Notes
on: Foucault M (1974) The
Archaeology of Knowledge,
London: Tavistock Publications
Ltd
[My] Critical Introduction
This book represents a different level
of analysis for Foucault, away from the
usual analyses of institutions and
institutional ideologies, or networks of
power, to look at the notion of
discourse as constitutive of academic
disciplines. I found many ambiguities in
the discussion of the term 'discourse':
1.
He seems to refer to
different levels of organization --
there are discourses, discursive
formations, positivities, epistemes
and so on. From what I can see,
positivities and epistemes are
discourses in principle, so to speak,
which affect concrete discourses.
2.
This produces an
ambiguity over whether everything is
'discourse'-- Foucault seems to affirm
it in part 2 but denies it in part 4,
perhaps because he is using different
notions of discourse.
3.
There are some weird
oscillations in the argument,
including lots of denial of causality,
essentialism, philosophical
anthropology and so on (especially in
part II), but there is a sense in
which these banned notions return:
Foucault needs causality to explain
the specifics of why one discourse
triumphs and not another; he needs
subjects to do the practices which
constitute discourses. There are some
strange discussions here too of his
own motives, interests, desires and so
on, raising the spectre of the old
combination of theoretical and
political motives for all this,
together with a personal desire to
innovate.
I'm not at all sure that it is all that
original. I was constantly reminded of
work like Kuhn's (which is certainly far
more readable).
Foucault seems to ignore or deny the
specific effectivity of universities and
pedagogies. They are mentioned once or
twice as being important in the
development of discourses, but this is
never pursued. As a result this seems to
be far too much emphasis placed on the
activities of linguists or political
economists or whatever to somehow
dominate public thought. Many of his
actual examples seem located in some
pre-University 'classical' era?
There are some lovely implication for
the emergence of things like 'the
perspectives' in sociology, though.
These must now be seen as a construct,
the result of a [pedagogical?]
discourse.They do imply some underlying
unifying concept as well. They clearly
need deconstruction and then
reconstruction -- as discourses
that claim to cross gaps, or show
relations of difference and so on?
Part one
We need to contrast the usual history of
the emergence of academic disciplines in
terms of some smooth development,
involving underlying causals, and trends
with those histories of epistemological
ruptures and discontinuities in the work
of people like Bachelard and
Canguilhem [which is where
Althusser got his idea of an
epistemological break in Marx]. Their
history is not a simple one of
increasing rationality of concepts, but
one of different uses, rules of use, and
contexts. There are plural
networks of pasts, histories, and
teleologies, which can be traced
especially in various figures of breaks
from ideologies to sciences. The problem
really is to explain the continuity of
terms such as concepts or theories.
There is one underlying problem in both
sorts of history -- what is a document?
Is it a trace of a past trend, of
'unities, totalities, series, relations'
(page 7)? Or a prompt for some
collectively unconscious memory? History
can now be seen as a way to link
documents rather than relying on such a
memory, as an 'intrinsic description of
the monument', as archaeology. This
means that:
1.
It is much more open to
different notions of series and so on,
and suggested relationships between
series; it becomes a history of
strata, events. In the history of
thought, this leads to an
individualization of series rather
than some overall totality.
2.
Discontinuity is much
more important and should become
central to a deliberate method to
avoid reductionism.
Discontinuity should emerge as a
result of a proper investigation, as a
general problem which history should
illustrate. Once seen as an obstacle,
it now becomes a problem to be solved,
or a definite working concept.
3.
There is no total
history, no general underlying themes,
no eras. We should now pursue a search
for series and their possible
interrelationships, which can be
displayed as 'tables', with no central
principles.
4.
We need new
methodologies to manage documents.
Should we take representative samples,
or whole ‘corpora’? What level
of analysis should be pursued, should
it be quantitative or
qualitative? What groupings
should be studied, and what relations
exist between them -- causal ones,
functional ones or linguistic ones?
This sort of challenge to orthodox
history dates from Marx, but we are
still waiting for an explicit theorizing
of discontinuity, for example in
linguistics. Instead, we have long been
afraid of discontinuity, of the
Other (page 12). We have wanted to
preserve history as the last refuge for
the 'sovereignty of consciousness'
(page 12): it guarantees the project of
the subject, its ability to grasp the
past so as to avoid alienation in the
future. Marxist decentring has been
fought off, often by referring to
matters such as 'values' or
'civilisation', which are assumed to be
continuous. Nietzsche's notion of
genealogy has also been resisted, by
insisting that rationality is a central
principle [rather than some
arbitrary starting point developed
according to rather petty interests,
which is roughly Nietzsche's position].
