Notes on: Hammersley, M
(1994). On Feminist Methodology: a
Response. Sociology. 28 (1): 293
– 300
Dave Harris
Ramazonoglu is wrong to say that the
whole of feminism is rejected, and instead
he is rejecting a distinctly feminist
methodology. Other arguments may well be
valid although they can all be questioned.
Like all new research paradigms based on
new epistemological and political claims,
they have problems.
One is that the transformation of gender
relations is the point of feminist
research as R claims. But the point of
research is to produce knowledge not
political results. The claim that
knowledge is intrinsically political can
highlight some features but obscure
others. Political activity is about
persuasion and the most effective and
ethical means to do this, including
playing down doubts or suppressing
relevant information, even 'deception and
manipulation' (294). These are not
reasonable in research, or rather they
should not be.
It should be possible to come to rational
conclusions about factual and maybe even
many value issues, and scholarly enquiry
is the best option. But this is not his
view held uncritically, as R suggests: he
is well aware of arguments against it and
the need to clarify the rational basis.
There can be disagreement, but this does
not mean that a position is uncritical or
irrational.
The split between the goals of science and
the goal of commitment is held to be
useful, but there may be no difference in
importance between these goals. However
only the former 'can be rational', that is
that different courses of action are
rational in each one. Feminism cannot be
dismissed just for being political or
dogmatic and he did not claim this, nor
did he claim that non-feminist research is
superior. He is not denying that his own
views have been shaped by his situation
including his gender, but he does not
think that this has had an inevitable
effect or a damaging one. Instead 'we all
have the capacity for approximating forms
of reason that are universally valid',
even though interests can be expected to
vary [shades of Popper and Third World
knowledge here]. R's distinction between
reason and commitment means that politics
is irrational [but not irrelevant].
Current conceptions of rationalism might
well be less than ideal but we need them
and there is no working alternative,
certainly not one offered by feminism.
Most of the ideas in fact are parallel to
conventional research and methodology —
there can be no sharp line drawn around
feminist methodology. R believes there can
but provides no evidence and assumes that
terms like reason and emotion are
unproblematic and universally accepted,
but they are not homogeneous any more than
positivism is.
There might even be an essentialist view
of non-feminist ideas here, some idea of a
long tradition of sexist and racist views.
No doubt some of the views in Western
scholarship can be sexist and racist, as
some of those found elsewhere, but they
are not so tightly defined that 'sexism or
racism in one corrupts all the rest'[as in
dominant ideology] (295). Women have been
excluded from the Academy, but this is not
the same as arguing that therefore the
knowledge produced by the Academy must be
sexist: that is as crude as arguing that
it must be bourgeois. There was a bias,
and sometimes knowledge was used for
exclusion, but it is not warranted to say
that therefore the whole of knowledge is
bourgeois ideology.
R argues that he sees no relationship
between gender and power, and has no
theory of power when discussing
sociological theory, but offers no
evidence — he just takes a different view.
She does no more than offer a declaration
with an implied determinism, which
threatens the basis for any rational
discussion.
Gelsthorpe makes more specific arguments
and these are not fundamentally different
from his own, although he accuses him of
exaggerating the emphasis on women's
experience. This is accepted although it
reflects the public discussions of
feminist methodology. G argues that there
is still a need to be critical rigourous
and accurate, but one problem here is the
term objectivity — one interpretation
refers precisely to rigour and accuracy,
and for him, there is a necessary
implication that 'the things we describe,
explain, et cetera are for the most
part... independent of our accounts of
them' (296) although of course there are
philosophical problems.
G says standpoint theory is not mutually
exclusive or fixed, but the versions he
was criticising are and claim privilege
knowledge for women or feminists. G's
argument is more general that different
social positions offer different insights,
but this implies that men as well as women
can have distinctive sources of insight,
and many feminist standpoint theorists
'would not be prepared to accept' this. So
there is substantial agreement overall
with G, but he was surprised with her
conclusion that he has demolished the case
that did not exist, since most of the
articles he cites to argue that there is a
convincing case for feminist methodology
and indeed R believes this, and so does
Williams.
Willams endorses R's rejection of his view
of knowledge and says that he operates
with narrow binary divides, that he says
that sociologists have no choice to either
aim at science or politics and personal
commitment, either reason or emotion. He
does make such distinctions but is not
clear whether she thinks that can be
overcome, are too binary, or should be
reinterpreted differently.
The complexities are seen in her response
to his discussion of experience and
method. She says he identifies experience
with the subjects of research, but he was
saying that participant experience should
not be treated as privileged, but nor is
the method and experience on the part of
the researcher sufficient. Nor is the
distinction between science and politics a
simple binary. It's not clear how Williams
would approach the task, and she is too
quick to accuse him of writing in a
political and committed way.
She also says that feminist sociology is
not homogenous, but he never asserted
that. He was more interested in the case
for a distinctive methodology. Nor can he
agree that conventional social science
offers a rigid unilinear approach. Other
claims about his work are simply wrong —
that he thinks that feminists have
neglected issues of power, although he
does say that nonhierarchical forms of
research are problematic. He is not
denying that method is prominently
discussed in some feminist ethnographers.
He is not particularly against
democratising research relationships,
although what is proposed is open to
criticism. he does not think that all
feminists hold notions of oppression
unthinkingly, and has drawn attention to
some feminists due to see the problems. He
has discussed ways in which feminists have
proposed to avoid subordination, and
although arguing that subordination is
unavoidable in some cases, except that it
is not in others. Some feminists prefer
qualitative data collection, he has
argued. He agrees that the everyday world
has access to sociology and that both
worlds use ideas creatively and
critically. For Williams to argue to the
contrary is a sign that she 'has
constructed a straw man' (298).
He is appealing to the intellectual
authority of elite sociologists, but he
does not say that they must be necessarily
male [bit of a weasel here — easier to
defend me!]. Williams does not clarify
what she means by intellectual authority —
she must have some version of it in
contributing an article to a refereed
journal, and in taking part in the whole
circus of teaching and research. Authority
is associated with an elite — although he
did not specifically say this, especially
if it means 'a single elite ruling group
whose authority is absolute and omni-
relevant'(299). It is instead based on
expertise and is admitted to be fallible
and open to assessment. That is another
difference with standpoint theory.
The three critics differ in their views
about whether there is or is not a
distinctively feminist methodology .R
thinks there is, G seems to think there is
not. Williams sides with R, but also
stresses diversity, leaving common
elements as 'minimal' (299). All the
critics disagree with him, at least
partly, and two disagree at a fundamental
level. However, positions may not be
'incommensurable, intractable though they
may currently be', because there is a view
that matters worth discussing and this can
be a precondition for clarification and
maybe even eventual resolution
|
|
|