READING
GUIDE TO: Latour, B
(1987) Science in Action, Milton
Keynes: Open University Press
Dave Harris
Two
useful
appendices summarize the approach: (scan
of pp 258, 259 of Latour)
APPENDIX
1 Rules of Method
Rule
1 We study
science in action and not ready made
science or technology;
to do so, we either arrive before the facts
and machines are blackboxed
or we
follow the controversies that reopen them.
(Introduction)
Rule
2 To determine the
objectivity or
subjectivity of a claim, the efficiency or
perfection of a mechanism,
we do not
look for their intrinsic
qualities
but at all the transformations they undergo later
in the hands of others. (Chapter 1)
Rule
3 Since the settlement
of a
controversy is the cause of Nature's
representation, not its
consequence, we
can never use this consequence, Nature, to
explain how and why a
controversy
has been settled. (Chapter 2)
Rule
4 Since the settlement
of a
controversy is the cause of Society's
stability, we cannot use Society
to
explain how and why a controversy has been
settled. We should consider
symmetrically the efforts to enrol human and
non-human resources.
(Chapter 3)
Rule
5 We have to be as undecided
as the various actors we
follow as to what technoscience is made of;
every time an
inside/outside divide
is built, we should study the two sides
simultaneously and make the
list, no
matter how long and heterogeneous, of those
who do the work. (Chapter 4)
Rule
6 Confronted with the
accusation
of irrationality, we look neither at what rule
of logic has been
broken, nor at
what structure of society could explain the
distortion, but to the
angle and
direction of the observer's displacement,
and to the length of the
network thus
being built. (Chapter 5)
Rule
7 Before attributing
any special
quality to the mind or to the method of
people, let us examine first
the many
ways through which inscriptions are gathered,
combined, tied together
and sent
back. Only if there is something unexplained
once the networks have
been
studied shall we start to speak of cognitive
factors. (Chapter 6)
APPENDIX
2 Principles
First
principle The fate of
facts and machines is in
later users'
hands; their qualities are thus a consequence,
not a cause, of a
collective
action. (Chapter 1)
Second
principle Scientists
and engineers
speak in the name of new allies that they have
shaped and enrolled;
representatives
among other representatives, they add these
unexpected resources
to tip the
balance of force in their favour. (Chapter 2)
Third
principle We are never
confronted
with science, technology and society, but with
a gamut of weaker and
stronger
associations; thus understanding what
facts and machines are is the same task as
understanding who
the people are. (Chapter 3)
Fourth
principle The more
science and
technology have an esoteric content the
further they extend outside;
thus,
`science and technology' is only a subset of
technoscience.
(Chapter 4)
Fifth
principle Irrationality
is always
an accusation made by someone building a
network over someone else who
stands
in the way; thus, there is no Great Divide
between minds, but only
shorter and
longer networks; harder facts are not the rule
but the exception, since
they
are needed only in a very few cases to
displace others on a large scale
out of
their usual ways. (Chapter 5)
Sixth
principle History of
technoscience
is in a large part the history of the
resources scattered along
networks to
accelerate the mobility, faithfulness,
combination and cohesion of
traces that
make action at a distance possible. (Chapter
6)
My
commentary:
Rules
of
Method
Rule
one It is science in action that is
studied, before things are solidified and black
boxed. The idea is to
trace the
acceptance of initial conclusions and
propositions as fact, either by
doing
history, or by reopening controversies. The
examples in Chapter 1
include the
tentative steps leading up to the acceptance of
the double helix model
of DNA.
The uncertainties and contingencies included not
only the decision to
share
knowledge with other teams, but also a very
interesting case where the
alternative model of Linus Pauling was examined.
At first it looked as
if the
Pauling model would triumph, since it emerged
from a world-famous
scientist and
a large laboratory, whereas Watson and Crick
were not really supposed
to be
working on the structure of DNA
at
all
. Watson and Crick
found the confidence
from somewhere to examine his model critically
and found some errors --
unbelievably. This spurred them on to continue
with their model and
also to
rush to solve the remaining problems before
Pauling discovered his
mistake. The
other example turns on the eventual emergence of
a particular kind of
personal
computer, with an number of competing interests,
including rival
companies and skeptics
within the company, who had to be persuaded that
the new model would
work.
Finally, almost accidentally, the last few major
bugs were fixed
sufficiently
for the new model to play a game, which
convinced the skeptics. Modern
scientists, working in the 1980s simply took for
granted that Watson
and
Crick's model was an accurate one, and that the
computer they were
using to
display the model was reliable -- both a model
and the computer had
been black
boxed.
Rule two.
It is not so much the
intrinsic logical or deductive qualities other
scientific claim that
means it
gets accepted, but the 'transformations they
undergo later in hands of
others'
(258)[ same as the specialist term? see below] .