Approaches such as those in structural
psychoanalysis, linguistics, or
ethnology which attempt to decentre the
subject have been resisted by developing
a notion of history as the 'hard work of
freedom', as a matter of dynamism
opposed to the stasis of structures (and
this includes the development of a
humanised marxism, page 13). The last
refuge of the subject can now only be
found in new 'myths, kinship systems,
language, sexuality or desire'
(page 14).
The project in this book is to do
history without such anthropology, and
also to systematise Foucault's earlier
work [specifically Madness... , Birth...,
and The Order of Things]. This
is allegedly pursued bottom-up, rather
than by importing a method, using
Foucault's own historical accounts [in
these books] as a basis, although they
are still too general (Madness)
or too structural (Birth).
Criticism from his colleagues has made
him aware of this, and so there is still
a need to be cautious. However, he is
still against those critical approaches
which seemed designed 'to reduce others
to silence' (page 17). Foucault
admits that his style can be vexing for
a reader [especially when he
indulges in strange imaginary dialogues
with the reader, as below], and he
enters a short digression on the
pleasures of writing:
'I am no
doubt not the only one who writes in
order to have no face. Do not ask who
I am and do not ask me to remain the
same: leave it to our bureaucrats and
our police to see that our papers are
in order. At least spare us their
morality when we write' (page
17).
Part 2
It is necessary to do some negative
analysis first, to deconstruct older
categories, including 'book', 'oeuvres',
genres and any [philosophical]
anthropological categories. We are
trying to get a set of discursive
'effective statements',which are not
just linguistic units but discursive
ones. Effective statements constitute a
large but finite field, which replaces
the idea of structural possibilities.
The issue here is not one of trying to
establish linguistic rules, but rather
asking 'How is it that one statement
appeared rather than another'
(page 27). This should lead to a
concrete, specific and descriptive
rather than an allegorical analysis of
things like films, theories or thoughts:
allegorical analysis always looks for
some other meaning in what is said, some
latent discourse. There is a need to
stress discontinuities,even though we
admit the possibility of a return to
more conventional unities at the end --
at least we will have denaturalised
these unities, however.There are good
empirical reasons for choosing the field
of the human sciences which can be seen
as 'groups of discourses', but only as
initial approximations.
What of the conventional disciplines?
These are seemingly based on identical
objects of inquiry, such as madness, but
does this mean that there is some common
space within which objects are
constituted? Such a notion would
help us begin to grasp divisions, and
dispersions of objects. A similar
argument might be developed about the
linguistic styles of discourses -- they
seem to have common vocabularies and
descriptive statements, as in medicine.
However, there is something deeper to be
investigated, a system which generates
such statements and rules of deployment,
so that we can investigate how these
discourses produce different concrete
and heterogeneous statements. We can
investigate for example 'ways they
interlock or exclude' each
other,how they 'transform', and the
'play of their location, arrangements
and replacement' (page 34). The aim is
not to devise a scheme to integrate
different concepts,but rather to
'analyse the interplay of their
appearances and dispersion' (page 35),
and the same goes for various organising
themes [as in sociological
perspectives?]. Again, there is constant
doubt about these themes, such as the
way they are articulated in different
concepts (page 36), or the way that
concepts are shared in discourses based
on different themes.
Discourses are specific because they're
always 'points of choice', in terms of
the different possibilities to animate
themes, develop strategies, or play
different games (page 37).
In this way, differences and
dispositions should not be seen as a
problem but as the raw materials of
analysis: they cannot be reduced or
managed, and they should not be ignored
in favour of generalisations from 'small
islands of coherence' (page38).
We should attempt to uncover 'discursive
formations'-- systems of dispersion,
regularities in choices -- rather than
operate with categories such as science
or ideology. We need to investigate
their rules of formation, their
conditions of existence. This is a
speculative venture and it could lead
either to the rediscovery of the older
genres, or ‘a blank, indifferent
space' (page 39).
How do the objects of the various
sciences emerge? [the example
here is psychopathology]. This often
happens against the context of other
objects found in other disciplines, and
involves processes working on those
objects, such as transformation,
resemblance, difference, proximity,
negation and soon. Various [usually
institutional] 'authorities' are able to
delimit this activity, using various
existing 'grids of specification'
(page42)-- which may involve familiar
categories such as the soul versus the
body, individual histories, whole
existing fields of causality and so
on.There are also various specific
connections, such as that between the
law and psychiatry [concretised in the
prison system]. If relations between
these concepts overlap then a discursive
formation can emerge. These are then
underpinned by 'institutions,economic
and social processes, behavioural
patterns, systems of norms, techniques,
types of classification, and modes of
characterisation' (page 45).
