Brief notes on: Nietzsche, F. (1989) On The
Genealogy of Morals.Trans Walter Kauffman and RJ
Hollingdale, edited anxd with a commentary by
Walter Kauffman.New York: Vintage Books.
Dave Harris
[These notes very brief because it is very
difficult to summarise in any detail this
collection of essays. They get increasingly
like a hysterical rant as you read through them.
They are very repetitive, and just really potty,
with all sorts of ridiculous projects announced,
such as finding physical causes for psychological
beliefs. The second main problem is that I
just cannot relate to this material very
well. I suppose I've grown up thinking that
Nietzsche is some kind of crypto fascist.
Despite the efforts of the translator, and,
Deleuze, of course, I cannot shake off rumbling
undercurrents of fascism. There are the
notorious phrases like the 'blond beast', who
represents real, vigorous, manly men, and the
increasing tendency to see the poor and resentful
as threatening to contaminate the rest of us with
their sickness. I am aware that fans of
Nietzsche want us to read these pieces
differently: the blond beast is not meant to refer
to the Nazi version of the Aryans; Nietzsche is
critical of Germans as of anyone else, because
they have also been corrupted by weakness [but
then Hitler said pretty much the same, and with
similar volkisch themes]. More generally,
obviously the whole style is ludicrously
exaggerated for polemical effect, and it is quite
amusing to see Christianity or community activism
rebuked like this].
This lack of sympathy (and experise) has had a
particular effect of my notes.They express my
rendition of Nietzsche's arguments in my words,
not his,except for quotes. This is important if we
know that these texts have been picked over and
interpreted one word at a time. You will be in no
position to argue what Nietzsche actually meant by
his choice of individual words or phrases if you
rely on these notes -- read the stuff for
yourself, as always
The main themes for me, appearing quite reasonable
in the first essay and then get more and more
wacky, turn on what we currently take to be the
basis of our morality, which is being kind to
people less fortunate than ourselves, sacrificing
ourselves for others, and generally insisting on
our own humbleness in the face of god.
Nietzsche will have none of this. He starts
by saying that the ancient words for 'good'
referred us to nobility, aristocracy, the
honorable doings of great men. The sea
change, that these people are now culpable, and
their victims the very repository of virtue,
indicates the extent to which resentment has
developed. Nietzsche uses the French
spelling, of course -- ressentiment.
Of course, Christianity is one or the worst
examples, but Nietzsche sees this as an offshoot
of Judaism any way. He is mixed about
orthodox Judaism from what I can see, sometimes
admiring its energy, and indeed attacks anti
semites, including one Eugene During. It is
the Christian legacy [a trick played by Jews
almost] which he objects to, which offered a
message to the poor and oppressed - not to blame
themselves, but to blame others for their plight.
Some of the best barbs are directed again the
religious , including Luther, whose critique was'
fundamentally the attack of a lout who could not
stomach the good etiquette of the church', keeping
the voices of louts out (145). We find 'Humility
and self-importance cheek-by-jowl...it is plain
that there is no trace of good breeding. How can
one make such a fuss about one's little
lapses...Who gives a damn? Certainly not God'
(144). Ascetics generally get mocked, as does
anything that lacks moderation and thus opposes
good manners. [Blond beasts doubtless had
impeccable manners].
In the end 'nausea' awaits -- people are sick of
themselves and their little lives [apparently the
theme of Sartre's Nausea, Kauffman says].
In more modern times, social policy aimed at
working with the poor can also be seen as based on
resentment, and there is a psychological pleasure
in helping people worse off than yourself in that
it makes you feel slightly superior -- this
provides the merest glimpse of the will to power,
doing something useful (135) These people suffer
from having Hegel's 'beautiful soul' --an
idealized view that everyone is beautiful in the
own way. Ultimately, community activity is only a
way of deadening pain.
Science has also been corrupted by asceticism and
become a 'means of self-narcosis', partaking of
this claim to be rooted in suffering. Secularists
of all stripes are the same -- too severe, too
'hectic', still having faith in a [limited] truth
(150) . They can still affirm some world beyond
the material or some other higher purpose -- but
if that is a world created by God, they are
mistaken [because God is dead]. The point is to
explain the will to truth, which itself involves
radical fearless critique. That is missing in
modern science,which is actually a 'hiding place
for every kind of discontent' (147).
