A Reading Guide -- Althusser on
Ideology
L. ALTHUSSER
"Ideology and Ideological State
Apparatuses (Notes Towards an
Investigation)" in Althusser L (1977)
'Lenin and Philosophy' and Other
Essays, London, New Left
Books
Introduction
This is an
influential, but seldom carefully read
piece, quoted all over the place in
Sociology of Education and Media/
Popular Culture or Politics texts. For
many commentators, it summarises
Althusser's main views on ideology,
reproduction ,and the role of the
individual, especially via the
discussion of hailing. However, there
are several other pieces in
Althusser's overall work which offer
different views, and getting the
overall picture of Althusser's attempt
to revive marxism is helpful in
locating this piece). In this
collection of his work (Lenin and
Philosophy…), try also the
article "Freud and Lacan" on the
individual.
The main
arguments
1. Social
reproduction can be simple or
extended. It goes on in the whole
social system outside production,
hidden to the usual view. The
productive forces must themselves be
reproduced - labour power must be
competent, provided with know-how and
with rules, subjected to ruling
ideology to employ knowledge
conscientiously. This occurs outside
production itself. Know-how must take
place in forms of ideological
subjection.
2. Marx's
base-superstructure metaphor should be
read as referring to foundations, e.g.
of a house, rather than to strict
determination by the economy. "Upper
levels" [later to be specified as
'political' and 'cultural/ideological'
levels, as well as the 'economic' --
the EPI/C model] have only a
derivatory effect, but can act
reciprocally back on the base - as
reproduction of the base.
3. The State is
not just a collection of repressive
state apparatuses (R.S.A.s). Early
Marx himself suggests this, but we
should see this too as only a
descriptive beginning. The issue today
is State power as the centre of
political class struggle. The modern
State is a plurality of apparatuses,
including ideological state
apparatuses (I. S. A. s). These are
still State apparatuses because their
very "private" nature is itself
decided by the State [so earlier
formulations, including Gramsci's are
suspect]. They function as State
apparatuses. , by ideology not by
repression, primarily, although they
are interwoven with R. S. A. s. They
are unified by the ruling ideology
which is revealed in I. S. A. s
"precisely in contradictions". The
ruling class must dominate I. S. A. s,
[although it must not look like it]
providing a possible site of class
struggle, and there are contradictions
in ruling class ideology, leaving room
for the exploited to gain power. But
even so, any struggle would still only
be in an ideological form, and would
be rooted elsewhere [a point
overlooked by advocates of activist
struggle in the media, in education
etc. ?].
4. Reproduction
occurs through these I. S. A. s. Any
force needed is already under the
control of the ruling class (r.c.)
(including administrators.). The
political conditions needed are
secured via the I. S. A. s, via the
ruling ideology. As above, this is
inevitably contradictory, having to
balance r.c. interests against broader
interests both national and
particular, and having to reconcile
r.c. interests with possibly
conflicting issues like nationalism,
moralism and "economism".
Education
5. In modern
capitalism, education is the main I.
S. A. It fits people to the labour
market and gives them an appropriate
ideology. It appears neutral -
knowledge can even seem liberating [a
dig at some old lefties here].
Internal struggles - progressive
challenges etc. - only make it look
more neutral or "natural": the real
challenge comes from "the educational
crisis", the world class
struggle.
Ideology
6. Ideology "in
general" "has no history" [i.e. no
actual content, no concrete origin in
wrong perceptions etc.], although
specific ideologies do. Ideology in
general is always "imaginary",
representing a non-historical
"reality". Imagination is "eternal"
[i.e. makes the same continuing,
permanent, and wrong relations between
people and social reality, the famous
"imaginary relationship of individuals
to their real conditions of
existence".] Ideology is a
representation of this imaginary
relationship. It is not just an
illusion which can be easily dispelled
by a correct interpretation, not just
a lie to fool subordinate classes, not
just the result of a necessary
alienation - ideology is needed in
social life. Ideology does not just
misrepresent the real nature of
capitalist society - the relation of
individuals to the realities is
necessarily "imaginary
distortion".
Individuals
7. Ideology has a
material existence in apparatuses, in
practices which are represented. The
imaginary relation at the heart of
ideology in general is grounded in
important practices which constitute
individuals as "subjects" [i.e. acting
individuals, with ideas of their own].
This subjectivity must be confirmed by
practice, or else individuals can not
be treated as such. Social rituals
[note the similarities with Durkheim -
or Goffman!] in ideological
apparatuses confirm this view that we
are subjects with consciousness "of
our own". This is done so well that
subjects seem obvious and natural.
Ideologies thus affect all practices
and all notions of the subject,
individuality, consciousness
etc.