Certain' primary relations'
between institutions on their own may or
may not make discourses possible:
usually, secondary or reflexive
relations are necessary too as well as
discursive relations in their own right.
All this takes place before any naming,
classification or explanation, and it
clearly operates as a practice rather
than just a linguistic activity. These
practical processes provide the unity of
a discipline. How it happens is the
point of analysis, rather than political
criticisms of some of the consequences,
such as labelling certain people as mad.
We need to rescue the complexity
and density of discursive objects,
rather than trying to recapture
'things', which apparently exist
prior to discourse, to examine
discursive rather than linguistic rules,
to write a 'history of discursive
objects' (page 48). Discourses are
positive practices rather than just
connections between words and things.
Discursive objects have their own rules
of ordering, as 'practices that
systematically form the objects of which
they speak' (page 49).
The example of clinical discourse makes
this point. It consists of a complex
relation of descriptions, accounts,
explanations and reasonings which are
linked in various ways:
1.
By the status of the
doctor as a person legally entitled to
use clinical languages. This is itself
a complex matter, relating to other
statuses, obligations, systems of
qualification and so on which make it
quite specific.
2.
In institutional sites
for the doctor where clinical
discourse is applied -- the hospital,
the laboratory, the library, or a
documented field, all of which are
regulated, constraining or enabling in
different ways.
3.
In various positions
occupied by subjects, who have to
learn, use instruments, and occupy a
place in information networks. These
positions are complex and can change
or shift in status, according to their
location in hospitals, laboratories,
or books in the library. We see the
emergence of whole 'modalities of
enunciation' of the clinical
discourse (page 53).
Overall, the practice of clinical
discourse fixes the relations between
these elements. Such relations cannot be
reduced to logical successions of types
of diagnosis, for example, or to some
general consciousness which progresses,
or to a story of how actual doctors
shifted from traditional to clinical
modes.Modalities of enunciation disperse
the subject (there is no unified medical
gaze as in Birth...). Discourses
are not simply the expressions of some
subjective synthesis, but are better
seen as spaces, or networks of sites and
statuses.
General preconceptual discursive
rules produce specific concepts in a
discourse. These may be localised into
specific fields, such as linguistics, or
economics, but they are interconnected,
either at some higher levels or via a
certain 'concomitance’ [the relations
between, say, linguistics and cosmology
are connected in that they are both
general scientific ways of thinking].
These rules generates a variety of
sometimes conflicting concepts, hence
the appearance of dispersion, since they
are not strictly logical [a large
number of details are offered on pages
56-60]. There are some general types of
rules:
1.
Forms of succession,
governing how implications are
pursued, how descriptions are
progressively specified, how various
statements are combined for example in
rhetorical schemata, or
hypothetico-deductive mechanisms.
2.
Forms of co-existence
which include boundaries around
statements in a discourse's 'field of
presence', and which leave some
outside. There are also fields of
concomitance, including analogical
confirmations, general principles or
models, and disciplines which act as
higher authorities, such as
mathematics. Finally, there is a field
of memory, which consists of
traditions to which one expresses
relations of 'filiation,
genesis, transformation and
continuity' (page 58).
3.
Procedures of
intervention, which regulates
rewriting, transcribing or
translating (including
translating qualitative into
quantitative terms). These can assist
in refining statements, delimiting
them, according to the validity of
transference from one field to
another. They permit systematising
propositions.
Some of these rules are explicit, some
rhetorical, some internal and some
relational in terms of other texts, but
together they constitute a system to
generate concepts and statements and to
explain their dispersion in various
actual theories, as actual discourses.
Strategies also focus discourses, and
this can explain how different
discourses can appear from within the
same discursive formations. Strategies
consist of 'themes and
theories' (page 64) [they seem to
function rather as do 'research
programmes' for Lakatos]. Strategies
crystallise out from a number of
possibilities:
1.
As the effects of certain
'discursive constellations' which
provide models, general theories and
so on [very close to Kuhn's
notion of a paradigm here]. New
constellations provide new
possibilities for discursive
formations to become autonomous from
their existing constellations.
2.
From various kinds of
social authority. There are social
functions exercised by a strategy,
including pedagogic practice
[but only, apparently for those
grammarians discussed on page 68].
Discourses are appropriated by various
social groups in the familiar way, but
also form connections to 'possible
positions of desire': they may
become 'a place for phantasmic
representations, an element of
symbolization, a form of the
forbidden, an instrument of derived
satisfaction’ (page 68), not
only for poetic discourses but also
those referring to wealth, language,
nature, life, and madness.