Generally, the whole approach is psychologically
appealing, Nietzsche argues, and there is no
surprise that it caught on, but at the terrible
expense of wanting to drag everything down to its
own level, arguing that any sort of excellence in
any field was suspicious, and had to be based on
exploitation [so we can see several digs at
Marxism as well]. There is no higher noble purpose
to it all. As a result, civilization itself
was in peril, and no one dared to do anything
anymore. What we need is a return to rigour,
proper manliness, which will make even women
happy, critical thinking, daring to say that the
emperor has no clothes, and 'fresh air'. We must
desire suffering and its deeper philosophical
meaning: the ascetic interpretation of suffering
causes more suffering, and results in hatred of
the human, a desire to escape from it all, a 'will
to nothingness, an aversion to life' (163), but
still a will: man would rather will nothingness
than not will'.
OK - -some more detail:
The work was inspired by reading The Origin of
Moral Sensations by Dr P Ree, an altruist. N
opposed it root and branch, not to refute but to
submit something better,more probable.It was tried
out in Human All Too Human. It led him
back to Schopenhauer who had also valued
'pity,self-abnegation,self-sacrifice' (19), a
rejection of life.This was the 'great danger to
mankind' , a morality of pity and nihilism.
By comparison, most philosophers did not think
much of pity or its value [including Spinoza and
Kant]. Once we start to think critically
about this 'pernicious modern effeminacy of
feeling' (20) we realize that this morality grows
in particular conditions and circumstances, and
can be their 'mask...
tartufferie'. The new prospect opens to
better morality offering 'the highest power and
splendour actually possible'. The history of
morality will help. It needs to be
approached with cheerfulness or 'gay science'
(21). It helps if people have read Zarathustra,
but N expects to be misunderstood.
The first essay: good and evil, good and bad
The English psychologists are at least
interesting, by bringing shame into the foreground
and discussing its evolution, instead of covering
up. They may even be acting in a good
spirit. However, their approach is
unhistorical, and their genealogy based on a false
premise - that good originally meant altruistic,
and that subsequently proved itself to have
utility. However, the good people, the
nobles or the most powerful created the first
conceptions of what was good as a result of the
distance from the plebeian. This had nothing
to do with utility, more with feeling, tightly
developed as linked to aristocratic value
judgements. Only when these declined did
altruism come to the fore, more as a result of
'the herd instinct' (26), again originally seen as
something opposite to morality. Spencer at least
had a better idea, that good meant useful or
practical in the first place.
This was wrong as well, but etymology came to the
rescue, and showed that the terms for good were
always associated with noble or aristocratic,
privileged, and it is this that there has been
overlooked in favour of 'the democratic prejudice'
concerning origin. Etymology shows us that
the ability was associated with virtue and truth,
someone who possesses reality, 'as distinct from
the lying common man' (29) in the words of one
classical Greek poet. The Latin term malus
was always associated with darker colour, black
haired men, pre-Aryan occupants of
Italy. The Gaelic also indicates that 'the
Celts, by the way, were definitely a blond
race'(30). All over Europe, the oppressed
race has regained the upper hand, and we can see
the move towards democracy as 'a tremendous
counter attack'. Unfortunately the
'conqueror and master race, the Ayran' (31) is
succumbing.
Given that the ruling caste was often a priestly
caste, we see developing a religious sense of good
and bad, pure and impure. Purity originally
meant simply someone who washes themselves and
avoids contamination by food, blood or 'dirty
women of the lower strata' (32), but these
distinctions soon developed into something
unhealthy, the physical decline of the priestly
caste, and asceticism, 'the entirely
antisensualist metaphysic', their valuing of
nothingness or union with god. However
the notion of the soul did at least help to
distinguish man from animals. Physicality
separated priestly from warrior castes, the latter
practicing 'a powerful physicality, a flourishing,
abundant, even overflowing health, together with
that which serves to preserve it: war, adventure,
hunting, dancing, war games, and in general all
that involves vigorous, free, joyful activity'
(33). Priests tried to build their power on
impotence and hatred.
The Jews offer 'the most notable example' of
priestliness which involved inverting the values
of their enemies in 'an act of the most spiritual
revenge' (34). The Jews said in effect that
only the wretched are good, only the suffering
pious and blessed by god. They are
responsible for 'the slave revolt in morality'
which has eventually completely triumphed.
That we have not seen so is because it took 2000
years to develop, and was disguised in terms of
the growth of love. That love grew out of
Jewishness, 'by the same impulse that drove the
roots of that hatred'(35). Jesus of Nazareth
offers a seductive form of Jewish values,
permitting 'sublime vengefulness', 'part of the
secret black art of truly grand politics of
revenge', even claiming its offshoot as a mortal
enemy. The people have won and overthrown their
masters, but this victory is 'at the same time a
blood poisoning (it has mixed the races together)'
(36) It doesn't matter if we call this being
'Judaized, Christianized, mob-ized'. Only
lately has it attempted to hold back the more
repellent aspects of modern taste.
