Notes on: Thomas, P. (1975) Karl
Marx and Max Stirner. Political Theory 3
(2): 159--79.
https://www.jstor.org/stable/190930
Dave Harris
Much of the German Ideology is about Stirner's
book (The
Ego and Its Own)
but this is often omitted, although it is central
to the argument. Stirner represents the best Left
Hegelians and Marx thought that he also indicated
the clearest shortcomings — that is changing
consciousness would change the world, that
material forces could be reduced to personal
forces.
The whole emphasis was upon the individual self,
contrasting particular selves with true selves.
Only an association of egoists (Verein ,
aka society) would encourage suitable
aspirations on the part of individuals, far more
effectively than any 'political, social,
ideological or religious' systems (160). Instead,
particularity, self assertiveness had to be
enlarged, and any system that depended on
an ought should be resisted.
Marx was already sure that this would be bogus
revolutionary politics. Stirner was right to
question whether following revolutionary ideals
would simply involve another form of subjection,
and this was the theme of Marx's response, trying
to show that 'communism and individuality,
properly understood, are anything but
incompatible', and that abstract categories or
principles should be replaced by understanding
real movements of history. In particular,
'communism transcends the Kantian is-ought
distinction'. Like the attack on Feuerbach,
however, this was something of a volte-face:
Stirner had actually led to this attack on
Feuerbach [he criticised Feuerbach himself,
possibly on the grounds that replacing God with
humanity still left humanity as some sort of
religious icon].
Stirner initially worked with Feuerbach's terms of
'alienated attributes and their
reappropriation'(161), but saw Feuerbach as
offering 'oppressive spirituality'. For Feuerbach
man was already divine, but this would become an
oppressive concept just like any other spirit or
collectivity. Feuerbach's atheism was therefore
'half-hearted', not iconoclasm but inversion. The
collectivity 'mankind' is still sacred and
oppressive in its relation to real individuals.
The point was to move beyond any notion of a
higher power that involved renunciation of the
self.
Marx did not exactly agree with this, but his
attacks on Feuerbach were similar, and he
was influenced by 'Stirner's assault on
Feuerbach's anthropocentrism' (162) which took the
form of an 'abstract love for an abstract "man"',
ignoring sensuous real activity. Marx had the same
objection to 'true socialism', that also focused
on '"man"' and thus retreated into ideology.
Stirner actually saw similarities between Marx and
Feuerbach, though, especially in terms of their
common notion of '"species being"' [specifically
in On The Jewish Question]. Thomas thinks
that the two concepts were quite different,
however because for Marx removing alienation does
not just require an adjustment of consciousness,
that the reality demonstrated by the state has to
be tackled by doing more than critique at the
level of consciousness [which includes just doing
ideology critique]. The real world had to be
transformed. For Stirner, this was a different
version of Feuerbach's materialism.
Marx had to reject Feuerbach's humanism, while
avoiding 'extreme individualism' (163) in Stirner.
He then extended the critique of Stirner to all
the young Hegelians. We can see the importance of
Stirner even in the opening words to the Preface,
about men making up false conceptions about
themselves which have come to rule them, which is
a précis of Stirner and Young Hegelianism for
Thomas.
For Stirner, consciousness dominated
history, and so thoughts had to be corrected or
mastered. This is quite unlike psychological
determinism, say in Hobbes or Spinoza, where egos
act only for themselves. History was seen as a
series of submissions to outside beliefs, idees
fixes which stop egos acting on their own behalf.
The future of politics was the autonomous
individual, but first alien consciousness had to
be overcome [classic Young Hegelianism says
Thomas]. Such egos would destroy all forms of
society, but there was no absolute ego or rational
universality, no higher obligations or
reciprocity. Instead, obstacles to the free
development of the ego, grounded in consciousness,
have to be identified.
The development of spiritual consciousness had
helped dominate the natural environment, but not
for the benefit of the individual, 'for its own
sake' (164). We could see S's spiritual drive to
autonomy as manifested in history, however, a
broad debt to Hegel. Christianity was the main
obstacle, with its disdain for the world and
devaluation of the individual. Descartes too in
thinking that human beings lived only as mind.
This stops love for any particular person, in
favour of love of God and the spirit. Like
Feuerbach, Stirner thought of that as enslavement
to categories created by men themselves. But
Feuerbach had made the wrong inversion to arrive
at his notion of human essence, still opposed to
real individuals, still with some notion of
essential self, still lacking a proper break with
Christianity [apparently, you can find support for
this in Hegel himself]. If we are to find
self-fulfilment in spirituality, we will lose
ourselves in reality, and this can be seen in
several stages. Protestantism is an important
stage, developing a personal conscience, an
'"internal secret policeman"' to regulate every
impulse. The absence of intermediaries is also
found in liberalism — for Stirner, rather as with
Marx, religious freedom and political freedom both
mean only freedom for religion or the state.