The examples in
Chapter 2
consist of a marvellously detailed analysis of
the argumentative twists
and
turns associated with original scientific
claims, especially one that
claims to
have discovered a particular hormone associated
with human growth.
Latour
traces the complex interweaving of claims and
counter-claims, ways of
attacking
counter-claims, further ways of gaining support
for original claims and
so on. Additional
references play a major part in this struggle,
as do various kinds of
presentations of data, which themselves may lead
to further
controversies,
claims and counter-claims.
In
the
end, a successful claim is buttressed by whole
arrays of supporting
resources, and a complex stratified structure of
argument. Some
excellent
examples are given of processes referred to as
'stacking' - an
interesting
practical version of induction, where some
observations of biological
specimens
are stacked to lead to conclusions about entire
species (see 51);
'staging and
framing' -- where ideal readers and their
possible objections are
addressed and
persuaded; 'captation'-- a way of steering
obstinate readers towards
particular conclusions by leading them down
various argumentative
routes.
The
whole
process might well be described as 'fact
writing', essentially
the same
process as fiction writing but with more limited
options. Ultimately,
only a
few people are left to thoroughly arbitrate the
claims, most possible
critics
or dissenters would have given up or gone along
with the argument. Of
course,
lots of texts are never even read at all.
Scientific writing is another
kind of
rhetoric, more admired because of its
dispassionate style, and able to
'mobilize
on one spot more resources than
[its
rivals]' (61). Because facticity and objectivity
depend on connections
with
other resources, Latour argues that successful
science is 'extremely'
social (62). It is
these connections to
authorities, experiments, definitions and
previous work that makes it
almost
impossible to disagree with a successful claim.
[Is there a pragmatic
way of
limiting the long list we are supposed to draw
up as in Rule 5? Let
scientists
draw one up until they are convinced of the
objectivity of the claim?
Otherwise
the list would be endless – tracing all the
references and background
to a
single Sports Science article would be
prohibitive! Why should we want
to draw
up any such list that is longer than what the
scientists themselves
would draw
anyway?]
Rule three. It is
not that easy to argue
from what 'nature' is really like to settle any
controversy. In
practice, what
seems natural and real is what emerges at the
end of long debates and
disputes,
when some consensus has been arrived at, or,
rather, dissenters have
been
driven off or given up. Incidentally, this
forgotten [repressed?]
creative
process is what Latour calls the 'tacit
knowledge' of the scientist.
This is a
long process, and in natural science, much
depends on what goes on in
laboratories.
Latour's examples turn on controversies that
went very deep indeed into
the organization
of laboratories, the calibration of instruments,
the purity of samples,
very
detailed attempts to control variables and so
on. He insists that this
should
really be seen as an element in the resolution
of disputes or trials of
strength, where laboratories serve to discourage
dissenters: the only
way to
respond to laboratory evidence is to develop
bigger and better
laboratories. An
instrument here is defined as something that
produces data connected to
displays. The relation between instruments and
their 'spokesmen' (those
who interpret the data and attempt to
make it as objective as possible) is crucial.
Scientists interpreting
data
strive to be objective spokespersons of
instruments, while the
dissenters
attempt to argue that some subjective matters
have been introduced into
the
interpretation. Anyone shown to be subjective
loses the strength of
support
gathered by a scientific writing and laboratory
experiments. There are
many
interesting examples of how particular
laboratory demonstrations or
experiments
or even canonical pieces of work became decisive
allies of particular
point of
view, including Mead's work on Samoan
adolescents, which became a
decisive
issue for those arguing for cultural versus
biological determinism of
sexual
behaviour. There are also political struggles
where spokesmen claim to
be
speaking objectively for their constituents.
This
is
actually an example of Latour means by the term
'actant' -- 'whoever
and whatever is represented [by a
spokesman]' (84) and it can be a machine as well
as a person. [This is
unexceptional, but is not the root and branch
challenge to human
subjectivity
that I had expected. I can see that Latour wants
to represent science
as wholly
and irredeemably rhetorical, and thus he has to
take on what looks like
the
objective elements. So he denies their
objectivity by saying they have
no
meaning until they are interpreted and woven
into controversies. But
this is
not saying, so far at least, that objects and
machines are fully
subjective as
humans are. Machines cannot be spokespersons for
and on behalf of
themselves.
Of
course,
people also need spokespersons to become active
in
controversies - much
work is simply ignored. This is also illustrated
by 'publication bias',
where
only positive results tend to be reported, both
by the companies that
sponsor
the research and by the scientific journals,
even the
Lancet]
Occasionally
instruments
and their readings are interpreted to suggest
that a whole
new
object has been discovered. Unusual readings or
findings raise a
tentative
claim to have discovered a new object, and again
these claims are black
boxed
in due course. One example was the discovery of
polonium, which
originally
appeared as a set of interesting findings in the
laboratory of the
Curies. In
this early stage, 'a "thing" is a score list for
a series of trials'
(89).