The slave revolt is based in resentment -- ressentiment
[Kauffman in his Editor's Introduction
says that he uses the French term, partly as a
matter of style, and it was subsequently taken up
in psychology and philosophy]. The slave
revolt is based on negation not affirmation,
saying no to anything different, including
anything outside. It assumes 'a hostile
external world', and it works by fundamental
reaction. Noble valuation, by contrast is
affirmative, 'filled with life and passions
through and through' (37). Of course the
noble valuation can lead to mistakes and
misunderstandings, even be contemptuous, but it is
still better than the serious falsifications of
slave morality, 'submerged hatred, the
vengefulness of the impotent'. The ancient
Greeks were positively benevolent about the lower
orders, seeing them as just unhappy. Their
own happiness did not have to be established by
contrast, nor did they divide happiness from
action. In slave morality, happiness is more
'essentially narcotic' (38) and passive. The
man of ressentiment 'is neither upright nor naive
nor honest and straightforward with
himself'. They do honour cleverness as a
means to importance, as opposed to 'unconscious
instincts', or 'enthusiastic impulsiveness' which
can produce recklessness. However, the noble
never take adversity or enmity seriously for very
long. The noble conception of good is
acquired in advance and spontaneously before
thinking of what is bad. Slave morality
thinks more of evil, as a matter of
ressentiment. All enemies are seen as
evil.
When the noble encounter something outside and
strange they are 'not much better than uncaged
beasts of prey' (40), free from all social
constraints, acting with a freedom that
compensates, but they can still return, showing an
innocent conscience. This combination makes
them 'the splendid blond beast' at their core,
with a need occasionally to go back to the
wilderness and the animal. [There is a
concerted effort in the footnotes to deny that
this meant the Nordic mythical races praised by
the Nazis, Teutons. It really relates to the
lion in Zarathustra, Kauffman
argues]. The noble races are responsible for
the dualist concept of a barbarian, as in Pericles
noting both Greek virtue and wickedness. The
display of such barbarism can be found among
Romans, Arabs, Germans, Japanese nobility, the
Homeric heroes and Scandinavian Vikings. It
explains indifference to security and safety,
'hair raising cheerfulness' (42). There was
also the 'raging of the blond Germanic beast' (42)
[which undoes some of the apologetic stuff?]
some sort of memory of the goths or vandals
perhaps, 'although between the old Germanic tribes
and us Germans there exists hardly a conceptual
relationship, let alone one of blood'.
Seeing culture as a reduction of the beast to a
docile man would validate ressentiment as a good
cultural device. For N, however, this is
'the regression of mankind' (43) something itself
oppressive, thirsting for revenge. It is
right to 'fear the blond beast at the core of all
noble races', but that is better than admiring
'the repellent sight of the ill constituted,
dwarfed, atrophied, and poisoned'. Tame
[middle class?] men already see themselves as the
higher man, and we no longer fear him. He is
at least better than 'the surfeit of ill
constituted, sickly, weary and exhausted people of
which Europe is beginning to stink today'.
It is awful to contemplate these people, and to
maintain hope: there is only 'a subterranean life
of struggle', but it does at least yield moments
in the light, even 'one glance of something
perfect, wholly achieved, happy, mighty,
triumphant, something still capable of arousing
fear!' (44). The 'diminution and leveling of
European man is the greatest danger' , and it will
get worse and worse 'more Chinese more
Christian'. We are weary of humanity: this
is nihilism.
Of course the noble are predatory, but they should
not be reproached for that any more than in
nature. Strength must be allowed to express
itself, to overcome, to triumph. Absurdly,
weaknesses now seen as strength. 'Drive,
will, effect' is what is crucial, not
'a"subject"', which is been falsely abstracted as
a concept. There is only 'doing, effecting,
becoming; "the doer" is merely a fiction added to
the deed'(45). The notion of the subject
persists even in scientific analysis of force or
causes, as when the atom is treated as a subject,
for example. In political terms, the notion
of the subject means that 'the strong man is free
to be weak' and can be accountable or blamed if he
is not. To argue that the good man is
someone who does no harm and desires little from
life is in effect to argue that the weak should do
'nothing for which they are not strong
enough'(46). This is reasonable enough, but
it now appears as a virtue, resignation, as a
voluntary achievement, or 'meritorious act'.