Together, all these possibilities
explain the formation of individualised
discourses clustered around strategies.
There is the usual need to remember the
specificity of the level of discourses
-- these are not merely ideologies, or
even expressions, but have their own
effects, of transformation, and linking,
or enunciation [they seem to
transcend individual ideologies, which
appear here as rather vulgar variants?].
Strategies are just one interwoven
element, but an important one to remind
us that discourses are never
'pure' (page 70).
It is difficult to trace all the factors
that produce these unities, but the
point here is to make the case for the
unity of dispersed and concrete
discourses.This case relies on a
two-level analysis, operating at the
level of the system first and then
moving to actual discourses
[sociology and politics can be used to
explain the latter as a crystallisation
of the former]. The lower levels are
also effective in choosing concepts,
though:the discursive level should not
be seen as dominated by determinant from
outside, and a discursive formation acts
merely as a link between discrete series
of discourses. This view opposes the
usual forms of analysis which are
typically one sided. The pre- systematic
and the pre-discursive are still
important 'Discourse and system
produce each other -- and conjointly--
only at the cost of this immense
reserve' (page 76). The
pre-discursive level is itself still
discursive, however, not some more
primitive underlying 'life' or 'being'
--'One remains within the dimension of
discourse' (page 76). [This whole
section seems to me to be in deep
trouble. I'm not sure if this is
sophistication or evasion of a
well-known problem. Discursive analysis
looks abstract and idealist, and
Foucault tries to avoid this by
introducing a major role for some
materialist 'pre-discursive' level, and
for practice and specific history -- yet
these factors cannot be grasped except
as discourses too!].
Part 3
Let us return to the issue of statements
rather than concepts as some kind of
basic unit of analysis. These
focus our attention on ‘enunciative
characteristics' (page 81) rather
than some logical or linguistic
structure.This helps us to analyse 'what
occurred by the very fact that the
statement was made in specific
circumstances' (page 83).[A
lengthy debate ensues examining the
claims of rival linguistic units such as
speech acts, propositions or sentences
-- pages 82-84]. Statement should
be seen as signs that make sense, as
functions such as the enunciative
function:
1.
Which is apparently not
reducible to mere linguistic
qualities, not just a matterof the
relations between signifiers and
signified, or proposition and
referent. [There is a great deal
of dense reasoning here, and swathes
of typically ‘philosophical’ argument,
often ultimately appealing to ‘common
sense’. I may not have understood a
word of it]. Social contexts are
crucial. Enunciation does not just
depend on meanings derived from
linguistic rules or logical truths,
but refer to much broader
'referentials', such as 'laws of
possibility' (page 91). The
relation between an enunciative
statement and its referential is not
logical or empirical either, but
should be seen as an internal relation
between the statement and its 'spaces
of differentiation' (page 92) [I
don't know what this means].
2.
It also has a
special relation with its
[human] subject
: statements do not simply convey the
privileged meanings of their author.
For example there might be some
special, anonymous, all-seeing subject
uttering statements, as in the
narrator of a [realist] novel. The
subject becomes a function rather than
a concrete individual, although
sometimes this function is so specific
that there can only be one
[bearer], such as the author of a
scientific innovation. Compare this
level of specificity with the
anonymous empty function of the
addressee in the simple maths
text (page 94).
3.
The relation of the statement to
its domain is a necessary one,
moving beyond the functions of
isolated sentences. We should not just
see this as a matter of some
determining context, since this
relation makes a context possible, by
operating in fictional or scientific
domains, for example (page 98). There
is an 'associated field', provided by
other elements, such as those provided
in a conversation or a demonstration,
a number of quite implicit references,
a set of implications which follow,
and a set of statements to which this
one belongs (marking it as
literature or science and so on).
These statements emerge from whole
metacontexts, or 'enuciative
fields' (page 99) This field,
and the enunciative function itself,
is therefore prior to the formation of
actual sentences or propositions, and
thus also prior to structural or
logical analysis.
4.
