Notes on: Dolphijn, R & van
der Tuin, I (2012) New Materialism:
interviews and cartographies.
Ann Arbor: Open Humanities Press
Dave Harris
[good collection of new materialists incl
DeLanda]
Interview with Karen Barad
[D and T]. New materialism was first outlined by
DeLanda and Braidotti. It argued that the mind was
'always already material '(48) or that there
were '"naturecultures" for Haraway. It opposed
transcendental and humanist dualist traditions in
cultural theory, although these approaches still
produce debate, for example in recent work by
Butler. Dualism is reduced by thinking of 'the
travelling of the fluxes of nature and culture,
matter and mind, and opening up active theory
formation'. Barad's emphasis on quantum forces
seems to be similar — agential realism wards off
dualisms and so does intra-action. It is an 'immanent
enfolding' of matter and meaning (49). Is it the
core of your critique?
[Barad] First, 'I'm not interested in critique'
which is overrated, overemphasised, and over
utilised to the detriment of feminism', as in
Latour's article. It is no longer right for the
situations we face. It's too easy, especially if
it no longer involves 'reading with care'. Reading
and writing are also ethical practices which
critique misses. Europeans might understand
critique differently. It is too often not
deconstructive, 'the practice of reading for the
constitutive exclusions of those ideas we cannot
do without', but just destructive, dismissive, 'a
practice of negativity', distancing and othering.
Latour suggests we use Turing on the critical
instead, a nuclear metaphor where a chain reaction
explodes with ideas — but this is too 'chilling
and ominous'. She prefers instead Haraway on
diffraction 'reading diffractively patterns of
differences that make a difference', in a way that
makes it 'suggestive, creative and visionary'
(50). She discusses this in chapter 2 of the 2007 book.
She acknowledges that insights are to be read
through one another to build new ones, but that
there is an intrinsic ethics 'not predicated on
externality but rather entanglement'. The idea is
to produce inventive provocations but these are
'respectful, detailed, ethical engagements'.
Entanglement does question dualism, including
nature/culture, matters of fact/matters of care,
which are currently dealt with in separate
academic divisions and a division of labour. This
makes diffraction patterns difficult to see.
Her keynote at a recent conference [at Stevens
Institute of Technology, NJ] commented on the
'innovative revamping of their humanities
program', proposing that we use the sciences to
rethink humanities. However, they seem to think in
terms of a synthesis, but this implies they are
already separated not entangled, and would invite
the old dualism again with values and culture on
one side and fact and nature on the other. This
would be analogical thinking, involving mirror
images between sciences and humanities. She told
them an anecdote about doing fieldwork on the
high-energy physics community [by a certain S
Traweek], where a physicist was admiring fractal
images, and saw their beauty in that they
illustrated the same patterns everywhere.
Feminists similarly are often 'not trained to look
or take pleasure in everything being the same, but
to think about differences'. We need a shift of
geometrical optics from mirroring and sameness,
reflexivity and image, which separates you and the
mirror, the subject and the object. Instead we
should shift towards diffraction, physical optics
not geometrical optics, which treats light as if
it were just a ray. Diffraction allows you to
study 'both the nature of the apparatus and also
the object' (52), the nature of light and of the
apparatus. We can learn a lot about diffraction
from quantum physics
There is a difference between macro diffraction
and quantum diffraction, so we can develop the
metaphor that Haraway has given as to add
nonclassical insights. Interference is replaced
with entanglement, which is 'an ethico-onto–
epistemological matter'. Entanglement produces a
phenomenon. Objectivity is not about accurate
images of the world, but about accountability to
marks on bodies and to taking responsibilities for
entanglements 'of which we are a part' [but isn't
that all of them?]. We can also consider insights
from outside of academia in diffractive reading
[Any? New Age?]. We need to be attentive to what
gets excluded as well as what 'comes to matter'
(53).
As another example, she taught a lecture course on
feminism in science which had science students as
well as humanities social science and arts
students, and they were discussing scientific
literacy: there is a big programme in the USA to
increase it but it seems difficult to do, and is
still found mostly among scientists and engineers.