It is necessary to believe in some independent
subject for this, or the soul, and this accounts
for the popularity of the ideas.
We need a proper account of how ideals are
actually made. The proper observer could see
sweetness overlaying weaknesses and impotence,
lowliness being transferred into humility,
patience appearing as virtue, inability to act as
unwillingness to act, a celebration of suffering
and misery, as something which eventually will be
rewarded. This helps the lonely claim they
are somehow better than the mighty and better
off. The whole thing 'stinks of so many
lies' (47) there are also people who develop the
arguments in for these transformations, themselves
'full of vengefulness and hatred', concealing
their ressentiment, acting they say in the name of
justice, not revenge, and praying for the last
judgement. Their day will come: they call it
'"the kingdom of god"'(48). It will offer
eternal compensation and indemnity. What
looks like Christian love is really eternal hate:
Aquinas promised the saved that they would be able
to witness the punishment of the damned to
increase their best. There has always been
cruelty as a part of Christianity [followed by a
long quote from Tertullian on the delights of the
last day, when kings and governors are burned,
philosophers shamed, and non believers tormented].
Good and bad, good and evil have been at the heart
of struggles for thousands of years, and although
the weak have dominated, there are still
signs of the battleground. In recent
history, the big struggle is between Rome and
Judea. Jews were condemned as unnatural
haters of humanity, and Roman aristocratic values
were seen as counterposed to theirs However,
the Book of Revelations shows a delight in
vengefulness by the Jews. By some inversion,
Christians came to see the Bible as the book of
love. The struggle is between the strong and
noble, and those driven by a priestly
ressentiment, admittedly equipped with 'an
unequalled popular- moral genius' (53), which made
the Jews a particularly gifted nation, at least
when compared to the Chinese or the Germans.
[Classic ambiguity again here - is this admiration
or an even stronger reason for hating them?
Is it enough to counterbalance the charge with
despising the Germans?]. Eventually,
Christianity was to conquer Rome.
The Renaissance helped to revive the classical
ideal to some extent, and even 'Judeaized
Rome'(54) revived itself a bit. However, the
reformation, the 'thoroughly plebeian (German and
English) ressentiment movement' put paid to Roman
catholic revival [oddly that is also seen as a
triumph for Judea]. Judea triumphed in the
French revolution, attacking 'the last political
noblesse in Europe', driven by ressentiment,
especially its 'mendacious slogan... "
supreme rights of the majority"'. The only
opposition came from the curious figure of
Napoleon, a new noble ideal, a 'synthesis of the
inhuman and superhuman'.
The struggle might still flare up again. We
must desire with all our might to go beyond good
and evil [plug for his book]. In a note, N
hopes that linguistics and etymology might be used
more to explain the evolution of moral
concepts. So might physiology - every moral
value 'requires first of all a physiological
investigation and interpretation, rather than a
psychological one' (55). [The reasoning
behind this cranky idea is that what survives as a
useful moral principle is really helping to
prolong the survival of a race, again an example
of how popular opinion might be thwarted in
advocating the well being of the majority].
Second essay: guilt and bad conscience
Human beings are able to make promises, but this
also involves them in forgetting as a positive
form of repression, which is responsible for us
not noticing most of the things that we
experience. We must attempt to become aware
of new things, especially the 'nobler functions
and functionaries' (58) 'for our organism is an
oligarchy'. We need to forget in order to
achieve any happiness, and if this repression is
damaged, we 'cannot "have done" with
anything'. The opposing faculty is the
memory, essential in particular to remember
promises. It involves active desire to
continue to desire something, 'the real memory of
the will'. However, this also involves
disattending to any distractions, being able
to think causally and anticipate, being
regular, and calculable. This explains the
origin of responsibility. It implies a
system of 'morality of mores'(59), and this
explains the prehistory of human being. The
culmination is 'the sovereign individual, like
only to himself, liberated again from morality of
custom, autonomous and supramoral', conscious of
his own power and freedom, possessing a free
will. Such a man deserves respect and a
feeling of superiority: he has mastered himself
and this 'necessarily gives him mastery over
circumstances' (60) [sounds like the headmaster at
my old grammar school]. It lends him
distinction. He is confident that he can
maintain his character in the face of accidents or
fate. This necessarily brings content for
'the feeble windbags... the liar'.
This combination of power and responsibility has
become instinct, and appears as conscience.