Analysis must be
material, since the form that a
statement takes, whether written or
spoken, for example, has a
material effect and an historical
location . Such statements are
constitutive, and should not be seen
simply as a variation from some
imaginary pure sentence. They exhibit
both specific and universal qualities,
as can be seen from difficulties that
arise in use, for example when a
statement is repeated. Their material
existence in institutions produce
definite possibilities of
reinscription and transcription, but
also constraints (page 103)
[Overall then, we seem to have some
strong arguments to distinguish
Foucault's formulation from his rivals
and to maintain his peculiar definitions
and so on. He claims that this will
enable us to examine matters such as
‘circulation, use, disappearance,
recognition, and various tactical
appropriations' of such statements
(page 105). As an example of his
appalling style,with which I have
struggled manfully, try the following:
'Should
we say similarly that the statement
refers to nothing of the proposition,
to which it owes its existence, has no
referent? Rather the reverse. We
should say not that the absence of a
referent brings with it the absence of
a correlate for the statement but that
it is the correlate of the statement
-- that to which it refers, not only
what is said, but also what it speaks
of, its "theme" -- which makes it
possible to say whether or not the
proposition has a referent: it alone
decides this in a definitive
way' (pages 89-90).
Aren't you glad I'm here? You thought my
stuff was bullshit?]
So we need to examine operational fields
rather than any kind of 'atom'. Foucault
admits that his use of the term
discourse has been ambiguous up to now,
referring to a group of verbal
performances, and acts of
formulation,and a collection of
statements. We can make use of
these three definitions as stages to
explain both continuity and dispersion,
and we should end up with the final
definition of discourse as 'the group of
statements that belong to a single
system of formation' (page 107),
hence clinical discourses, economic
discourses and so on. The point is
that relations are always implied in a
discourse, relations to objects, via the
offer of a number of subject positions
to other elements in a field, and to
material institutions.This solves some
problems but it is now not so easy to
isolate statements which do not function
like sentences.
Foucault is keen to deny that he wants
to reveal hidden meanings behind
discourses, and says he wants to perform
an historical analysis of emergence. One
way to begin this is to see discourses
as polysemic where some possible
meanings have been repressed but there
are other analyses too, and this one
operates at a secondary level
(page 110). Repression of this kind
still depends on enunciation in the
first place -- first you have to
describe the enunciative field itself,
and only then can you go on to analyse
the suspicious lack of alternatives
found in concrete discourses. A
preliminary investigation is required of
statements before utterances are
actually 'solidified'. Some
description of an enunciative field is
always implied in specific analyses of
works and texts. Analysis of
sentences is only possible after
sentences have emerged in the domain of
enunciation: sentences do not emerge
directly from some 'primeval night
of silence' (page 112), and they
all contain residual elements from this
domain. This transcendental level cannot
itself be reduced to some simple source
by materialist or humanist analysis.
How does all this relate to the earlier
work? Foucault undertook his archaeology
in order to try and regularise his
insights and proceed 'without flaw,
without contradiction, without internal
arbitrariness' (page 114) [ a
typically scholastic agenda]. The point
was only to establish a possibility, and
not to found a full theory. The point
was to see how statements were linked in
a discourse, not sentences with
linguistic rules, nor propositions with
logical ones, nor formulations with
psychological rules (page 115). So
what were the rules are to describe
various relations, like those between
subject positions and domains? How were
they institutionalised and actually
used?
The search for rules led him to the
notion of a discursive formation
.There seemed to be 4 aspects of such a
formation -- the formation of objects,
concepts, subject positions and
strategic choices. These correspond to
the 4 domains of the enunciative
function outlined above. Together they
provide a number of possibilities to
explain both continuity and dispersions,
at both the general and individual
level.
Another definition of discourse follows:
'a group of statements in so far as they
belong to a discursive formation', and
this is contrasted to some ideal form
that mutates over time. Discursive
practice now becomes a body of rules for
the operation of the specific
enunciative function (page 117).
The result is a triumph for his analysis
of 'concentric circles', going out to
discourse and in to statements. There
are clear dangers of tautology, though.
Discourses refer both to some totality,
some 'great, uniform text' expressed in
lots of specific ones (including
institutions), and to open possibilities
of plural meanings, since 'each
discourse has the power to say... other
than what it actually says' (page
118). The real interest lies in how
particular enunciations arise:
1.
There is a ‘law of
rarity' (page 118), which yields
a 'distribution of gaps, voids leads,
absences are, limits, divisions'
(page 119). This does not depend on
some hidden process of repression,
however, there is no depth mechanism:
we are describing a process of
localisation. Rare statements are
reworked, duplicated, extended,
translated, and commented upon, and
then those products themselves
generate new meanings. There is an
inherent political struggle here,
since statements are seen as assets to
be struggled over. This is in stark
contrast to the idea that there is an
infinite wealth of meaning available
in cultural traditions, as in
hermeneutics.
2.
