992).
On Feminist Methodology. Sociology 26 (2): 187 –
206. DOI: 10.1177/0038038592026002002
Dave Harris
Feminists claim that they have a distinctive
approach, a commitment to qualitative, for
example, or particular 'methodological and
epistemological assumptions'(187). There are
different positions, but four underlying themes:
1. Gender is seen to be central to human social
relations, and a key reason for differences in
power. It's crucial and must be included in any
analysis. Conventional social science is primarily
about the experience of men 'presented as if it
were human experience'. Women's experience must be
studied, conventional social science must be
assessed for male bias.
2. Personal experience is emphasised instead of
scientific method, sometimes with empiricist
undertones. This can lead to the argument that
personal experience cannot be invalidated, that
women have access to truths and reality that are
not available to men. They are oppressed and know
about this at a bodily level, while men lack
empathy and therefore sociological imagination.
Sometimes, women have double consciousness,
knowing both the dominant culture and their own
deviant perceptions. Sometimes this leads to the
argument that only women can do feminist research,
to unstructured qualitative data and analysis, the
denial of objective rules and objectivity in
research which is seen as a masculine perspective:
objectivity itself can be '"an excuse for a power
relationship"' [citing Stanley and Wise] (189).
3. There should be no hierarchies between
researcher and researched, researchers should
share personal experiences and authentic
relations. Sometimes this means equal
participation of people studied, so that
participants can see what is significant to them.
Sometimes it needs to an interest in
conscientisation. The researcher is also relevant
in research, and has a duty to explain underlying
reasoning procedures and their own experience.
Hierarchy is rejected on ethical grounds, with
non-hierarchy particularly relevant to women; on
methodological grounds, only authentic relations
will deliver the truth; a practical interest in
consciousness-raising and emancipation where the
researched must necessarily be involved.
4. Research is aimed at emancipation rather than
the production of valid knowledge. Truth can only
be discovered in struggle against oppression and
should be related to how it achieves emancipation.
This is conscientisation. The opposite also
follows — that mere description is conservative,
and that struggle itself is necessary to produce
adequate social science research.
There are clearly some underlying ideas about
method:
1. Gender had been given relatively little
attention, not much research had focused on gender
differences and the experiences of women, and the
importance of gender is an extraneous variable had
been 'underplayed' (191), and research from boys
and men generalised instead. Gender difference on
the research process itself had been ignored. All
these are valuable, but is gender of unique
importance? Other variables have also been
neglected — some black feminists have mentioned
race, some poststructuralist feminists have talked
about a 'wider plurality of differences'.
Establishing 'essentializing definitions of
womanhood' has led to problems, and gender has
been unduly prioritised – 'while gender is very
important, in my view it should not be given any
preestablished priority over other variables'
(192) [you're dead mate].
2. Claiming the superiority of direct experience
over method is fairly common in qualitative
methodology, but this privileges experience as a
form of 'direct access to the truth' (192). We can
never get outside our own physiology and culture.
Experience is important, but it cannot replace
method. It risks 'false cultural assumptions being
embedded in the data', it still contains error and
may prevent 'efficient data collection'. Instead,
experience should be corrected by method, and vice
versa. Few philosophers stress exclusive reliance
on method or procedure, and few would reject
method completely. We need to retain the idea of
making the means of doing research public, and
'therefore open to collective assessment and
improvement', explicit, and more instrumental
about choosing appropriate strategies. We should
apply methods 'as a trial, in a tentative manner',
and we may have to change them. Feminist
challenges might help counter rigid methodological
ideas, but they also encourage an idea that
experience is 'beyond question' [193). We need
instead 'communal questioning of assumptions…
Those judged to be open to reasonable doubt', we
want to involve the research community in
suspending assumptions that are not shared, and
attempting to establish validity within shared
assumptions.
Feminists can suggest that direct experience
prevails over method and gives uniquely valid
insights — 'feminist standpoint epistemology'.
Other groups also claim privileged insights,
including Marxists, but also Nazi scientists.
