Notes on: Latour, B [Jim Johnson] (1988)
Mixing Humans and Nonhumans Together: The
Sociology of a Door – Closer. Social
Problems 35, 298--310
Dave Harris
The general position is that sociology should
study associations, including nonhuman ones. This
text is itself a machine and the author is
'constructed and deconstructed several times to
show how many social actors are inscribed or
prescribed by machines and automatisms' (298)
Sociologists tend to ignore the nonhuman, partly
because of technical complexity and partly because
there is no convenient vocabulary. Nonhuman should
be reinserted into the mainstream, however.
Sociologists often make assumptions about the
social context of machines but this needs to be
explored.
Walls clearly need holes, and holes in turn have
to be regulated with a door. This is actually a
clever invention involving the himge, and it makes
passing through walls extremely convenient, with
no need for destruction and construction. Doors
actually regulate by directing things and people —
that is why we do not get equilibrium in terms of
the population of adjoining areas. So 'techniques
are always involved when asymmetry or
irreversibility is the goal' (299), and this is
common in social situations.
We can list the work that people would have to do
if there was no door, and it would be enormous
compared to the small effort involved in opening
and closing doors. A major effort has been
translated or delegated into a minor one — the
hinge shows this delegation or translation or
displacement. We can do the work of walking
through doors because the door itself 'was
delegated by the carpenter'. As a 'general
descriptive rule' we can note what work and
nonhuman does by imagining what humans would have
to do if they were not present, 'imaginary
substitution'. In walking through doors, we make a
small effort to balance out the very large one,
and this can also be seen as 'a very moral story
indeed (think of David and Goliath)'. It also
illustrates the workings of levers, via
Archimedes, and the King of Syracuse who together
helped defend the city. This is a better way to
understand the '"social construction" of
techniques' instead of invoking some hypothetical
social context.
Doors do not solve all the problems. Some require
humans to close them, but this is by no means
routine. The option is to discipline the people to
close the door, or substitute 'another delegated
human character whose only function is to open and
close the door' (300) — a doorkeeper, but they
require payment, and even the best doorkeepers are
sometimes irregular. Excessive disciplining would
be unacceptable and involve large costs. Compare
all this effort with the nonhuman hinge, which is
equally important, cheaper, and requires no
attention except basic maintenance [which he calls
'a reversal of time']. Humans require a time
schedule. Some habits are incorporated into their
bodies, but this is a continuous delegation,
requiring attention in the present tense, whereas
the machines have a 'built-in inertia' (301)
[again this is talked up as 'a profound temporal
shift… time is folded', when nonhumans were
involved.
A nonhuman will perform the task of closing the
door [for some reason, the door closer is also
known as a groom -- in the USA?]. However, this
might involve deskilling and the replacement of
humans. More generally, whenever humans are
displaced and de-skilled 'nonhumans have to be
upgraded and reskilled', and this is not easy. The
characteristics of door closers affect human
behaviour, because you have to get through the
door before they close it — this 'presupposes a
skilled human user'. We can call this imposed
behaviour 'prescription', and they can be put into
speech, sometimes in the imperative. They actually
look like a programming language. They can appear
in instruction manuals, or in training routines as
in the military. There is always a 'moral and
ethical dimension', and overall, 'no human is as
relentlessly moral as a machine' especially if
they are user-friendly.
Using a machine like a door closer also stratifies
the human users, some of whom know about the
characteristics and others don't. Sometimes this
stratification is remedied by new design — a
weaker spring, for example, but there is a limit
to ambiguity in a useful door closer — it is 'an
OR not an AND gate' (302). Some door closes are
particularly clever with hydraulic dampers, worked
by 'extracting energy from each and every
unwilling, unwitting passerby'. 'This is as clever
as a tollbooth'.
Even the best door closers leave out some human
beings, like infants or the very old, so in a way
they discriminate against these people. They can
also discriminate against people who require them
to be open all the time, such as package
deliverers. However, they can be blocked or
propped open, although this is rarely fully
successful.
However, overall, 'three rows of delegated
nonhuman actants (hinges, springs, and hydraulic
pistons)' will replace an undisciplined human most
of the time, 'the technologist's dream of
efficient action' although things can still go
wrong and door closers can go '"on strike"', and
remind us that we must interact again. The term
strike was used in a particular university
department, and this sort of humour is common —
people swear at their cars or talk to their
computers. It is common to see sociologists in
particular scandalised by this behaviour, may
refer to projections of human behaviour,
anthropomorphism 'which for them is a scene akin
to zoophily but much worse' (303).
This is irritating moralising, because the door
closer 'is already anthropomorphic through and
through' shaped by humans and giving shape to
them, substituting for people, delegating and
prescribing. It seems unfair to forbid anyone
attributing additional human properties. Indeed,
sometimes they have extra properties such as
electronic eyes or machine pass readers. In
general, it is a problem 'to decide forever the
real and final shape of humans' to decide between
a real delegation and an imaginary projection. It
is a form of discrimination to 'always plead
against machines and for de-skilled workers', and
he does not 'hold this bias'. So it is accurate to
say that the door closer is on strike.