The
chapter
ends with the points summarized in rule three
about nature.
Scientists sometimes
want to claim that nature will resolve disputes
in the end. At the same
time
though, they face the other way [Janus figures
appear throughout],
because much
of their activity is designed to find out what
actually is natural.
Only after
a great deal of activity does this become
apparent. In this way,
scientists
face both ways, claiming to be both realists and
relativists. Latour
does not
want to argue for one option rather than the
other, but to agree with
the
scientists themselves -- that once a controversy
is settled, we can
call the
result natural and real. However, all the time
controversies persist,
what is
natural and real is in doubt. Nor is it any good
to use current science
to
arrange past scientific experiments in terms of
their correspondence
with what
is now thought of as real and natural. This is
merely 'Whig history,
that is, a
history that crowns the winners, calling them
the best... and... the
losers...
simply... wrong' (100). [In
other words,
it is teleological, or historicist]. The double
stance toward nature is
also
used to fight off critics, invoking the realist
stance against
relativists, and
occasionally vice versa [possibly
when
accused of being naive positivists . This might
happen with sports
science --
on one hand, approaches are simply either right
or wrong, but on the
other,
sports scientists congratulate themselves on
finding ingenious ways to
define
and
operationalize particular matters, and maybe
even to manage
controversies].
Rule 4 It is a
problem to decide who
actually qualifies for the title of scientist --
is it those few who
work in
leading laboratories, or the much wider group of
people who keep them
there,
including those senior scientists who travel the
world getting funds
and
licences? [This is
going to be one of
those
distinctions that Latour simply sidesteps, by
refusing to prioritize or
organize
them into a hierarchy instead of a network]. The
latter group is
important to
permit the former to operate. When we look at
where scientists or
actually
employed and who pays for them, we find only a
few are engaged in
experimental
laboratory work, and that the biggest budgets
are found in defence and
health.
Latour says that these tend to have limitless
budgets so it is a good
idea for
any scientific programme to get connected to
them if it can. Scientists
themselves are not interested in these links,
and don't understand
anything
about society, certainly not in the way that
sociologists understand
it
-- hence the absence from the book of any terms
like class or gender.
What
'society' amounts to is a pragmatic matter for
the scientists
themselves, and
they don't really understand its extent until
they can point to a
stabilized
network of contacts. Thus both society and
nature are sometimes seen as
the
causes of scientific activity, but they are
really the results of
extensive
activity stabilized into a network.
Rule 5 Chapter 5
has a very interesting
discussion on relativism with some excellent
examples including the
Azande and
the Trobriand Islanders. It is easy to
demonstrate that the simple
opposition
between Western thought as rational, and
everyone else's as limited and
partly
irrational, will not hold water. Western
thinking and practices are
every bit
as irrational as Azande witchcraft, and vice
versa. Both systems of
belief and
science result from a network of claims,
problem-solving and activity
developed
according to an everyday logic - a 'sociologic'. [Here
and elsewhere we find echoes of American
pragmatism
both as a way
of organizing ordinary beliefs and of developing
scientific knowledge].
There
are important differences between science and
belief, however, seen
best when
scientific networks encounter nonscientific
ones. There are a number of
ways in
which this can happen, and Latour uses terms
like the angle, direction
or scale
of the encounter. [There are also hints of Schutz's work on
different
notions
of reality between 'strangers' and residents,
and between scientists
and
others.]
Latour points out that scientists go off to
investigate other social
lives, not
to settle among them and maintain their network
of belief, but to
return back
to their home countries and strengthen and
extend scientific networks.
There is
also a hint, developed fully in Chapter 6 of the
greater explanatory
power of
scientific networks.
Rules 6 and 7 There
is no difference
between
the way that ‘savages’ think and the way that
scientists think, no
‘Great
Divide’. Scientific networks and belief systems
are elaborated and
extended in
the same way, buttressing claims, managing
crises and refuting rivals
using the
same pragmatic procedures – ‘sociologic’.
Science is organized
differently
though, since it operates with much more data,
gathered systematically
and then
processed, abstracted and rationalized into
systems. Science operates
just like
bureaucracies do. Back at the metropolitan
centres in Europe,
people are despatched to discover data about
other people and bring it
back for
processing and addition (this is like capital
accumulation but Latour
says the
term capitalism is confusing and ambiguous). A
large interlocking
network is
required, of scientists but also politicians,
explorers, rulers etc.
Once
collected or imported, data is subject to
further processing,
abstraction (like
the ‘stacking’ mentioned earlier), and is
ideally mathematicised.