There can be diversity arising from different
social locations, and this can be fruitful, but
'we must beware of claims that one group or
category of people necessarily has more valid
insights than another'. Experiences are
construction, with the capacity for error as well
as truth. All information is processed by factors
including 'cultural conditioning, social context'.
Perhaps women have unique insight into the motives
of their oppressors — but the reverse could also
be argued for effective oppression. Women can
appeal to both dominant culture and also their own
direct experience, as can some members of both
dominant and subordinate cultures — 'there is
probably some truth in it' (194), but so can other
categories of persons experiencing more than one
culture. This can even be seen as 'the norm in
large, complex societies'. There is a parallel in
the Marxist view that the proletariat have
uniquely valid insights, but this usually
necessitated separating a true vision from actual
beliefs: the latter often diverse and
inconsistent. Same problems arise with the
category of woman, and there is an implicit
elitism here too — that insight belongs to
'feminists involved in the struggle'. Of course
feminist themselves displayed diverse and
inconsistent views, leading to a problem about
which ones we should select. Stanley and Wise
suggest that all experiences and views are valid
in themselves, but this involves relativism and
'provides no basis for the rational resolution of
disagreements'. It also minimises the real
conditions of women's oppression independently of
their experiences. This diversity can actually be
an advantage in helping us minimise bias, as
Merton once said — using both insider and outsider
perspectives will enlarge our chance of
understanding. This is preferable to any attempt
to privilege some category or declare all points
of view to be equally valid. One consequence on
the emphasis on experiences is an undue emphasis
on unstructured methods — these are valuable but
may not be appropriate 'to all purposes' (195) as
many feminists recognise.
3. Ethnographers have often discussed the
variations in the role of participant and
observer. There are both observer effects and
ethical concerns. The consensus these days seems
to be that no one should try to act as a neutral
or uninvolved observer, even if they are not
actually committed to a particular group. It is
common to argue that the researchers' own values
should be explicit [and the authority for this
goes back to Weber]. Collaborative research has
emerged in a number of other fields, including
educational research [Stenhouse]. So these are not
distinctive feminist ideas. There are ethical and
political issues raised by feminists, but problems
with them.
For example, there are 'ethical, methodological
and tactical considerations' which lead to an
argument against hierarchy in the research
relationship. It is not clear if the elimination
of hierarchy just involves research on women. It
would in any case be difficult to study women
alone because their lives are 'so closely
interrelated' with those of men. If we focused on
unique women's experiences, we might have more
trouble researching 'the world that produced these
experiences' (196). If men are included as sources
of data, they may insist on introducing their own
hierarchy, requiring special control by feminist
researchers — such as choosing 'between being
dominant or being dominated'(196) [so when
researching men, hierarchical research techniques
might be needed]. Women in powerful positions
might raise the same dilemma, and researching them
means 'feminists may also be forced into
hierarchical relationships, one way or the other'.
How desirable are non-hierarchical relationships
and equality of control over the research process?
Feminist discussions often use a one-dimensional
notion of hierarchy, implying all-pervasive
control usually exercised by a group or person at
the expense of others. Such 'power is rarely
all-encompassing' in pluralist societies, so it is
unlikely that researchers will dominate the lives
of their subjects. They do have limited control
over the project, defining the topic, deciding how
data is to be connected, how the analysis is to be
done and so on, but this is not even 'a claim to
total control over the research process itself',
because they can be denied access to places or
information. Research is usually marginal to the
research subjects. It is not the same as
controlling employers, clients or students [which
are probably worse]. Can all inequalities be
rejected anyway? Can there be no hierarchy as in
representative democracy? Is democracy always the
best way to make decisions?
Even if researchers do dominate the research
process, this still might not be against the
interests of others. Having a say is not always an
overriding issue. This is to deny the expertise of
the researcher and reduce her opinion to that of
any other woman. This has led to accusations that
publication involves domination. Research does
involve a claim to intellectual authority, which
is circumscribed and based on the idea that the
findings of research are 'on average, less likely
to be in error than information from other
sources' (197), and this is so because there is a
whole research community which can scrutinise
research. Everyone is entitled to their own
opinions, but they need not be treated as equally
likely to be true. We do not even do this in
everyday life. Of course it is not only research
findings that are superior — we also trust
information based on first-hand experience. It is
rational nevertheless to give them more attention
than mere opinions.
