Notes on: Richardson, T.
(2015) Indigenous Methodologies and
Educational Research for Meaningful Change:
Parsing Postpositivist Philosophy of Science and
Mixed Methods in the Collaborative Research
Settings. Journal of American Indian
Education, Vol. 54, No. 1 (Spring 2015),
pp. 33-62 .
Dave Harris
Place, language and narrative seem to be the
principal elements but there are different facets.
postpositivism and mixed methods may offer an
alternative way to offer meaningful interventions.
[Lots of references exist on page 33, including L
Smith]. The intention is to combat indigenous
knowledge as prescientific. Qualitative research,
say in Denzin and Lincoln, and feminist research
have led to further discussions of indigenous
epistemology and methodology. These has always
been linked to indigenous self-determination, and
the need to conform to indigenous ethics and
philosophies, authentic and thus different
methods. This led in turn to a discussion about
how they differ, and the usual list:
'understanding principles of relationality and
reciprocity, deep attentiveness to place,
engagement with specific Native narrative
traditions et cetera' (36), although some have
argued that seeing method as a tool only, any
method can be used. Others have stressed the need
for links with intellectual traditions leading to
story work or conversational methods as crucial.
One example cited here has two approaches one from
the worldview of indigenous methodologies, and one
from a more conventional one — a mixed
methodology.
There are obvious problems in generalising, but
this seems to be a consensus on 'the broad
characteristics of indigenous methodologies'
especially in the North American and Pacific
contexts. This seems to be an agreement that the
activities involved are 'empirical, tactile,
emotional, regulatory and most often narratively
organised' (37). The methods may also centre on
place, 'intimate interactions with specific lands
and waters' (38) [there is a claim that they have
been tested over the generations and thus 'proven
reliable']. Together, this shows the importance of
relationality, ties to place and community, social
relations which reflect these ties and extend them
to generations [the examples chosen here are
Native Americans]. The self emerges as a relation
as well, and it fosters 'reciprocity and
non-domination'.
Relationality guides the aims and practices of
research as well, because it entails
responsibilities to community and land, even a
kind of healing, 'an attentiveness to one's
actions, approach and efforts as a researcher'.
There is often a ceremonial dimension. Dreams may
be important as a source of knowledge, as might
other kinds of revelation: these or serve
ceremonial dimension.
Storytelling can show all these elements, as
relational or 'synergistic', offering both power
and knowledge as people are brought together.
There is a 'highly ethical character' (40), often
based on kinship duties [which could also be seen
as a constraint?]. There is an emphasis on process
rather than outcome.
The emphasis is on local rather than global, as in
LT Smith [who goes on to argue that the global
focus is characteristic of positivism]. Wilson has
seen some continuities with indigenous methodology
and postpositivism, although both share the goal
of pursuing knowledge for its own sake, or
discovering truth, leading to prediction and
control. This is the definition taken here. One
example is research from the American
Psychological Association which talks of rigorous
systematic and objective procedures based on
observation and experiment, and objective data.
This is apparently Postpositivist [!] [Because it
is pragmatic and procedural rather than
philosophically committed?]. Scientism is
Eurocentric.
Philosophers of science might disagree with social
scientists, and actual researchers in proper
sciences. For them, this is too narrow a
methodology and they currently welcome
'historical, philosophical, ethnographic and mixed
methodological approaches'(43). This is more
promising for links with indigenous
self-determination. One particular philosopher of
science, Phillips, has opposed the definition of
science supported by US politicians as far too
narrow, enshrining RCT, for example.
Phillips argues that philosophers have a new
understanding of positivism but they do not wish
to return to it. He saw Comte as foundational, and
Mill, Mach and Dewey. The Vienna Circle developed
the philosophical positions best — '(1) a
"hostility towards metaphysics"; (2) the
verifiability principle… "Something is meaningful
if and only if it is verifiable empirically or is
a tautology of mathematics or logic"; that the
verifiability "had to be in terms of simple "rock
bottom" direct and indisputable descriptions of
sense experience"; (4) that the logical
positivists "often took a non-realist stance'
(44-45). It is a mistake to see this as the same
as behaviourism or empiricism.
Popper did not want to totally dismiss metaphysics
as meaningless, but he did see science as offering
testable statements. Some scientific research
programs may indeed be based on principles that
are not subject to empirical refutation, so
science can never be free of metaphysics, and
these forms of knowledge still provide meaning
[important in making this stance Postpositivist].
Verifiability never worked because so many
entities are unverifiable [what about
falsification?] like those in nuclear physics or
those in human processes — they can be no rock
bottom sense experience descriptions of them
either. [But what about 'basic statements'
ultimately related to them] [apparently this
difficulty led to the rejection of realism in
logical positivism — I can see that it would lead
to problems of specifying universal laws because
not all of them could be verified. Presumably,
they relied on induction?]. Positivists remain as
a kind of convenient ghost, however.