She thinks a different kind of literacy is
required, including 'consideration of the ethical,
social and legal implications': that should not
just come 'after the fact' — current bioethics for
example just examines imagine consequences of
given projects. But this is 'based on the wrong
temporality', so asking questions is too
little and too late, 'because ethics, of course,
is being done right at the lab bench'. We should
approach the issue of scientific literacy through
asking what apparatuses of bodily production are
involved, and this would involve far more than
scientists.
[D and T] who is the agent in agential realism?
[Barad] she wants to avoid agent or even actant as
insufficiently relational. We risk seeing humans
as the only agents who can then grant agency to
nonhumans, due to the 'gravitational force of
humanism' (54) in the question. Agency is not a
property, it is not held, but should be seen as an
enactment 'a matter of possibilities for
reconfiguring entanglements'. This does not
involve liberal notions of choice but rather
possibilities and accountabilities, 'including the
boundary articulations and exclusions' inherent in
these practices. As to how agency works, that is a
matter for the 'specificity of the particular
practices', although we can consider 'the space of
possibilities' [surely infinite?] .
Butler was wrong to suggest that agency requires
'a clash of apparatuses' [the 'contradictory norms
of femininity']. Instead, there is no need for a
clash of apparatuses 'because intra-action is to
begin with never determining, even when
apparatuses are reinforcing'. They entail
exclusions which 'foreclose determinism'. However
once determinism is foreclosed, free will is
limited [about time this was recognised]. This is
a better way of thinking it instead of an
opposition between determinism and free will,
which follow each other like cause and effect.
People need to talk about causality again for
example trying to find out causal relationships
behind clusters of cancer in particular populated
areas, for example to identify local
contaminations. There are different kinds of
causalities. Intra-action helps us rethink those.
Intra-action is not just a neologism moving from
interaction, it is instead 'the new understanding
of causality itself' (55).
Agency 'is about response – ability', possible
mutual response. This requires us to attend to
power imbalances. Agency means the possibility for
'worldly configurings', as enactment. Nonhumans
are involved. The point is not to democratically
distribute agency to humans and nonhumans, because
'there are no agents per se'. Specific
interactions show us power imbalances in a field
of forces. We miss this if we localise agency in
human subjects alone, and we cannot take account
of the power imbalances it involves. For example
she found an article on avian flu and the 'bio –
geopolitics of potential flu pandemics'(56). The
analysis looked at 'agential entanglements of
interacting humans and nonhuman practices'. [looks
like classic ANT]. Governments are surveying
migratory birds and small chicken producers, but
the empirical data suggests other causalities,
like the diffraction patterns of large-scale
poultry production which increases the density of
birds and thus of viruses. Industrial production
and international trade and transport 'are among
the various agential apparatuses at work' (56).
Causality is not interactional but intra-actional
— policy based on additive causes misses key
factors [which can be included in further
interactions, I would have thought]. It would be
wrong just to attribute agency to humans. This
would lead to inadequate counting. Complex
material practices also contribute, which are not
attributable to organisms or people.
Haraway has another example referring to research
by Smuts on baboons in the wild. She began by
keeping a distance from them so as not to
influence their behaviour, as 'the condition of
objectivity', but this prevented her doing
adequate observations because it resulted in
behaviour that looks strange to the baboons. She
had to be responsible instead, and this was also
objective, although it did not require distance.
She learned to be 'completely responsive to the
nonhumans' (57), 'she became a good baboon
citizen' [all the paradoxes of going native, and
engaging in inauthentic relationships because you
are the only one doing research]. 'They left her
alone… Making it possible for her to conduct
research' (57) [very naive].
[D and T]. You stressed diffraction, but how does
that relate to your treatment of Böhr, and other
scientists? You seem to read them 'very
affirmatively', rather than agreeing or
disagreeing. What about the generational
implications among feminists who are keen to avoid
Oedipality relating to Masters and affirming their
creativity, including the way they have negated
other work. How does diffraction steer between
duty to Masters, and [extending] them?