There is systematic
exteriority, in contrast to the usual
view of interpretation which tries to
move from external traces to internal
meanings. This involves a view of the
'practical domain' as autonomous
rather than as a trace, as a
configuration of anonymous fields
rather than as the acts of the
subject. There is no cogito,
no speaking subject, and no collective
consciousness behind the 'totality of
things said' (122).
3.
Accumulation of
statements takes place not in a memory
or in some primary collection of
documents, both of which imply some
notion of origin, but as the results
of the history of how the statements
were established, used, forgotten or
destroyed, and how they have
accumulated through specific forms and
processes: subjective memory and the
repression of it 'are merely unique
figures' in this history (124)
So we must avoid any simple notions of a
return to origins, and deny any
teleology. Instead, we must establish a
'positivity'. [Foucault flirts with this
term here, saying he will accept he is a
positivist if that means abandoning the
transcendental level of analysis -- page
125].
This is a descriptive task, focusing on
concrete unities rather than underlying
truths, operating somewhere between a
science and an oeuvre. This leads to a
necessary 'historical a priori'
(127), as a 'condition of reality for
statements' (128) [I think this
means that we are going to privilege
history, albeit specific histories, when
we try to explain the generation of
statements]. Discourses can relate to
this condition of reality in different
ways, and we need to tell the story of
'points of contact, places of insertion,
irruption or emergence, domains or
occasions of operation' (128). These
events are not just contingent
connections. Systems of statements,in
all their dispersion, produce archives,
and these in turn produce regularities.
Archives offer a 'law of what can be
said' (129). They provide rules to
group statements, systems to enable
enunciation and preserve the differences
between discourses which make them
specific. Archives operate between some
general system of language and the
concrete corpus of actual works, and
guide the practice that generates, forms
and transforms statements. [We are
talking about a kind of virtual archive
here, not an actual collection of
documents]. An archive can never be
fully described, and it appears only in
fragmentary form. It has a real effect,
though, in limiting our activities and
our analyses. The archive alludes
to discontinuity and difference rather
than underlying unity [because it
is a mere collection of
approaches?]. Thus difference is
at the centre of reason, history, and
ourselves. Archaeology is therefore the
correct process to use, instead of some
search for an origin. Archaeology is 'a
description that questions the
already-said at the level of its
existence: of the enunciative function,
of the discursive formation, and the
general archive system to which it
belongs. Archaeology describes
discourses as practices specified in the
elements of the archive' (131).
Part 4
What can archaeology actually
offer [Foucault offers some
delightfully modest self doubt on pages
135-7]. It needs to separate itself from
the history of ideas. This is far too
sloppy, concerning itself with
'shapeless works' and 'unrelated
themes'. Archaeology tries to show
how the disciplines emerge, how their
boundaries are constituted, and how
concepts diffuse. It is also interested
in 'interdiscursive
configurations' too, which are
usually called epistemological
generalities.
Foucault admits that his own earlier
work is limited. For example, he decided
deliberately not to explore concepts
such as zeitgeist
[spirit of the age] or weltanschauung
[collective world view], but admits that
he did so on principle, rather than
following an investigation. He denies
that his concepts here are claiming some
privilege, and insists that they
represent only one possibility [so
they are arbitrary?] (159). He
asks his readers to undertake 'the test
of analysis' [some naive
pragmatism?].
Archaeology is 'not a science, a
rationality a mentality a culture'
[with 'a' emphasised each time]
(159). It offers a comparative analysis
designed to show diversity [But
why is diversity so important?].'What
archaeology wishes to uncover is
primarily... the play of analogies and
differences' (160), to show:
1.
Archaeological
isomorphisms [things of similar shape]
between different discursive elements
at the level of rules.
2.
How these rules operate
to produce different formations
3.
How different concepts are endowed
with significance and shaped by
archives,and occupy similar
positions (161)
4.
How a single notion can
cover two archaeologically distinct
elements [to expose hidden
contradictions?]
5.
How 'relations of
subordination or complementarity...
[are] established' (161) The
issue is to find what makes these
possible rather than how they have
actually occurred [some strange
notion of practice without a subject?]
6.
How ‘configurations of
interpositivity' form, which is
a fancy way of referring to the law of
communication between discourses.