Interpellation
8. Ideology
interpellates individuals as subjects
-i. e. the very category of the
subject is ideological, and "all
ideology has the function [n.b.] of
'constituting' individuals as
subjects". The very obviousness and
naturalness of the experience of
ourselves as subjects is an
"ideological effect". We recognise
ourselves as subjects - ideology has a
recognition function as well as a
misrecognition one [witty, no?].
"Hailing"
9. Recognition
arises in rituals such as "hailing" -
calling someone's name : ideology does
this too, it "hails" us
(interpellation), although we are
usually unaware of this. It has done
this "eternally" - an abstract
category of "subject" lies waiting for
us long before we actually fill out
that category with detailed, concrete
"individual" performances. [ There are
clear links with "positioning theory"
in Film Studies which argues that
films "hail" audiences precisely in
this way - see the file on
realism .
An
example in Althusser
10. The Christian
ideology says that God addresses
individuals (hails them) in order to
make each of us a subject, free to
obey or disobey etc. But Christianity
also expects recognition of God's
constituting role back from the
individuals concerned. To be a subject
in Christianity, you have to subject
yourself to God - the human subject
merely reflects the Subjectivity of
God.
11. This "mirror
structure", where a centred Subject is
surrounded by nothing but pale
reflections of Himself is typical of
all ideology - a system of mutual
reflection of images guarantees the
credibility of the whole system [this
helps us distinguish ideology from
marxist science, which actually
produces new knowledge from productive
work on ideologies -- as in the
"generalities" model, and note the
link with the "mirror relation"
borrowed from Lacan on Freud]. Rituals
make all this work apparently quite
naturally - Christians soon learn the
difficult idea that to be a subject
you must subject yourself willingly.
The reality that is not obvious or
easily grasped is that subjection of
subjects serves the reproductive
function of the social
formation.
An
example not in Althusser
12. The ideology
of assessment in educational systems
says that individuals freely, and as
an expression of their subjective
"knowledge", "intelligence" or
"quality" subject themselves ("submit"
pieces of work) to the processes of
grading. If individuals gain good
grades they are entitled to award
themselves self-defining labels such
as "bright", "academic", "clever",
"suited for a higher degree", and so
on. Subjective prowess and personal
status implies subjection to an
impersonal and crudely operationalised
grading system. Individual students
are thus interpellated. They are
allowed to make concrete the abstract
categories (grades) which await them.
The whole system is self-sustaining -
the more good grades you want, the
more you have to submit work, the more
work that is willingly submitted, the
more rational, helpful and natural the
assessment system becomes. The whole
process is centred on a myth. The
reality that is not so easy to grasp
is that the assessment system serves
to reproduce the technical division of
the labour force, and its docility,
required by capitalism see also
Bowles
and
Gintis .
This is not a
conspiracy, not another example of
"alienation", not the result of open
control by a rapacious ruling class or
academic elite - it is necessary, one
of the "eternal" practices by which
individuals recognise themselves.
No-one controls it . Some mugs think
they do when they "play the game" in
assessment - but, in the end, just as
with Willis's lads (see P. Willis's
book Learning to Labour or reading guide), the system
reproduces its own requirements.
Struggle
13. In the last
appended section, Althusser admits
that his analysis is too "abstract",
that the function of completing
reproduction depends on a successful
class struggle by the r.c. At most, I.
S. A.s represent only the necessary
forms of class struggle developed
elsewhere [This restoration of class
struggle might save Althuser from some
of his critics who have accused him of
"functionalism" etc -but he then
leaves himself open to the charge of
Hirst et al. (eg in Hirst, P On
Law and Ideology ) that this is
"class reductionism" of the old kind
after all!].
Discussion
The usual reaction
to all this in British marxist circles
is to condemn it all as hopelessly
"functionalist", deterministic,
leaving no hope for activist teachers
who "resist" or activist film
audiences, underestimating resistance
etc. Gramsci is usually preferred for
a whole range of reasons. So, just to
end on a pro-Althusserian note, for a
change, try thinking about the
following:
1. Gramsci locates
one of the bases for activist
resistance in areas outside of the
State ( "civil society"). Althusser
doesn't think much of this concept,
and there is a hint of his criticism
in the ISAs essay - dig it out from
Section 3 and think about it.
2. "Activism" is
often seen as a good thing in its own
right (and it was very fashionable
once among academics). Has Althusser
simply forgotten about it in this
essay, or has he offered any reasons
for thinking activism is likely to be
limited as a political strategy?
3.Is Althusser
offering us no hope of radical change
at all in this essay? Is this a
conservative analysis? Is it a
functionalist one ( like, say, Davis
and Moore or Parsons)? What marxist
politics might (did!) follow from this
essay?