[Barad]. She's glad they have carefully read her
work. She agrees that she is not seeing Böhr's
work as scripture, nor just being a dutiful
daughter. She wants produce something new well
still being 'very attentive'(58 )to Böhr [which is
evading the question really].
[D and T] Gender has been seen as a concept with a
particular 'Anglo – American and linguistic'
legacy. This is sometimes seen as requiring a
rejection of biological determinism or
essentialism, or any fixed sexual ontology.
Guattari himself once said that he and Deleuze do
not speak specifically of sexuality, but rather
refer to desire, to avoid any physiological
reduction. This also involves elements beyond the
individual, in social and political fields Is this
how you see the concept? You do not refer to
psychoanalysis, but rather to physics
[Barad]. She's sometimes been accused of not
talking about women or gender specifically and
thus not being a feminist. She is glad she can now
operate at a new level where 'Eros, desire, life
forces run through everything, not only specific
body parts' (59). Matter is not a substrate for
the flow of desire but is 'always already desiring
dynamism, a reiterated reconfiguring, energised
and energising'. The question is how matter comes
to matter, 'makes itself felt'. This is a feminist
project, even though women might be absent. There
are others who agree — Kirby, argues that 'matter
feels, converses, suffers, desires, yearns and
remembers'. A certain N Davis has also agreed. She
tries to make this 'vivid'in her chapter 7,
although feminists have been less engaged.
Nevertheless this chapter on the physics of things
cannot be assumed to be relevant to humanities or
social sciences. Physics has a broader concern
than is usual. If you work through the issues you
will see there are some 'important ways for
rethinking some key feminist issues about matter
and space and time and so on'.
First a crash course on quantum physics [particles
and waves, two-slit experiments and so on] (60f
— starts with talking about diffraction a
lot more in the macro world, with amplification
and cancelling, and the differences with
electrons. She also talks about another which-slit
device which mounts a slit on a spring [a
gedanken? propsed by Einstein with predicted
contradictory results?] so that any particles
going through impart detectable momentum. Böhr's
argument is that such a mechanism revises the
whole apparatus, 'that the ontology of the
electron is changing depending on how I measure
it', and that this arises because we are taking
the objective referent to be the independent
object, and we should be focusing instead on the
phenomenon. 'When we change the apparatus… We are
investigating an entirely different phenomenon'
{doesn't seem to have a virtual level in there at
all?}].
There are important feminist lessons, which are
already built in. She has taken insights from
feminist theory in order to read them through
physics, including 'going back and seeing if
agential realism can solve certain kinds of
fundamental problems in quantum physics' (62). She
cites 'the fact that it is robust enough to do
that', so feminist theory has important things to
say to physics. She probably made the wrong choice
to publish the results in a feminist book because
this limited the engagement of physicists, but
then 'practices of publishing are always
political' (62) [then stuff on the dispute between
Böhr and Heisenberg, the uncertainty principle
explained by ontological indeterminacy — 'there
are no inherent properties… Before the measurement
intra-action… There are no things before the
measurement… The very act of measurement produces
determinate boundaries and properties of things'
for Bohr.
The dispute was actually resolved, so we can now
'do experimental metaphysics' (63), showing there
is no longer a boundary between physics and
metaphysics or philosophy. The thought experiments
are now technologically possible. They have
'designed out' Heisenberg [and Einstein?]. A laser
beam excites a rubidium atom 'see, there is
already talk of desire in physics!' And when these
enter the which slit detector they revert to their
ground state by emitting a photon, which means no
observer disturbance. This means 'you can now show
that Böhr is right not Einstein'] referring
specifically, I think to Einstein's doubt about
the coherence of quantum physics].
There are 'amazing' implications for
feminists from erasing information [erasure is
actually done by adding a retractable plate which
absorbs the photon]. When this happens, there is a
diffraction pattern. Which might be '"delayed
choice"' — 'I am able to determine its ontology
[wave or particle] afterwards'. Some physicists
have said this means 'we have the ability to
change the past' (65) but this 'a very convenient
kind of nostalgic fantasy' will be a seductive one
— we'd all like to be able to change the past.
