Notes on: Zembylas
M, Bozalak, V and Shefer. T. (2014) Tronto's
notion
of privileged irresponsibility and the
reconceptualisation of care:
implications for critical pedagogies of emotion
in higher education. Gender and
Education 26(3):200--214.
DOI: 10.1080/0954025.2014.901718.
Dave Harris
Tronto is a care theorist.This article looks at the implications for
critical pedagogies of her
'political ethics of care'.In
particular, the notion of 'privileged
irresponsibility' raises issues of power
and privilege in the management of emotions and
practices related to caring.
We have known for a while that
care giving is a gendered
form of labour.Tronto sees carers
practice and disposition, to do with maintaining
and repairing the world.Privileged
irresponsibility extends the
politics of care.Tronto has argued that
majority groups take their privileged positions
for granted, and allocate
caring responsibility to others, usually women or
marginals.Caring
is both relied on and disavowed.We can
use this work to challenge moral and
political frameworks underpinning divisions of
labour, including teaching and
caring.We
can also explore 'the
"difficult" emotional knowledge arising from
practices of privileged
irresponsibility…[Including]…The feelings of moral indignation when care
givers are treated unjustly…Emotions
of
guilt and shame' when care receivers realise they
have been complicit as practice
of privileged irresponsibility (201). Caregiving
work is still low status, and
is devalued as a practice.
There are implications for
critical pedagogy of emotion at
HE.This
requires students and educators
to interrogate 'the intersections among power,
emotion, and praxis in society
and education' (201).Tronto
will help
us see how power and emotion interact with
particular concepts of
responsibility.It also raises issues
such as why he we can feel disgust towards the
other 'often concealed under false
claims of empathy and caring' and how we can
'objectify and sentimentalise the
other'in a way which preserves privileged
irresponsibility.Emotional knowledge has been insufficiently
addressed by critical pedagogues so far.
Tronto and Fisher originally
saw caring as everything
required to maintain and repair the world,
including bodies, selves and the
environment.This might be too broad
[!], But it is at least inclusive.Self
care is particularly important for gender and
education, especially caring for
teachers' own needs [including the need to publish
are not always meet student
needs!] It is important not to subsume the self
while caring, and also to be
aware of our own needs for care.The
definition is right to include environment, as a
'"post humanist"
perspective' (202), reconnecting us to the
suffering of animals and how they
might cause 'emotion and discomfort'[a south
African study is cited]. Relations
to the environment can help us develop
'imaginative and inclusive ways of
thinking about relationality , connectivism and
attachments in pedagogical
contexts' (203), with a reference to Braidotti.The definition takes care to be an
emotional practice, in the Marxist
sense of human engagement, something 'crucial for
human life'.As a practice, there is a necessary
political
social and emotional context, which cannot simply
be devolved on to particular
groups.It
follows that ' some caring
practices may be superficial and sentimental if
they do not challenge
inequalities'.The broad definition
helps connect human flourishing to the environment
and to social justice, and
this [somehow] justifies embracing rather than
glossing over feelings.Finally,
care becomes a collective activity
not just a dyadic one, and this helps support
'collaborative teaching and
learning practices'[all a bit forced and bolt on
here].Overall,
this broad definition helps us to
challenge conventional notions of care, including
'seeing the educator as
expert' instead of 'engaging with many and
different sources of authority in
epistemic communities…That
challenge
hegemonic views on care'.[So it
can be
read as a radical practice, but there is also some
notion of adjustment to
social conditions?A politics of care
not a politics of protest?].
We can use Tronto's discussion
of moral elements to form an
evaluative framework to charge current caring
practices.Tronto
says that care involves five phases
and moral stances: (1) 'caring about'(204)
noticing that people have needs which
ought to be addressed, invoking the moral element
of 'attentiveness', the
opposite of active ignorance and denial. (2)
'caring for', taking
responsibility for meeting people's needs, as a
moral matter of responsibility,
more than just 'obligation and duty'. (3)
'caregiving', involving 'competence'as
a moral quality, the opposite of a 'learned
incompetence…A way of avoiding menial caring tasks' such
as pastoral care. (4) 'care receiving', where we
have to be responsive to the
care giver, and this might involve, in education,
assessing whether students
have gained their goals…'This
can be
equated with lifelong learning where learning is a
continuous process'. (5)
'caring with', depending on 'the moral qualities
of trust and solidarity'(205),
and these might be important as the basis for
subsequent struggles against
privileged irresponsibility.[Real
portmanteau stuff here, with all the fashionable
causes crammed in.Rather sinister Foucaldian undertones with
care defined in a rather narrow way, leaving out
granting people independence,
for example and made universal].
All these phases are required
for Tronto, although they are
'inevitably involve conflict', for example when
care givers are not adequately
resourced [which must be virtually the case all
the time].The
second moral element of care,
responsibility, might be focused on in particular,
especially as it seems to
help us understand privileged irresponsibility and
how to contest it.