Postpositivism for Phillips sees researchers as
fallible, a matter of 'viable warrants or chains
of argument' drawing upon 'diverse bodies of
evidence' offering general support. He implies
that different sorts of evidence are better if
they can be welded into a coherent case. He also
refers to 'quality evidence' [which is?] [NB he
has the term warrant here]. He seems to support
Dewey who sees science as the extension of normal
problem-solving, not the pursuit of some ultimate
reality. He fully accepts that scientific research
might be based on metaphysical assumptions or
something like them, and that it also operates as
rhetoric in the classical sense [presumably as a
way of persuading people to adopt a worldview] [he
nearly gets to Habermas on the well formed
argument?]. So language is important and
communication is for action. [It all looks pretty
pragmatic to me, and assumes that progress is
possible and good].
Indigenous researchers should be cautious but
should engage and look for points of
complementarity. They should share an interest in
effective communication. Some already do and he
has some examples from Maori.
Bishop sees scientific research as 'the
development of warrantable assertions' (48) he
wanted to improve relations between teachers and
Maori students, trying to see if there was a
change in teacher practice after professional
development, not in the form of a correlation but
in the form of a warrantable assertion. He used
evidence from a number of sources and methods
including statistical analysis and interviews, but
also indigenous methodologies such as cultural
meetings discussing 'gifts' provided by visitors
which then oblige them to reciprocate, in the form
of data. They exercise rights and responsibilities
through traditional notions of relationship and
join a community, a kind of family. Bishop
describes what happens both in terms of
traditional Maori terms and as mixed methodologies
in postpositivism. He does think that he has
provided warrantable descriptions of what
developed. Gifting and exchange seems to be
crucial extending to the exchange of knowledge and
the responsibility for it, providing argument and
data which involved Maori as academic researchers.
It is debatable whether this just anticipates
indigenous customs or whether it is more
ambiguous: it might even be an expression of new
possibilities of colonialism (51).
In another example on Alaskan natives mathematics
education in a locally-based community curriculum
was developed, working with local elders and
teachers building on '"everyday indigenous
subsistence activities"' (52). Insiders and
outsifers collaborated — indigenous knowledge was
still kept separate, but articulations were
sought, a bridge between elders' knowledge and
mathematics, especially 'rational number thinking,
symmetry, algebraic equality'. Every day practices
included 'Equipartitioning' which led to concepts
such as fractions ratios and proportions [seems
old hat to me]. Classroom tests and assessments
were modified, in order to demonstrate positive
learning outcomes that paid off both in the
everyday world and in assessment for grades. They
claimed that working with example such as salmon
fishing helped to develop rational number
reasoning more effectively. They fully embraced
'the postpositivist fallibility principle' and
made frequent changes. [A cynic would also say
that they did quite a bit of coaching, in the
guise of item analysis and ensuring questions were
interpreted correctly].
There is a clear link between postpositivism and
the pragmatic practices of indigenous peoples, and
claiming them as mixed methodologies can disrupt
conservative agendas as long as definitions of
research rigour are accepted.
Turning to more focused studies of indigenous
methods, Hermes undertook some research on
indigenous Native American youth enduring poverty.
They criticised the abundance of workshops on
culture in the curriculum, sponsored by academics!
Material conditions could have been examined from
an indigenous perspective, however, and Hermes
attempted to do so in a way that was consistent
with native oral traditions and narrative methods.
She started with economic disadvantages and the
recognition that they disrupted school, more than
cultural differences. She noted that some
indigenous parents had made special efforts to
increase school attendance and to focus upon '"low
socio-economic status and a myriad related
issues"' (56). There was a strong emphasis on past
colonialism and dispossession. [There is a strange
running commentary on how all this relates to
Williams and the Birmingham school — Hermes claims
to have discovered the material components
independently, but Robinson is a bit sceptical]
He claims to have justified the inclusion of
indigenous methods as playing an important part,
even though they must be combined in mixed
methodologies, and generally embraced within
postpositivism.
Indigenous people themselves might approach the
issues differently. It might be best to explore
research questions in different ways, at the level
of funding agencies as well. They might consider a
twin study conducted by indigenous scholars as
well as official ones. They might share databases.
At the same time, courses might be offered for
indigenous researchers on matters such as managing
official datasets. Beneath this, the whole
political and legal relationship between
indigenous people and federal and state government
needs to be examined as relevant to research —
this context matters as well.
There needs to be a particular focus on the
'material economic conditions' [about time too],
and the local capacity to relate. There is no need
to preserve 'the federally defined "gold standard"
of research' (59), nor is there any need to
condemn in a blanket manner science. Postpositivism
is required, with a full explanation of the range
and variation of methods available. Qualitative
research including experiences of indigenous
people must be included. Mixed methods studies
should become the norm.
|
|