The problem is that the dichotomy between humans
and in humans is often confused with one between
figurative and non-figurative. The latter arises
when we move a personal figure to a less personal
one [Hamlet becomes a representative of the
aristocratic class]. This does not affect the
status of actants when we are talking about
humans, and humans can be treated both
figuratively and nonfiguratively. It is the same
with nonhuman actants, where engineers delegate
and prescribe a series of interlocking characters,
and face many chances 'for figuring or
de-figuring, personifying or abstracting,
embodying or disembodying actors'.
We see this in everyday life, when we mistake
machines for human beings [the example is a
robotic human-looking traffic director on a US
highway]. Engineers could do much more of this
figuration, supplying electronic eyes or facial
expressions, or less figuration, removing the
robotic human and just leaving the signal, a
variety of signals, perhaps no signal at all.
We can use the term 'enunciator' (304) to combine
authors of texts and mechanics who devise
machines. They can represent themselves in what
they do, or not. It Is no different from adopting
a pseudonym, as he did for this article. Or there
can be a much vaguer relation between enunciator
and product, and sometimes figuration can be left
out altogether, even in texts [anonymous
narrators].
Generally speaking, people are not all that
'circumspect, disciplined and watchful'. They
relate to 'two systems of appeal: nonhuman and
superhuman, that is machines and gods'. The people
who said the door closer was on strike were first
relying on the morality and common sense of humans
to use doors properly, then to some nonhuman Court
of Appeal — the door closer. When that failed,
they had only the 'oldest and firmest Court of
Appeal' — they appealed to 'the respect for God'
[the notice said for 'God's sake keep the door
closed' ](305), but this is not enough these days.
Nothing seems to work. There is a tendency towards
more and more figurated [personified] delegates,
but even they lose their effect. A simple
instruction to shut the door might have been
sufficient, but its effect weakened and stronger
reminders were required.
The movement is not always 'from softer to harder
devices' , however, from a reliance on autonomous
knowledge through to worded injunctions.
Deskilling might be the general case, but it can
work the other way. For example red lights are
normally respected, and so are delegated
policeman. Both rely on car drivers doing a
thought experiment — what would happen if there
were no regulation [which he says is like the
original exercise to work out how important
nonhumans are by thinking of all the work required
to replace them]. In many other circumstances, we
do no thought experiment at all, and take for
granted that the car engine will start. The skills
are 'so eill embodied or incorporated' that
written instructions are unnecessary.
There is no simple direction between humans and
nonhuman is, so it is useless 'to impose a priori
divisions between which skills are human and which
ones are not human', or what is personified and
what remains abstract, or what sort of delegation
has taken place. Instead, we require 'a few simple
descriptive tools'. [He acknowledges the work of a
certain Madeleine Akrich here]
We might think about 'scripts'(306) or scenes
played by actants, figuratively or not. We do not
treat all humans figuratively, as a friend, and
sometimes they act as machines. We can think of a
'description' of a situation as retrieving
its script, commenting on a text, or turning
to programming language. Just as with semiotics,
these descriptions 'define actors, endow them with
competencies and make them do things'.
Most scripts are silent in practice 'because they
are intra-– or extra-somatic', but they do not
always exist only in the mind of the analyst. They
can be 'explicitly uttered'. There is no simple
division between intra-and extra somatic skills,
as in cases where human beings follow instruction
manuals, or do thought experiments. The same goes
with innovation where objects begin as projects on
paper. The situations are all important and
analysts have to deal with them through another
thought experiment — 'comparing presence/absence
tables and collating all the actions done by
actants: if I take this one away, this and that
other action will be modified'
Scripts can be transcribed, inscribed or encoded,
shifting to a more durable repertoire. Translation
here is not just a linguistic operation, but a
matter of transferring thoughts or meanings into
something more material. This is not just the move
from soft bodies to hard ones, but rather a move
from something less reliable to something more
faithful and longer lasting — sometimes
instructions are embodied in human performance,
and sometimes the other way around when humans are
replaced by machines. This is unlikely to be ever
completed one way or the other — 'the pipedream of
total automation', because some skills are better
delegated to humans, and others the other way
around.
'Prescription' is something presupposed from
transcribed actors and authors, rather like the
role expectation in sociology, but to include
nonhumans. Thus Renaissance paintings were
designed to be viewed from a particular angle, and
so were traffic lights. Traffic lights also
presuppose there is some rational operation at
work, some reliable author. User input in
programming language is another example, where a
living character is automated.