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
While you're here,
let me also offer some notes on
another famous piece by Althusser on
ideology. This one is much less well
known, probably, and it concerns
what looks like a different definition
of ideology. Here, Althusser is
attempting to clarify the distinction
between ideology and science, part of
a major effort which led him into
famous pieces like the one on 'the
Generalities'. Of course, ultimately,
the project was to defend marxism as a
science. Meanwhile, the piece offers a
nice example of good skilled
marxist 'ideology critique' --although
you might need to know a bit about
Rousseau's Social Contract to
really appreciate it
READING GUIDE TO:
the chapter on Rousseau, Althusser L
(1972) Politics and History,
Part 2, New Left Books: London.
Here, Althusser
argues that ideology is a theoretical
practice, which is locked in a
problematic which defines both
problems and solutions. It has a
reflective, mirror structure. It
cannot produce real, concrete
knowledge. Althusser goes on to apply
this to Rousseau's notion of the
social formation. This is a
specifically theoretical object,
produced from mere philosophical
reflection, and producing definite
theoretical effects of its own.
Specifically, Rousseau's thought
contains discrepancies -- ambiguities
or contradictions. These can be
'solved' only by the introduction of
further discrepancies. Ultimately, all
these specific discrepancies are
traceable to a fundamental one --
between the 'concept in theory'
and the 'real concept'.
The first
discrepancy. The relation
between individuals and the community
is conceived as a Social Contract, in
Rousseau. This is odd though, because
the two 'contractors' are the
same thing, according to Rousseau. The
community and the General Will emerge
only after individuals have
constructed it together. At the same
time, individuals can only really be
free and fully social after the
General Will rules. This is surely
ambiguous. Althusser goes on to
suggest that Rousseau owes a debt to
Hobbes in all this, although this is
not immediately obvious. Rousseau can
only get out of this discrepancy by
saying how the Social Contract
actually emerges. However, when he
tries this he only runs into...
The second
discrepancy. The Social Contract
is established as a result of the
pursuit of the personal interests of
individuals, and Althusser says that
Rousseau was at pains to stress the
personal benefits of it all for
individuals, as all liberals must.
Rousseau's emphasis is on 'moral
benefits' , but as he acknowledges,
there will be slightly more material
benefits too, such as the right to own
private property and to pursue
material economic interests. We all
know that that will lead to massive
social inequality, and for marxists,
of course, that does not benefit many
individuals at all. The real advantage
to be gained in moral communities,
suggests Althusser, is that they
regulate capitalism rather better
than 'Nature' does --
'Nature' was Rousseau's earlier
utopia. Rousseau recognises
this, but hopes that some elusive
moral freedom will emerge once the
General Will is released. However,
moral freedom and economic freedom fit
together rather uneasily.
The third
discrepancy. Apart from all the
usual problems and ambiguities about
how the General Will preserves and
reconciles individual wills, Rousseau
is very confused about the dangers
presented by sundry sections or
factions who might pervert the General
Will. Althusser says Rousseau
knows very well that these are the
really important social groups, and
that they will, and do, dominate real
social conditions. However, all
he can do is simply hope that they
won't interfere. Other practical
problems -- such as the mechanics of
political constitutions and so on --
are well discussed in Rousseau, but
this issue of factions is simply
denied. For Althusser, of course,
these factions are social classes, and
they determine or constitute both of
the mythical polls -- the General Will
and the individual will. Anyway, at
the first really crucial confrontation
between the theoretical model and real
social conditions, Rousseau's whole
argument fails to comprehend or to
give a plausible account.
The fourth
discrepancy. Rousseau does offer
major reforms to attempt to suppress
the role of factions:
- First by
educational reform and general
Enlightenment in mass education --
found in just about all the
liberals. The problem remains that
Rousseau offers no good reason
(one based on actual interests, like
the whole thing is, allegedly)
for such a programme. It is only
worthwhile if you take Rousseau's
vision of society as a matter of
faith, as a 'civil religion'.
Rousseau offers no conceivable
rational social base for such
programme, in other words.
- Secondly by
economic reform by the State,
involving mildly socialist
programmes of redistribution,
flavoured with a bit of nostalgia
for pre-industrial forms.
However, though, Rousseau offers no
real economic or social bases for
these programmes either -- all he is
left with is mere 'moral
preaching'. In both cases, Rousseau
is trapped by a reality he cannot
analyse. He can only appeal to old
bits of ideology which already
exist, such as a kind of secular
Christianity at times. He does offer
us one other way out, though --
fictional utopias like the one
described in Emile!