Exploring relations between discourses
and formations, and non-discursive
domains [But isn't everything
discourse?] leads to an interest in
'institutions, political events,
economic practices and processes'
(162). This should be descriptive
rather than an attempt to interpret or
describe causality: 'symbolic analysis',
or 'causal analysis' of things
like medical discourse offers merely a
series of ‘readings’. Foucault wants
something more fundamental, how
political or economic factors 'take part
in the conditions of emergence,
insertion and functioning' of a
discourse (163). How might they
delimit objects? For example, political
developments led to new issues for
medicine, such as the need to control
conscript armies. Another issue concerns
how the status of the doctor emerged,
and what functions were ascribed to
medical discourses in the managements of
various conflicts among the
professionals.It is not a matter of how
politics influences medical concepts or
theoretical structures, but more to do
with how 'medical discourse as a
practice... [was]...articulated on to
practices that are external to it, and
which are not themselves of a discursive
order' (164). [OK,but this seems
like a very abstract and scholastic
project to me, despite all the emphasis
on practice. The project of showing how
politics influences medical concepts
seems far more interesting and
relevant!]
Does archaeology freeze history?
Foucault denies the relevance of simple
chronologies,but not the effects of
time. He does describe articulations
over time, such as how things become
operationalised in to statements, or how
the mobility of discourses takes place,
but these are not just driven by events:
on the contrary, the relation to events
varies according to particular
discourses at work (168).. There
is a sense of succession or
development,but this is not always
chronological. Time is never a simple
determinant, according to some 'original
calendar', usually based on linear
speech and the stream of consciousness.
There is a need to undo simple histories
and expose all the glosses which cover
over differences. There are different
types of differences anyway, such as
primary ones, localised versus
general,or transforming.
Foucault wants to deny that
transformations are authored or
caused, both of which reduce specificity
by deploying some single notion such as
the 'living force of change'.
Transformations can be uneven, are
seldom revolutionary and complete, and
these continuities are also of interest
[which denies the notion of a simple
tradition]. The idea of an 'active
continuousness' (174) is used to
deny a view of history as a series of
eras or watersheds. Discourses vary in
their reactions to temporality [which
leads to an interesting aside on the
epistemological break in marxism.
Foucault says there are different
notions of epistemological breaks as
well, and different effects -- compare
the one inaugurated when Marx broke with
Ricardo to the one identified by
Althusser between the early and late
works of Marx].
Archaeology seems to apply to Foucault's
own limited examples, but what of any
wider implications? What about natural
science? Archaeology is not about
specific disciplines as such, but about
positivities, and discursive formations
are not the same as established
disciplines either. Discursive
formations are ‘larger’ and more general
than individual disciplines, and can be
shared between them, as is psychiatry
and law in Madness...
Discursive practices also preceded
disciplines, and are manifested in other
sites as well. However positivities
sometimes do turn into sciences, and
discursive practices sometimes do act as
proto-disciplines.
Positivities are not forms of knowledge
nor just a collection of acceptable
knowledges, but are the effects of
discursive rules. They are not
necessarily sciences. Rules are not just
prototypes or some archaic stage of a
discipline. They are best thought of as
knowledge itself ['in general',
one might think?], produced by a
disciplinary practice, a space for
subject positions, a ‘field of
co-ordination and subordination of
statements in which concepts
appear' (182), a set of relations
of use and appropriation [Do you
find any of these stylish but flatulent
metaphors of any use?]. These practices,
spaces, fields or sets can be
independent of specific sciences, but
not of discourse.
It might be possible to see sciences as
a selection from knowledge, operating
with rather stricter criteria?
Archaeology explores territories beyond
scientific domains, such as those shared
by literature and philosophy. So how
does science emerge?
1.
It is a selection from
knowledge, a local region in
knowledge. Its boundaries vary as an
effective discursive formations. The
function of science is the important
issue rather than the science/ideology
issue [which Althusser had made
central]. Turning to that [rather
hastily I thought], science and
ideology share features as discursive
practices. There is no sharp
distinction between them, but the
level of discursive formation is
decisive. Whether one uses causal
explanations is irrelevant, and it is
not just a matter of rigour. [Having
disposed of that], the ideological
role of science is established by
looking at 'the system of formation of
its objects, its types of enunciation,
its concepts, its theoretical
choices' (186). [So a great deal
of wriggling must take place here.
Both science and ideology are
discourses, but we do not want to let
anyone say that therefore they are of
equal value -- we have not yet got to
post-modernism. So we assert some
differences, and claim they are
important. But this is really very
near the end of the book, and we have
not mentioned these crucial
differences before but have stayed at
a very general and abstract level
indeed. By the time we have got to
these crucial specific differences, we
have done enough theorizing and there
is time and space enough only to jot
down a few remarks].
2.
Discursive forms emerge
first as positivities [practices
become autonomous and systematised
first?]. Then there is a stage on the
'threshold of epistemologisation',
when norms are clarified and begin to
function as a model. Then formal
criteria and logical explicitness
develop,on the 'threshold of
scientificity'. Further definitions of
axioms, propositions,and rules of
transformation leave us on the
threshold of 'formalisation' (187).