Some feminists would reject this claim to
intellectual authority because it conflicts with a
commitment to equality, the right for individual
groups to define reality for themselves. But this
still assumes a link between understanding a
situation and then being able to change it by
activities such as redefinitions. Successful
action equally depends on accurate information and
therefore expertise. It would be 'an anti-realism'
to deny such expertise. We see the problems with
Stanley and Wise who pursue the anti-hierarchical
argument to a logical 'and contradictory
conclusion' [they don't want to be seen to be
telling other feminists anything should be,
because there is no one feminist research; the
personal is the main principle for research anyway
— '"this may be a contradiction at the heart of
what we believe "' (198), but their book
necessarily makes a claim to valid knowledge].
Researchers always do if they publish their
findings, and this makes them obliged to check on
the reliability of information themselves.
There is a methodological case against hierarchy
in that hierarchy will distort the context and
thus the data. This assumes that you get data only
from unconstrained accounts by informants.
Informants have more interests and commitments
than those of the research team, however. It also
assumes that the only data is provided in the
accounts of informants — but what of the wider
social forces that influence behaviour, what of
the threats to reliable observation, do people
always know their own motives? Informers' accounts
should always be examined. Much data is
observational anyway. The researchers are
necessarily more active, collating information,
and there are always threats to validity. There is
no 'single ideal authentic situation in which data
are necessarily error free' (199).
The final argument is that if the goal of research
is to bring about female emancipation, then women
need to be involved in it. This assumes that
research should aim at female emancipation.
Overall, the specifics of the research
investigation need to be investigated. There is no
'authentic related (personhood)' as in Stacey, and
the rest of life shows all the usual dilemmas and
inequalities as research does, so it is naive to
insist that that one relationship is
nonhierarchical.
It is argued that scientific enquiry should
attempt to change the world rather than just
describe it, in the classic work of Marx, and
others argue that truth should be judged in terms
of practical efficacy, including US pragmatists.
Again this claim is not unique to feminism, and it
has a number of problems. Changing the world
should not be the immediate goal of research, nor
should it be judged against that goal.
Emancipation seems to be too simplistic, implying
a neat division into oppressors and oppressed,
with no proper analytical content for those
concepts anyway. Oppressions of different kinds
cannot be reduced to sexual oppression, so many
people will be both oppressors and oppressed — we
know for example that black feminists criticise
white feminists for neglecting racism, and even
black women in Western societies might be regarded
as oppressors on an international scale. For that
matter, oppression itself is problematic, assuming
some state where there is never a frustration of
preferences, where only real needs are identified.
This will depend usually on a '"naturalist
conception of the human agent"' (200) who can
identify all their needs, or that experts can
identify needs. Human agency is too fluid. It is
not easy to identify needs, and we tend to
reconstruct them on the basis of their own
feelings and our interpretations of what others
say. There may be inconsistency in disagreement.
Interests or needs sascribed to a group might not
match their actual beliefs and this contradiction
can be a problem. There is a particular problem
with distinguishing genuine desires and those
which are actually against the group's interests.
Finally, there might be several alternative
reconstructions of what the needs are and much
genuine disagreement.
If oppression is difficult, so is emancipation. If
oppression is not simple and reducible to a single
dimension, nor can emancipation be. Marxists claim
that their view will be validated by history which
will finally reconcile different views in the
triumph of the proletariat. Just as his views were
limited, so will be the argument that women's
emancipation will abolish all the other forms of
oppression — 'indeed, it is possible that it could
worsen them' (201). Without emancipation, however,
'negative critique can be little more than
negativism for the sake of it'.