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
POSTSCRIPT
Reading all this
again in the late 1990s is really
rather interesting. This is Althusser
at the height of his powers, really,
confidently asserting marxist science
against the forces that were already
at work in France which threatened to
end its monopoly for ever. Benton
(1984) offers a clear account of the
development of Althusserian
marxism. It is a long and
interesting story, but we can
summarise the main developments in
terms of problems with the
interpellation model:
1. The ideological
messages offered to the helpless
subject in ISAs turned out to be
far from clear and far from simple. At
its most abstract, this emerged with
further work on language and how it
worked. All language was contaminated
with ambiguity, it was argued. In
marxist terms, this ambiguity could be
explained as the residue of past class
struggles -- hints of the old
suppressed meanings of terms like
'freedom' remained despite concerted
attempts to make them fit only
capitalist freedom. This insight is
usually associated with 'formalist
marxists' like Volosinov, and gave
rise to one interesting experiment to
try to detect such oppositional
residues in the language of Glasgow
workmen (Woolfson 1976). Pecheux
traced similarly oppositional readings
of different kinds in his own work
(Pecheux 1982). There is an excellent
online essay on Pecheux, with
considerable relevance to contemporary
cultural studies by Montogomery and
Allen in the splendid Canadian
Journal of Communication. You
can access it on the S Zupko site (
see external
links)
In Britain, we might be more familiar
with Hall's (1980) work on alternative
possible 'decodings', classically of
the messages in the mass media (
see file) . This might still
require only an amendment to
Althusser, but the real problems arose
with 'post-structuralist' analyses of
language, which put a considerable
amount of uncontrollable ambiguity at
the very heart of language
systems (to put it simply). Authors
could still attempt to fix meanings as
tightly as possible, but the most
determined efforts were doomed to rely
on little tricks and glosses to cover
up ambiguity, which were inherently
unstable: for every clear statement or
image in an ideological discourse,
there were alternatives, 'ghosts',
lying dormant and waiting to be
activated. The problem gets worse when
one considers the huge amount of
alternative texts floating around
which suggest such alternatives
to the most innocent reader. Worse
still, marxist analyses themselves
were, it had to be admitted, just
another kind of attempt to fix or
center meanings, using the same tricks
and glosses.
2. The apparatuses
themselves needed to be investigated.
They might have the formal function of
interpellation, but that did not
entitle us to assume that this is what
they actually did, or that they did
this without contradiction.
Apparatuses in liberal democracies
especially had a number of functions
to discharge, including maintaining
some sort of critical distance from
dominant ideology. It is all very well
for Althusser to assume that these
apparent alternatives only helped
strengthen the authority of ISA -- but
that needed to be shown. There are
several attempts to show how these
institutions work -- later Gintis and
Bowles (see
file) analyse the school
system as a site of such
contradictions and struggles between
the liberating and ideological phases.
Thompson's celebrated (1978) critique
of Althusser pleads for an analysis of
how ideologies actually get
produced, with all their struggle,
hesitation and ambiguity, before
becoming safely installed in ISAs.
Hall et al (1978) try to show that the
mass media are genuinely independent
and critical to some extent, yet those
very professional values can still
preserve overall ideological
frameworks nonetheless ( see reading
guide)(and for a more general
commentary see Harris (1992)).
3. The 'knowing
subject' needed to be examined. There
ensued a whole shift towards the
notion of the 'active subject' after
this essay was written, largely based
on the notion of floods of textuality
we mentioned above, rather than on the
usual rather naïve view of ourselves
as clever individuals. The active
subject alone can fix meaning amidst
the flux of intertextual references
available to him or her. In their
famous analysis of the Bond
movie (see file) , Bennett and
Woollacott argue that there is no
point even in talking of a singular
(ideological) Bond film, so varied are
the readings of the individual
'formations' (not individuals) likely
to be -- and the ideological codes,
which had been so carefully analysed
in the earlier work only existed, in
effect, if they were read.
Despite these problems,
'interpellation' or 'positioning'
approaches remain in much critical
work in Cultural Studies, often
accompanied with warnings about their
assumptions. The most outstanding
example is in the work on the Disney
site, (see
file) in my view, which
often cheerfully assumes that Disney
parks do and must interpellate their
visitors in a very straightforward
way. Perhaps it is now a matter of
faith that this must be so for the
critic?
References
Benton T (1982) The
Rise and Fall of Structuralist
Marxism, London: Macmillan
Hall S et al (1978) Policing
the Crisis: Mugging, the State and
Law and Order, London:
Macmillan
Hall S et al (eds) (1980) Culture,
Language and Media, London:
Hutchinson
Harris D (1992) From Class
Struggle to the Politics of
Pleasure...,London and New York:
Routledge
Thompson E (1978) 'The Poverty of
Theory' and Other Essays,
London: NLB
Woolfson C (1976) 'The Semiotics of
Working Class Speech' in CCCS (eds)
Cultural Studies 9, Birmingham
University
more files
on various topics
|