However, more careful examination shows that the
original pattern is not being restored, there is
no complete erasure. Implications for time follow
'using the insights from feminist theory, from
poststructuralist theory, and things that Cultural
studies has been telling us' (66) — we are seeing
'the making of temporality', that time is not
universally given but is 'articulated and
re-synchronised through various material
practices', so that time only makes sense in the
context of particular phenomena. 'Physicists are
actually making time in marking time', but past,
present and future are really entangled. We have
discovered 'intra active entanglements' as 'the
only reason we get a diffraction pattern again'.
The old one does not just return, but a new one is
created. So 'the "past" was never simply there to
begin with' but is 'iteratively reconfigured and
enfolded [with present and future] through the
world's ongoing interactivity'. Causality is
interactivity, not the usual billiard ball model.
This produces 'possibilities for reparation'
rather than erasure. We cannot undo the past,
although the past and the future 'is not closed'.
The past is open to change and it can be
'redeemed' (67). It does have 'sedimenting
effects', though, which cannot be erased,
and this memory 'is written into the world'.
Schrader argues this in the pfiesteria paper —
showing that 'time is differently
made/synchronised through different laboratory
practices. She argues that memory is not a matter
of the past, but recreates the past each time it
is invoked'.
This is the sort of thing she has learned from
diffracting quantum physics and feminist issues.
This shows her passion is grounded and [also?] based
'in questions of justice and ethics' (67). She has
brought 'an important materialist sense of
Derrideann notions of justice to come' [followed
with the Derrida quote about how the past has
never been present, while justice involves
responsibility, both to ghosts and to those not
yet born] [so is this still an interview?].
Overall she thinks responsibility 'entails in our
active engagement of segmenting out the world in
certain kinds of ways and not others'. We have to
be attentive to this process because 'each
intra-action materially [is] redoing the material
configurations of spacetimematter' (68) we are
alway reworking past present and future, which
'says that the phenomena are diffracted and
temporality and spatially distributed across
multiple times and spaces', which requires a
different sort of understanding of social justice
as well as causality. She has not just learned
something from physics 'and applied [it] to
feminism', there is 'something [more] fundamental
'(68).
[D and T] Post-humanist theories are said to lack
an ethics, and a connection with physics will
emphasise this. Your ethics is central, as in your
post humanist performativity material, although
that also seems to imply 'cases in which meaning
can be nonmaterial, idealistically travelling
through space while not being affected by matter',
something not entangled.
[Barad]. For her, 'questions of ethics and of
justice are always already threaded through the
very fabric of the world', with mattering (69).
Matter and meaning 'cannot be severed'. Matter is
an expression or articulation of the world 'in its
interactive becoming' and bodies come to matter
through this activity or performativity.
'Boundaries, properties, and meanings' are also
differentially enacted. Differentiating does not
just refer to radical exteriors, but also to
'agential separability', not othering or
separating but 'connections and commitments'.
Ethics is not about responding to a 'radically
exteriorised other' but rather about mattering and
responding to mattering [actually 'the ability to
respond'], 'an obligation to be responsive to the
other, who is not entirely separate from what we
call the self' if we think ontology, epistemology,
and ethics together, the world is 'always already
an ethical matter' [almost a tautology].
[D and T] you are in the same post Kantian boat as
Badiou and Meillassoux , and this must involve
revaluing various disciplines without 'falling
into the traps of disciplinary, multidisciplinary
team, interdisciplinarity or post disciplinarity.
[Barad] I'm not writing a manifesto. Haraway meant
her manifesto ironically. Agential realism is not
a manifesto because it does not assume everything
can be made manifest. It is instead 'a call, P, a
provocation, a cry, a passionate yearning for an
appreciation of, attention to the tissue of
ethicality that runs through the world'. Ethics
and justice are at the core of her concerns, and
run 'through "my" very being, all being' (70). We
do not just add ethics — it is 'the very nature of
what it means to matter'.
Barad page
|
|