Although liberalism did introduce some notion of
real conflicts, they still thought that '"nothing
but mind rules the world"' (166) — abstract man
has rights, general collectivities can enslave
individuals, citizens or political men emerge
instead of individuals, there is impersonal
authority and an increase in submissiveness. The
whole existence of the state depends on this
notion of abstract man.
The opposite of this conception should be
valorised — the pauper with nothing to lose.
[Apparently Stirner uses the word proletarian, but
this is not the same as Marx's proletariat, and
this is an unwarranted generalisation]. He thought
that the bourgeoisie maintained pauperism to
justify their own superiority, using the state
where necessary, and its empty moralism [the state
also refuses to deal with pauperism]. The state
needs pauperism if it is to manage and get value
from people.
This leads Stirner in the wrong direction, for
Thomas, thinking that the exploitation of labour
simply depends on the operations of the enemy,
with the labourer as the desired egotist. This is
an unwarranted extension of some underlying
ideological principle for Thomas, which 'led him
to suppose that disparate elements of reality are
linked because they express some "principle" or
other' (167) [endemic to philosophical thinking?].
He also failed to see any alienating or oppressive
consequences of enshrining egoism as an essence —
it remained as a term helping to define the
oppressiveness of society and state, '(which he
fails to distinguish clearly)'. He embraced
anarchism by arguing that the exercise of will
would destroy the state, although he did not see
the self as a revolutionary — those who did were
just displaying another variant of faith requiring
submission. [Apparently this extended to
Proudhon's socialism as well] This was another
point at which Marx disagreed with Stirner.
Nevertheless, as an anarchist, Stirner believed
that freedom had to be asserted and the state
overcome, and tried to distinguish revolution from
insurrection, a social and political act to
overturn some order as opposed to a rising of
individuals 'without regard to future
arrangements', [sounds a bit like Derrida] opposing
arrangement, leading only to a '"union of
egoists"'. Marx apparently regarded this as
'"comic"' (168).
Stirner was prepared to see the state as the
historical embodiment of morality, as in Hegel,
but this led him to reject both the state and
morality, which were linked together in an
oppressive '"apparition"' (168). This led him to
'play down the coercive force of state
repression', and he was not interested in
different forms of the state since they were all
despotic. All states, including the liberal one,
'moves the clockwork of individual minds'
necessarily restricting autonomy. However, the
state itself is not a simple delusion, and Stirner
learned from Marx here — but it emanated simply
from the general process of human beings 'being
ruled by their own illusions'. One implication,
which led to Marx's ridicule, was that 'law
embodies no coercive force'. Nor do we get much
specific politics. The state is an agent of
sacredness and so is society, morality, and even
revolutionary organisation. The state is just an
organ [the result of the division of labour?]that
necessarily oppresses and requires regulation and
surrender.
For Marx, the 'total debasement of the individual'
was alienation in the labour process (169). The
social division of labour was crucial in The
German Ideology. The issue for Stirner,
however, was not this sort of debasement, but a
particular one — the 'denial of his Eigenheit
[peculiarity]'. This was upside down for Marx: the
state does require limited understanding from its
subjects, and there is contentment with bondage of
human beings — but Stirner therefore concluded
that 'the valueless individual is made the
bondsman of himself' [which confirms the organic
link between social life and the state which I
thought I detected above — it's a bit like the
argument in functionalism that says that what's
functional for society might well be dysfunctional
for individuals, even though society might be made
of individuals?]. Marx had already written the
EPM on the economic and social processes of
self bondage, rooted not in the state in the
labour process.
For Stirner, any society involves influence and
constraint unless it is produced by individuals
themselves. We should not aim at 'the chimera of
community', but combine with others to multiply
our own powers, and then only to achieve specific
tasks. Marx saw in this an idealised version of
Hegel's civil society. Stirner realised it would
turn into a free for all, and it is easy to see
that '"egoistical property… Is nothing more than
ordinary or bourgeois property sanctified"'.
Stirner seems to be advocating '"possessive
individualism"'.
All social relations seem to be based on
agreement, all property relations are temporary.
In practice, agreements are only made cynically,
and rejected at the first occasion [paraphrasing
Marx]. It is absurd to see property as something
belonging to individual egos, which makes actual
forms of private property into something abstract
and universal.