We start by realizing that care
givers are usually
under-recognised.Caregiving is clearly
connected to gender other forms of inequality, as
when migrant women workers
fill the care gaps in wealthy countries, as with
child care.Powerful
groups have avoided their
responsibilities, for example not even
acknowledging that these practices go
on.Tronto
says this is a way of getting
out of responsibility, or demonstrating privileged
irresponsibility, where
privilege helps us ignore hardships.This can take the form of devaluing the
contributions of the care giver,
trivialising or ignoring them.Privilege
is
also supported by constructions of dominance,
including hegemonic
masculinity [welcome back!Haven't
seen
you for a long time]—real men don't care.[Lots of literature is summarised
displaying the usual contradiction,
that although masculinity is constructed in
different ways, it seems to remain
hegemonic.The
key is 'the conflation of
masculinity with notions of strength, resilience,
and independence…In opposition to vulnerability and care
seeking'(206).So care remains
feminised.Tronto
adds some more
issues—men see themselves as protectors of women,
which makes them subordinate,
and offering 'masculinist non-caring" care'[so is
this care or not?];
dominant groups are interested in acquiring
economic resources and arguing
'that they should be exempted from caring
responsibilities' [assumes that
caring is nothing to do with providing economic
support?]; caring only for
those close, a kind of privatized care, which
ignores wider forms of activity
and exploitation; seeing care as a matter of
personal responsibility, as in neo
liberalism generally, and holding individuals
personally responsible for their
vulnerability; charitable giving [always an
evasion?] [We can clearly see the
notion of care that is privileged {SIC}
here—personal, generalised, nothing to
do with economics, or with organised professional
charities].These
practices help us [men?] to remain
ignorant about the real pattern of care and how
central it is, how everyone
benefits from the gendered division of labour and
so on.Some
misguided female teachers even think
that they 'benefit from working with young
children on the assumption that this
is their vocation as women'.We must
break with these rationalisations and develop
instead 'a sense of our
collective social responsibility for care'(207).
Critical pedagogies of emotion
have arisen from an awareness
of the importance of emotion in higher education
and critical pedagogy [largely
citing Zembylas].Much critical pedagogy
by four overlooked the emotional aspects of
difficult knowledge such as
'trauma, oppression, racism'.The
entanglement of emotions, structures and
inequalities needed more
investigation.Privileged
irresponsibility stands in the way of this,
including the importance of trust
and solidarity: moral responsibilities can be
ignored, and it can be assumed
that other people are tending to them.Ignoring emotions causes harm and this is
'also deeply
emotional'(208).For example, female
teachers who are treated badly can demonstrate
'the emotion of moral
indignation', but this can be dismissed by men as
irrational, a further
justification for women's subordination [lots of
references].An adequate critical pedagogy of the motion
can see how this anger has been constructed, and
what its consequences might
be.[I
go along with this to the extent
that it is a way of calmly discussing emotions
instead of just dismissing them
or fearing them, but the argument is pretty
tenuous in general.Strategic demonstrations of emotion are not
discussed
either].
We can also trace practices and
dispositions about hearing
to social structures and 'socially constructed
identities'.This can 'urge us to reconsider existing
policies and practices of care', for example
understanding emotions of shame
and guilt when care receivers notice the social
position of their carers
[maybe...This
seems to be a suggestion
that care receivers can also develop privileged
irresponsibility].We should be interested in how schools and
other institutions try to eradicate shame, by
erasing history and sanitising
wounds.We
need to reconsider shame and
guilt in a more productive way, for example as a
way into critical reflection
and 'renewed action' (208) towards responsibility
and attentiveness.In HE this would require 'a critical and
sustained engagement' with feelings, their
consequences, and what might be done
to transform the impact of the past.It
would be a way of critiquing neoliberal notions
including the view that
personnel are personally responsible, especially
towards those who are already
unequal and excluded.Of
course, we must
'not dismiss personal responsibility altogether',
or but context it and deny
neoliberal versions.
In this way we can take a
critical stance towards ideas and
practices that ignore emotions and the emotional
consequences of privileged
irresponsibility.It will help us see
how emotions are linked to caring
responsibilities, and how these have been
evaded by privileged groups.We can
see
how work places and organisations help to sustain
hegemony, for example by
dismissing moral indignation, or trying to
eradicate shame 'via an erasure of
history of privileged irresponsibility'(209). We
can offer both analysis and
'action - oriented possibilities', to counter
hegemonic emphasis on some
emotions while ignoring others.
A critique of 'the entanglement
between power, emotion and
responsibility' is been a major contribution of
critical pedagogy of emotions,
addressing important issues such as the movement
of migrants and how they are
included or marginalised.An
emphasis on
the politics of care can see how vulnerability is
constructed and managed, and
responsibility allocated differently.
Dewey [no less] warned that
sometimes compassion will lead
to paternalism which infantilizes and objectifies.A focus
on emotions connecting them to action
will avoid such simplistic and essentialist moral
categories as 'that of
"good" vs. "evil"' (210).These categories can lead to a sentimental
account of the suffering of
others which evokes pity rather than action,
voyeurism and passivity [reference
to an earlier piece,.One
outcome is
charity.However,
overall the picture is
one of complexity, including ways in which
compassion is allocated to different
groups, how power relations produce responsibility
and irresponsibility, and
how power structures are supported by 'emotional
investments and emotion -
informed ideologies'.We
should be
'seeking to make a concrete difference in the
lives of marginalised groups'.
In conclusion educators and
students need to consider their
own conception of caring responsibilities and
irresponsibilities.They might wish to interrogate 'emotions of
anger and resentment among care givers'.They might reconsider the caring
responsibilities of privileged
groups.They
might want to ask how
'emotions such as indignation shame and guilt
become the point of departure for
trust, solidarity and social change'(211).Above all, they need to consider the issues
in 'social ethical and
political terms'.Caring is so
important, that it might be taken as the central
issue, and we can see how it
is bound up with inequalities and their
production, especially gender.It will
help us challenge 'the binaries of
masculinity and femininity', and the denigration
of those who care.If we challenge privileged
irresponsibility,
we can 'create space for the transformative
potential of reconstructing caring
responsibilities for all citizens'.It
has been helpful to discuss Tronto's work because
of its ethical and political
dimension, and because the educational context
shows a particular formation of
caring responsibilities.