There are inequalities between sexes and feminist
politics need not wait until these issues have
been resolved, but researchers do have a
responsibility to attempt conceptualisation. One
thing needs to be reformed is the instrumental
view of the relationship between theory and
practice: practice is complex and it cannot just
be driven by research findings.
There is a pragmatic criterion for truth in the
argument for emancipation, and practice again
suggests greater complexity. Successful action can
be based on false assumptions, and vice versa.
Truth and effectiveness are different values with
no necessary connection. We cannot judge the value
of research 'entirely in terms of practical
success'(202) and research anyway requires 'some
autonomy from practical concerns', rejecting the
idea that research that is not immediately useful
in emancipation is illegitimate.
Political movements must reflect on goals and
strategies and gather information, but with them,
practice shapes the process of enquiry, and this
is both good and bad — the bad bits involve the
pressures of practice and the commitments of the
audience restricting topics of enquiry and
limiting testing. Raising wider questions may be
counter-productive from the point of view of
immediate practice, however. This makes a case for
some form of 'institutionalised inquiry that is
not geared to the immediate requirements of any
single political or social practice', but whose
findings might be relevant to a wide range of
practices. It should not be directed to pragmatic
goals or judged in pragmatic terms, but judged
against a wider view of public relevance. This is
the traditional basis for scholarship and science,
and we need to defend it against those who would
'wish to tie inquiry to their own practical goals,
and this includes feminists'.
In conclusion, feminism is a major contributor to
the social sciences, but feminist methodology is
not 'a coherent and cogent alternative to
non-feminist research'. Ideas are shared with
non-feminist literature. Many ideas are
unconvincing. Separating off a specifically
feminist methodology 'homogenises other research
and other views' (203). It suggest a strong link
between political and philosophical assumptions
and research decisions, but research is 'a more
pragmatic enterprise'. Methodological distinctions
can lead to Balkanisation [apparently Merton's
term]. It is counter-productive in that there
would be no obligation to adopt feminist
methodology if you are a non-feminist, or to
respect their findings. Others should engage in
debates with feminists. 'This article is offered
in the spirit of such a debate' (203)
[There are some interesting notes, including note
12, 204, that says that collaborative research
with other women is not unproblematic and might
actually involve a form of exploitation].
Replies:
Gelsthorpe,L. (1992) Response to
Martin Hammersley's Paper 'on Feminist
Methodology'. Sociology, 26 (2): pp 213
– 18. DOI: 10.1177/0038038592026002004
This addresses the first three headings [since
Ramazanoglou has addressed the 4th]. Gender is
privileged by feminist but not any uniform way, as
some of the feminists quoted indicate — there are
intersections. Nor should emphasis on gender just
mean an emphasis on women. Early feminist work did
privilege gender for rhetorical reasons, but later
material looks at masculinity and femininity.
Gender is a crucial mediating variable when
discussing racial or class oppression, for
example.
Female emancipation should not be emphasised if
feminism is seen as 'a transitory stage to an
ideal human state which would accommodate the
diversity of men and women' (213), but it is
acceptable 'as a necessary corrective to male
domination' (214).
The focus on experience is indeed misplaced if it
assumes that anything goes, and critical awareness
is abandoned. However much recent feminist work
talks about 'the role of experience in method
rather than versus method'. Quantitative methods
are commonly dismissed as inconsistent with
feminist values, mostly because they offer only a
shallow understanding and can even ignore sex and
gender differences. It is intensive quantification
in particular that needs to be tackled.
The emphasis on experience does recognise personal
reflexivity in the sense that researchers are also
human beings and that they use normal human
methods to understand. This is part of the 'quest
to be open and honest' rather than an attack on
objectivity. Scientistic objectivity does need to
be questioned. None of this implies not being
'critical, rigorous or accurate'. Instead,
researchers should make ' interpretive schemes
explicit'.
Hammersley is right to express a concern of the
view that accounts of women's experiences offer
better knowledge of situations — this is his
version of standpoint theory. Nevertheless
researching standpoints can be valuable,
especially if we remember that people do not just
occupy one standpoint. This is a safeguard against
excluding those who do not seem to adopt that
standpoint: 'we cannot assume that black/white,
young/old, and so on, experience life in the same
way' (215).