Science then becomes
specialist and powerful, capable of considerable
application – but only
if the
real world is transformed first (tidied,
rationalized, made to resemble
the
data of science). This process ‘hardens’ facts
(surrounds them with so
much
support that they are irrefutable).
Overall,
this is not quite as strange
and alien as it looks. I think Latour mystifies
it a bit, possibly for
good
reasons: he is wary of using conventional terms
such as 'abstract'
to describe scientific theory,
although he is content to rely on that word as a
verb in order to
describe the
explanatory power of scientific theory. The same
goes for words like
'transformation', which is not much more than
the process of
objectifying
complex reality so as to make it compatible with
the formulae of
science. I
suppose both of these words indicate that
scientific theory doesn't
just
describe worlds, but colonizes them (although
Latour would not like the
political and critical sense of that term).
As
for
the famous bits about agencies and networks, I
think this is not
much more
than saying that individual action always takes
place within collective
action.
Obviously, the efforts of others are crucial for
understanding the
activities
of individual scientists. Those others include
not only instrument
makers and
technicians, but collective activity going on in
universities, funding
bodies,
government departments and the like. Instruments
and machines become
actants
because they condense a large network inside
them, so to speak? These
networks
are so interconnected that it makes no sense to
describe events as 'theoretical', 'political', 'geographical', or
whatever, since all of
these aspects
are
involved (the
example here is a rather
good one -- initial explorations of Pacific
islands by the French
government in
order to map and possibly settle particular
areas of the Pacific
Rim. The more familiar case of
Darwin's voyage on the Beagle might also serve. A
series of familiar social networks got Darwin on
board, including the
social connections between his father and
various Government agencies,
and it was also essential that he cope socially
as a gentleman
companion for the Captain. The voyage
itself was launched for
several interlocking reasons, including the
Admiralty's desire to chart
the Pacific, commercial interests wanting to
establish trade with South
America, and the Church of England wanting to
establish missionary
outposts. To achieve the latter, the
Beagle carried a missionary and three
natives of
Tierra Del Fuego who had been 'brought to
England' [actually abducted,
originally as hostages] several
years before and Anglicised: they were to be
returned to their homeland
to set up a missionary station. Darwin says that
returning the
Fuegians was the main motive for the journey as
far as the captain was
concerned. Darwin himself took several risks in
his
adventures and might well have perished once or
twice. The implications
for science would have been very interesting!).
The
notion
of a network is actually rather like that of the
rhizome ( in
Deleuze, as
Latour himself says), extending in
different areas and dimensions in a kind of
practical problem-solving
way --
a 'sociologic'.
Theoretical science,
social science, and religious beliefs are
identical in this sense --
they're
all cobbled together as they go, in order to
extend themselves and
defend
themselves against rivals. We're not far away
from the notion of
bricolage,
surely, with a possible role for particularly
gifted bricoleurs?
Of
course
science is organized and systematized, and this
is the secret of
its
huge explanatory power. Experiences are turned
into data, and this data
is
'mobile', that is it can be imported back to the
centres of networks,
abstracted and managed, and slotted into systems
of classification of
various kinds.
Cartography and taxonomy are the bases of the
growth of science in Europe.
There is a power relation involved, in that,
usually, data moves into
centres
and not the other way around.
This
is
an area where Latour is occasionally evasive. For
example, he says that he will not use
sociological terms such as class or power
because that is not the ways
that
scientists themselves understand the world, and
he is simply trying to
map
their understandings -- Science in Action. Yet
there other reasons as
well --
sociological theory is a form of science itself,
and he would not wish
to
privilege one form in order to understand
another. The implication is
that his
concepts, such as network, are more powerful
than either, or at least
more
general. The usual lack of reflexive critique is
applicable here -- has
Latour
simply been cobbling together bits of history,
scientific practice,
observation
and sociological terminology in order to develop
ANT?
De
Certeau’s critique of Foucault’s use of
history might apply here:
Latour is
displaying such a grasp of historical and other
detail that it is
impossible to
refute him. His decision to explore the esoteric
realm of science also
leaves
many sociologists without any way to disagree.
More
mundanely,
many of the examples are historical, no doubt to
help us
understand
before things got really technical. But is
modern science like that?
Does it
still do simple induction? Isn’t there another
stage where
mathematicised
‘facts’ are themselves manipulated and never
actually ‘applied’? To use Lyotard’s
terms, Latour is describing
modernist science where it all still ran
according to the performance criteria: now it is
a mere game is it
easier to
extend networks? If it is now a research
programmes, doesn’t that make
the
politics of universities more prominent?
At
times
he seems apologetic towards the use of power,
seeing it as
necessary to
consolidate networks, inevitable, or so well
established that it is
irreversible. The links between knowledge and
power need be clarified
though,
unless he really is doing a simple description
of the world-view and
activities
of natural scientists, who could not be expected
to want to clarify
them.
index
page |