The way these develop and interlock
can vary: there are no neat
periodisations, and stages 1 and 2 can
be mixed, for example. Mathematics
seems to have crossed all the
thresholds at once, which is why it is
often taken as a model for the
development of a discipline.
3.
So distinct histories are
possible. There can be a history of
formalisation, and one of
scientificity. [Bachelard and
Canguilhem are much admired here].
Such histories are often situated
within science itself, and thus tend
to be saturated with terms like truth
and error, rational and non rational.
A history can stop at the stage of
epistemologisation -- not all
discursive formations lead to
sciences.
4.
Analysing the dynamics
within discursive formations and
positivities leads to an analysis of
the episteme itself, the
‘relations that unite... the
discursive practices that give rise to
epistemological figures, sciences
and... formalised systems'
(191). These affect the different
thresholds and the paths between
them. An episteme is more than a
form of knowledge or type of
rationality, but is best seen as an
'indefinite field of relations',
including relations with other fields.
This varies over time. It gives the
right to be a science, not as a
one-off gift, but as an historical
practice again.
Is archaeology right to focus on this episteme?
Other kinds of archaeology are possible:
do we need, say, an archaeology of
sexuality which would involve not
only the science of sexuality, but also
a field of possible enunciations in its
own right? Should we not be
oriented to ethical rather than
epistemic issues? What about political
knowledge? Foucault says that he is
interested in the emergence of sciences
in particular for several reasons --
because they are emerging strongly these
days, because it is an important
political task to criticise science, but
principally because they demonstrate
best the points about positivity.
Conclusion
This offers one of those dialogues, in
which Foucault replies to some imaginary
questions:
Do we need,
concepts rather than structuralist
analysis? Surely concepts like langue
and parole would deal with the issue of
how specific discourses arise?
Discourses seem to be very context
bound: surely they express the relations
between real successive events?
Analysing discourses reveal their
identity and diversity, and there are a
number of ways to grasp them, as well as
using structural and interpretative
approaches. The intention here is to
reveal [micropolitical] possibilities.
Surely we
cannot do without teleology and
subjectivity as unifying
themes? Some discourses, such as
structuralism, are already capable of
generalising about other discourses.
Surely current theoretical practice is
immune from charges of historical
specificity?
Some sort of break from ideology into
science seems to be promised here, with
an implicit view that new forms of
reason are transcendental. I aimed to
analyse the past to exhibit irreducible
discontinuity and dispersion, the
impossibility of transcendentalism.
Attempts to deny this application to the
present stem from a desire to defend the
consciousness of the subject, and there
are elements of special pleading
[a number of attacks against his
Archaeology are summarised, page 204],
and a hint that this debate is all about
boundary maintenance.
What
legitimates Foucault's
discourse? Is he offering a naively
positivist description? Is it all
subjective? 'Either [your
discourse] does not reach us, or we
claim it' (page 205). Is it
history or philosophy?
There is no attempt to find some hidden
law in discourses. There is a genuine
attempt to describe dispersion and
decentring, to make differences,
constitute new theoretical objects. This
is neither history nor philosophy.
It is not
science either! The claims made are
still in their infancy. The project
tends to define what it is not, always
postponing systematisation, always
claiming to be a new research programme.
Isn't it likely to die with its author?
This project is a survey of concrete
research rather than a scientific plan,
although it is related to science [via
the reconstruction of the sciences it
analyses?] It is scientific in that it
is interested in performance [politics?]
rather than mere linguistic competence.
Sciences are seen as possibilities
within this overall archaeology,
'correlative spaces' (page 207),
although we might find a general theory
of productions eventually. The project
aims to occupy a specific domain, which
could be unstable: the problems could be
better grasped by some other discipline;
it could be a false start; it could die
with the author.
While
arguing that all other discourses are
constrained, are you not claiming a
revolutionary freedom for yourself?
Positivities should not be seen as
closed forms of determination. Instead
they constitute a field, a set of rules,
relations or supports. They describe
pragmatics rather than logics.
Discourses should be seen as practices
rather than just linguistic expressions.
Discourses can change, but not only via
subjects.Notions like evolution or
essentialism deny the impact of
political changes,and see discourses as
transparent bearers of subjective
meanings.This is a pleasurable view, and
we like to think of ourselves as
subjects.It is irritating to have to
deconstruct instead. It is also nice to
want to banish death via discourse
(page 210) -- if there is no interior, is
everything else indifferent? There
is no real response to this except
sympathy!
back to social
theory page
|