Knowledge can emerge from the struggle to overcome
domination, raising awareness of 'multi
dimensional experiences of reality' and revealing
how everyday worlds are shaped. It is another
thing to claim that this would provide better
knowledge. We should focus instead on knowledge
production, how the process of knowing can be
traced to particular standpoints [sociology of
knowledge then? Any shared criteria or is this
relativism?] . There is a need to distinguish good
from less good knowledge [how exactly, though?] ,
but the knowledge claims of science 'can be viewed
as deeply suspicious' [citing Feyerabend and
Popper — neither of them feminist as far as I
know]. Cain argues for 'successor science'[so
that's where it comes from in Denzin's stuff on
indigenous people]. Personal reflexivity is linked
with theoretical reflexivity, and we can pursue
the second by drawing upon a number of 'guidelines
developed from realist ontology and epistemology'
to provide a foundation [not a feminist foundation
then?] — Including 'hermeneutic techniques,
theoretical pragmatism' (216). She still argues
that knowledge produce from this standpoint 'must
"work" for those from whose standpoint it was
produced' [cf plugging in]. But an adequate theory
must explain not only ourselves but also 'those
whom we investigate'[does she mean women and their
male oppressors, or researchers and researched?].
Feminists are already aware of the difficulties of
managing hierarchical relationships. They should
be abandoned in research because otherwise the
relationship involves 'treating people as mere
objects', with a link between sex objects and
research objects for Stanley and Wise. [BIzarre
universal humanism which invovles, to take
Schutz's example, a full intimate knowledge of the
postal worker's world as she delivers the mail] It
goes against the traditional advice to be entirely
neutral and to refuse all questions about the
researchers opinion. However there is a difference
between dismantling power differentials between
women and women and between female researchers and
men. The first will value interactive methodology,
but not necessarily the second, for example where
male offenders are being researched. There are
problems with democratising the research process
discussed by feminists themselves, and Barker has
even argued about the dangers of a false equality
where researchers somehow have to negate their
knowledge and skills in a gesture of equality.
So while Hammersley's comments are useful, he does
tend to miss out the debate and internal critique
in feminism. Feminists have been struggling with
these issues and there is no single feminist line.
So his discussion ought to really begin with his
concluding points on the complexity of the issues.
There is no single feminist position on all these
issues. Finally, feminists have not particularly
argued for a domination of feminist methodology —
there is no consensus on methodology although
there are methodological preferences.
'Hammersley has thus demolished a case that never
really was'(217).
Ramazonoglou, C. (1992) On
Feminist Methodology: Male Reason Versus Female
Empowerment. Sociology 26 (2): 207 – 12
Hammersley has a 'fundamental opposition to the
central tenets of feminist thinking' (207) which
can be assembled from the piecemeal points he
makes. Contradictions include acknowledging the
positive contribution feminism is made while
finding feminist methodologies unconvincing. He
wants to privilege reason 'in some sort of
established scientific community'. For him,
knowledge reflects 'a conceptual split between the
goals of science and rationality and the goals of
politics and personal commitment'[old weberian
fact/value stuff]. Any paradigms trying to link
these two threatens an obstacle to open debate and
dogmatism.
The transformation of gender relations cannot be
the point of feminist research, therefore.
Feminism along with Marxism can be dismissed as
political and dogmatic and therefore not
scientific or rational. To give feminists any
credit involves accepting empirical findings is
valid but not accepting the grounds on which this
knowledge has been produced.
Hammersley does not 'seem to see his own place in
the research process as a gendered one' and
assumes that his stances value free and gender
free. The same goes with his demands that public
relevance is the issue, but this ignores how the
public domain itself is gendered [and dominated by
class]. He can only rely on some tradition of
scholarship and science, which again is taken for
granted: the rational validator is do not seem to
have political positions or make key assumptions
or have practical goals.
