White, J. (2008)
‘Illusory Intelligences’, in Journal
of
Philosophy of Education, Vol. 42, No. 3-4: 611–630.
Gardner’s
intelligences:
linguistic, musical, logico-mathematical, spatial, bodily kinaesthetic,
intrapersonal and
interpersonal, to which have now been added naturalist and possibly
existential
intelligences.
Gardner
proposes that these
intelligences arise from his attempt to apply certain prerequisites. Intelligences must indicate a general ability
widespread among human cultures. White
says this is already a problem—all human cultures or just some? He also does not like the first example which
is rejected—the ability to recognise human faces. This
is the first example of what seems to be
arbitrary choice at the heart of
Gardner’s system.
Then there are
specific
criteria:
potential isolation of the
area by brain damage
the existence in it of
idiots savants, prodigies and other exceptional individuals
an identifiable core
operation/set of operations
a distinctive developmental
history, along with a definable set of expert ‘end-state’
performances
an evolutionary history and
evolutionary plausibility support from experimental
psychological tasks
support from psychometric
findings
susceptibility to encoding
in a symbol system (Gardner, 1983, pp. 62–9).
White
indicate some
problems with these criteria, principally the idea that there is a
development
in intelligences. This is misleading,
because human abilities do not develop in the same way in which
biological
faculties do: they might change and grow, but not in a preordained way
as an
unfolding of some quality. To apply
developmentalism here is to imply that there is some upper end state, a
ceiling. This leaves Gardner with the need to define what he means by
maturity,
and this is inevitably subjective, depending on value judgments. Gardner does try to obtain objectivity by
suggesting that evil tyrants can also display a maturity, but this then
invalidates the prerequisite.
White indicates
additional
problems with the idea of encoding in a symbol system.
Gardner depends on another writer, Goodman,
here. In general terms, there is also an ambiguity about the symbol: in
one
sense it means expressing emotion, but in another it has a more
technical
meaning as in a mathematical symbol.
White also
dislikes the
idea of brain damage and brain localisation, which he says are
connected to
Gardner’s developmentalism. White denies
that idiots savants possessed distinct kinds of intelligences, and
prefers the
concept of a particular mental facility to describe their unusual
achievements.
In
general, Gardner’s
criteria are far from easy to applying without invoking subjective
meanings. They seem to depend on
particular theories of developmentalism and symbolisation. Gardner
himself
seems to suggest that not all the criteria are crucial anyway, but
simply a
majority of them. He admits that it is a
matter of judgement, indeed, artistic judgment, whether to admit a
candidate or
not. Nevertheless, Gardner insists he is
doing science, and not offering some kind of philosophical account of
forms of
knowledge. Gardner has tried to reply to
White’s criticism here by suggesting the whole scheme is tentative, a
mere
first step to be confirmed by later work, but this is not enough for
White who
points out that the whole thing might be misplaced.
White says he finds no strong arguments in
Gardner to defend this particular choice of criteria.
Instead,
White proposes to
explain Gardner’s by looking at the intellectual influences that
affected his
approach. He was interested in Piaget
and structuralism, for example, which explains the developmentalism. However, he saw symbols as important to
explain
innovation and creativity, borrowing from structuralism the idea that
these are
basic codes which can produce innovative combinations.
Goodman supplied the necessary symbol theory:
Gardner used it to extend Piaget into the Arts.
Of course, both Piaget and Goodman have been much
criticised. Interests in the other areas
arose from
Gardner’s participation in a project to extend human potential at
Harvard—Gardner was the social psychologist on the team.
Further doubts with subjective judgments were
aroused in the course of this work, Gardner admits, and he flirted with
terms
other than ‘intelligence’ to describe human accomplishments. However, he resisted the idea of forms of
knowledge because that seemed too philosophical and a priori. Gardner wanted to base his theory on
biological psychology.
The extension of
the
original model to include naturalistic and existential intelligence
also
reveals its arbitrary nature. The idea
here was simply to try to expand the scheme to incorporate all human
knowledge—a
forms of knowledge approach, denying that the categories just merge out
of
empirical study. Gardner wants to modify
his approach in later work to separate the intelligence, the capacity,
from the
domain, the area in which it is applied.
But this introduces incoherence, since the whole
approach depends on the
biological and psychological being closely linked to the social. Now they are potentially separated, with the
symbolic relocated to the domain, the social aspects of intelligence. However, the criteria remain unchanged, and
they feature the symbolic as part of the biological and psychological
notion of
intelligence.
Although they
are not
central in Gardner himself, the educational implications have been
substantial,
and the theory of multiple intelligences has been eagerly adopted by
teachers. White is not denying that
there have been useful improvements in dethroning the idea of a central
intelligence measured by IQ, and in allowing greater diversity. However, there is no need to adopt Gardner’s
multiple intelligences to justify this practice. Indeed,
it might be even more satisfying to
suggest there are more than just the seven kinds, and that individuals
have
many more ways of demonstrating their abilities. It
is important for White that practices are
not based on theories that are so demonstrably ‘flaky’.
Gardner is
really in the
business of defining a liberal curriculum, although he denies it. There’s nothing wrong with this idea, but we
should remember that it is only one option that will not suit everybody.
The article ends
with White
running over some of the counter arguments that Gardner has made. The main one for our purposes is that White
denies he is merely getting philosophically picky with what is
essentially an
empirical psychological project. It is
not a matter of different approaches or paradigms, simply that Gardner
misunderstands his own project as a scientific one.
back to ed studs
page
|