This unthought out notion of society just
reproduces the older one, with all its existing
forms of ownership and divisions of labour. It is
division of labour that produces peculiarity. It
is also obvious that the egoist for Stirner can
only be 'an imaginary being', like an Hegelian
category for Marx. Celebrating peculiarity for
Stirner involves making peculiarity into something
holy, an abstract principle again that will force
all analysis into privileged categories. It is
also hard to deny that privileging peculiarity is
just a particular value for Stirner — there is no
way to generalise into an agreed social principle.
Since historical stages and societies are the
embodiment of ideas, all the egoist can do is
overcome ideas, struggle against concepts.
Historical conditions are turned into ideas
[without much systematic research, so that the
dominant ideas of the epoch have to be taken as
literal truth --one of my favourite bits from GI].
It is impossible to disentangle this from Hegel's
system. Individuals are turned into consciousness,
while the world becomes simply an object, and
history proceeds according to the relation between
them — successive stages of consciousness and 'a
ready-made world' (171). Stirner's method is even
simpler than Hegel's, and more dogmatic [Marx's
notion of praxis was apparently derived partly
from Hegel's conception of the will. This might
lead to Marx defending Hegel against the Young
Hegelians, as in the dead dog metaphor].
Consciousness is not originary, but is made, this
is a mistake common to Feuerbach and Stirner,
despite the differences. [The actual quote from
Marx is lovely, arguing that since the holy must
be alien, everything alien must be holy, and by
the same token a mere idea, which can be
overturned just by protest]. The same charge
against Feuerbach can be made against Stirner —
both deal with 'generalities with no meaning'. In
Stirner's case this involves '"man"' as the main
propellant of history, the operator of abstract
ideas. As we saw with the paraphrase above,
Stirner rejects atheism and communism, any
revolutionary action, as a sin against the holy
[so Stirner is a functionalist when it comes to
the social, but objects in particular to the form
of the state as the policeman of the social? Using
the sacred to critique the profane forms it
takes?].
As soon as he moves from ideas, Stirner 'makes
serious mistakes' (172). Historically, capitalism
has fettered self activity through the division of
labour. It is that that has increased productive
force though, not just the productive forces of
individuals or their consciousness. Germany's
industrial underdevelopment conceals that. It is
true that labour can re-appropriate individual
powers, but it requires the end of capitalism
first to develop these abilities — communism. Thus
Marx's apparently general remarks are really a
response to Stirner — individualism was not an
issue with Feuerbach, but central to young
Hegelians and true socialists.
This response helped clarify Marx's own view about
young Hegelians. He 'fully appreciated'(173) the
importance of individualism, and this led to the
idea that social relations have an existence
independent of the bearers, that social division
is reproduced as divisions within individuals who
experience their own powers as something alien.
The point is, however, how to get to emancipation.
Stirner attacks communists because they do not see
a theoretical contradiction between the ego and
self-sacrifice — but that is because they are
interested in the material base which engenders
this contradiction. They do not enshrine
individualism, but they do not just want to
sacrifice individuals to the wider movement.
Stirner is wrong to see labour as inevitably
egoistic, because in capitalism it is dominated by
material conditions, which suppress individuality
and introduce dependence through the division of
labour. As a result labour does not resemble life
activity at all, but stunts it. It is not a matter
of achieving self activity as much as one of
survival. If we could only reappropriate the
instruments of production, we would develop the
total capacities of individuals. This broader
social and political change is required if
individuals are to become free to manifest
themselves. Without grasping that, 'the individual
can be conceived as being opposed to the
collectivity only if he is conceived mystically as
"unique"' (174).
As well as offering critique, Marx also developed
his own ideas about individuality. One critic
thinks that he realised for the first time that
there was a need to consider ideas and how they
develop in the minds of intellectuals, whereas
before he had been thinking only in terms of
classes. However, the real focus for Marx was
rethinking the relation between individual and
class in capitalism — 'thanks in no small measure
to Stirner himself'. [I must say I went back to
re-read my abridged copy of The German
Ideology after reading this article, in
2020, and there are indeed some remarks at the end
of the section on Feuerbach, about individuals and
how they can only flourish after the revolution.
That was new to me! There is more predictable
stuff in the section on 'unique individuals' like
great artists and scientists --M&E insist on
the importance of social context and the
contingency it produces for individuals -- and on
the allegedly universal drive to
self-assertiveness -- only realistic for the
bourgeoisie at the moment is the response there]
back to social theory page
|
|