If reason and emotion are linked, feminists might
be forgiven an emotional reaction at this point,
referring to 'unthinking sexism and implicit
racism… Widespread in sociology'. (208) Hammersley
might at least have looked at 'the feminist
critique of the Enlightenment dualisms'[but are
these valid critiques, just to close the circle].
Hammersley's position has been analysed and
rejected by feminists. Value neutrality is not
possible, objectivity is not separable from
subjectivity, any more than mind is from body
reason from emotion. Feminists have attacked these
conceptions of rationality and 'male dominated and
male defined relevance in the public domain'.
Western scholarship in science depend on views
that are 'blatantly sexist and racist, and
privilege middle-class males'. Notions of reason
and science are 'masculinist' and used to exclude
and belittle women and other subordinates.
Feminist scholars themselves have experienced
sexism and subordination in the so-called neutral
Academy.
All schools of sociology 'systematically privilege
male knowledge, experience and interests but
without acknowledging that this is what they do'
(209). There are intersections with other forms of
domination. Feminist research does not just choose
gender as an additional variable but 'offers new
theories of power' and how it works in social
divisions, including those between women.
Feminists are aware of the difficulties of
validating experience and there is disagreement.
This should not detract from the point that
'women's experiences of gendered power relations'
as a source of knowledge has been hitherto ignored
by 'masculinist sociology'. Even theorising has
not been possible, hence 'new ways of knowing',
feminist methodology.
If we study domestic violence, we cannot study it
'apolitically' [but should we try to?], Especially
if we see '"normal" domestic behaviour as violent'
[so we have politicised it first by definition].
Knowledge gained of domestic violence from
initially political aims has led to new knowledge
and identified the 'social relationships, ideas
and institutions which allow such violence to
develop'. This sort of effort both empowers women
and problematises notions of knowledge and
rationality. Feminist methodologies address issues
of ways of knowing and criteria for valid
knowledge. Hammersley has ignored this because he
lacks 'a theory of power' and has a 'supposedly
ungendered stance' (209). He is ready to accept
inequalities of class, race and gender while
ignoring the effects they have on power, on ways
of knowing, and on experience.
Feminist methodologies are not claiming privilege.
There are varied explorations of how we validate
knowledge. These raise difficult problems about
truth which had been evaded by sociology before.
We now know about 'power struggles throughout the
research process' (210) and can challenge the way
they have been silenced 'as leading to gendered
knowledge which privileges male interests'.
There are differences between feminists, including
methodological and epistemological differences.
Some are empiricist, others realist. Sometimes
standpoint epistemology helps share the
experiences of the researched, but in other cases,
there are power relations dividing subjects from
researchers, and subjects do not 'theorise
themselves'in the same ways in which they are
'theorised by feminists' [false consciousness].
Feminist methodologies are about seeking knowledge
and truth, but also forms of political commitment.
This is a necessary characteristic, an 'immensely
ambitious project in seeking ways of knowing which
avoids subordination'. There is no alternative to
political commitment or 'any other ways of
knowing'. Validation is always a problem. Ways of
knowing which Hammersley likes also have political
goals, and his support for them 'will by default
empower men by maintaining the status quo'.
Weaknesses identified in feminism in fact applied
to sociology in general: feminism has just made
them explicit. Threats to validity are matters of
concern for funding bodies colleagues and
students, so the 'problems of explanation raised
by feminism' (211) are 'necessary and urgent'.
Feminism has exposed the role of power
relationships. It has exposed unreasonable
assumptions about 'reason'. It might have no
general solution, but we cannot dismiss it in the
name of 'the assumed superiority of a rational
scientific community'. Researchers have political
commitments and elements of subjectivity. It is
more logical to accept them rather than 'to assume
that some of us can rise above them'. In general,
feminist work has been open, creative and
productive, but Hammersley's position threatens to
close off further discussion by seeing gender as
'an extraneous variable within a male
appropriation of knowledge'. This would disempower
women and 'should be resisted'.
back to Hammersley page
|
|