It is just the same 'as that of a text'. Authors
can be wrongly ascribed, and so can readers –
inscribed readers have qualities and behaviour
prescribed to them. Sometimes they subscribe to
these definitions, but generally, nothing prevents
an inscribed user from behaving differently, and
sometimes we can even ignore things like traffic
lights or instructions. Attempts to close the gap
between inscribed and actual can lead to things
like appeals to God. Although at other times,
prescribed users have been indeed well anticipated
and dovetailed into design. We can describe the
two alternatives as 'des- inscription'and
subscription (307).
Anticipations of use vary with distance — door
closers work well when people are close to the
door. But scenes do have preconceived ideas,
prescribed actors, and this can actually limit
individual freedom throughout. 'Pre-
inscription'refers to all the' upstream' work by
both user and author. So hydraulic pistons were
used for years before they were added to door
closers. Sometimes this is called '"articulation
work"'. In Citizen Kane, the hero bought a theatre
for his wife and then bought the journals that do
the reviews, then bought off the critics and
finally paid the audience to turn up. As that
example shows, human indiscipline often triumphs.
Sociologism involves the idea that you can read
out the scripts from understanding competence and
pre-inscription of human users. A symmetrical
claim is technologism which applies to predicting
the behaviour of and reactions to nonhuman actors.
Both of them assume we can split humans and
nonhumans. That society is made up only of human
relations is 'bizarre', and matched by the idea
that techniques are only nonhuman. Instead there's
a variety of characters, delegates,
representatives, figurative, nonfigurative, human
and nonhuman, competent and incompetent. It is
absurd to divide these into society on the one
hand and technology on the other.
It is important that other setups are aligned if
prescription is to work — the door closer works
after people have been directed to the sociology
department, perhaps following maps, perhaps being
able to locate the University in the correct
state. This is a 'gradient of aligned setups'
(308), and actors have pre-inscribed competencies
in order to produce the '"necessary path"' [also
called a ' chreod']. The clearer this necessary
path is made, the fewer instructions are required.
Actions become routinised. This in turn
problematises 'classic debates about freedom,
determination, predetermination, brute force, or
efficient will'. [He says that a clever author
such as himself can lead a reader along these
necessary paths — but that does not always work].
There is also [interdependency — chains of
obligation], where prescriptions assume the
efficient discharge of other actions — like all
the parts in a machine working. It is even more
important with nonhumans, and we might need to
watch out for it if we are looking at relations
among nonhumans altogether. We can still use
sociological terms such as '"role expectation,"
behaviour, social relations' even with
nonfigurative actors.
So he has used the story of a door closer to make
a nonhuman delegate 'familiar' to sociologists.
Used semiotic techniques to explain relations
between things like inscription and prescription.
However there is one important difference between
texts and machines — 'machines are
lieutenants'(308 – 9) holding places and roles
delegated to them. But there is a different way of
'shifting', displacing characters onto other
spaces, times or characters. Telling a story can
shift the setting to another space and time,
enunciators may decide to be represented by a
narrator, words like 'I' can position any reader
inside the story, and there are many ways to shift
a story, through dialogue, for example, or through
progress through nested stories.
Engineers do better! They constantly shift
characters into other spaces and times, devise
different positions, break down competencies and
redistribute them, build 'complicate [sic]
narrative programmes and sub- programmes' (309).
Much of this work escapes the attention of the
public, sometimes because when engineers shift,
they fix words in a particular matter, they choose
between frames of reference, they even permit
enunciators to ignore delegated actors. As an
example, he has yelled at his child on the
motorway to not sit in the middle of the rear
seat. Then he came across a special child seat
ideal for cars like his. It had been 'nicely
analysed by these Japanese fellows', and he is
happy to subscribe to the descriptions in the
device. It comes into its own on the freeway,
where he suddenly realised he needed it — it was
pre-inscribed. He can now delegate his own actions
to a device. He detoured through his wallet and
then to the toolbox, and had to make sense of the
instructions. The detours and translations do
represent 'shifting out' (310) but not of the same
type as in a story — the device has replaced him
[without any pleasing ambiguity]. [There's an even
better comment in note 3 on page 309. An art
historian has described a Scottish Iron Bridge and
notes that it remains 'silent (black boxed)' as
opposed to the 'rich series of mediators who
remain present in a work of art'. This is
important for Barad, who seems to think that
infinfte possibiiities are always present with
each agential cut -- not once previous cuts have
been embodied in hardware, black boxed!]].
There are thousands of lieutenants like this. They
are important in our social relations — they
prescribe. 'Knowledge, morality, craft, force,
sociability are not properties of humans but of
humans accompanied by their retinue of delegated
characters'. Each delegate ties together part of
the social world. It is impossible to study social
relations without nonhumans, and so sociology has
to address them, just as they once addressed 'the
masses of ordinary and despised humans that make
up our society'. We must add in the mechanism. If
we have to change some of our concepts and habits,
'it is a small price to pay'.
back to social theory
|
|