Conscience takes a variety of forms, however, and
this sovereignty of the self is developed only
late. Earlier on, it had to be developed in
ways that were 'not precisely gentle', like
burning something into the memory, using pain to
jog memory, developing cruel religious
rites. This is still effective. This
is the history of asceticism, making ideas
unforgettable, repressing everything else.
Even the Germans, no longer cruel, used these
techniques to breed their own nation of thinkers
and civil trust, to 'master their basic mob -
instinct and its brutal coarseness' (62) [some
nasty examples are listed]. Current levels
of reason and seriousness have been developed from
these practices.
What about bad conscience, guilt? These are
actually worthless, something merely modern, not
based on the past. Guilt actually originates
in the notion of debt [etymologically that
is]. It is modern in the sense that it was
not always possible to distinguish intentional
from accidental practices. The notion that
criminals could act differently is 'an extremely
late and subtle form of human judgment' (63), and
punishment used to be imposed not because someone
was personally guilty, but in the sense that
injury must be paid back through its equivalent,
the 'contractual relationship between creditor and
debtor'.
These contractual relationships could take a
repugnant form, to instil that kind of memory
necessary for prices, to instil a sense of duty or
obligation. Creditors could torture the body
of the debtor, cutting from it an equivalent to
the debt, and there was even a system of legal
evaluation of the value of different limbs or
parts of the body. What is actually gained
for the creditor is pleasure at being able to
'vent his power freely upon one who is powerless'
(65), the enjoyment of violation. It is
particularly satisfactory if the creditor is able
to dominate someone of higher rank, to share for a
while the right of the masters.
This is where all the apparently moral notions of
guilt consciousness duty and so on have their
beginnings, 'soaked in blood thoroughly and for a
long time'. Cruelty still abounds, even in
Kant's categorical imperative. Making
someone suffer was pleasurable 'in the highest
degree', often leading to a genuine
festival. Modern men like to resist such an
analysis, but even Spinoza knew that malevolence
was 'a normal quality of man', which did not
trouble the conscience. People were able to
laugh at cruelty and thought that 'to see others
suffer does one good' (67). Life was more
cheerful in that era of cruelty, and there was no
shame 'at man' (67) or disgust with life.
These developed later following 'morbid
softening and moralization', so that life
became repugnant, and a Pope even listed all the
repellent aspects of the flesh [67].
Perhaps pain did not hurt as much then as it does
now, and we can see this with doctors who have
'treated Negroes (taken as representatives of
prehistoric man)' (68). Susceptibility to
pain seems to vary according to social class as
well. Animals might suffer, but this is
'negligible compared with one painful night of a
single hysterical blue stocking'. Suffering
can be senseless, but there is a whole Christian
mechanism to explain that it is really a sign of
salvation. So to abolish knowledge of
suffering, men had to 'invent gods and genii', to
justify it. Life became 'an epistemological
problem' to explain evil, perhaps as a
demonstration of the power of the gods for the
ancient Greeks, where human wars were
festivals. Later, those same gods saw
suffering as involving moral struggle and
heroism. The notion of human free will
provided additional spectacle, 'the idea that the
interest of the gods in man, in human virtue,
could never be exhausted'(69): full determinism
would have been boring.
The relation between creditor and debtor
represents some initial human relation, the first
encounter [sounds like Locke now]. These
relations were so important that they dominated
thinking, and produced the first feelings of
superiority in relation to other animals.
'Man designated himself as the creature that
measures values' (70). These basic rights
got transferred into social complexes and customs,
and gave thought a direction, proceeding to the
'great generalization "everything has its price;
all things can be paid for"', and the notions of
justice which emerged to produce
settlements. The earliest notions of
community also emerged from this process, and with
it, the first notion of the outsider. Any
breaking of promises to the community would invite
repayment, irrespective of the actual harm caused:
it was breaking the contract with the community
that produced the problem and it would lead to
being deprived of community benefits, exile or
outlaw. This mimics the rights of war over
defeated enemies, and indeed, war 'provided all
the forms that punishment has assumed throughout
history' (72). As the power of communities grow,
the threats from individuals are less serious, and
the community takes on the role of mediator
between criminal and victim, bringing with it the
notion that some discharge of guilt is
possible. There is still internal isolation,
but the general moderation of punishment, even to
the extent of ignoring crimes like debt, in the
name of mercy (which is still a privilege of the
most powerful).
Ressentiment is less powerful as an origin of
justice, and it 'blooms best today among
anarchists and anti semites' (73), something
hidden. It can resurface by arguing that
revenge is required in the name of justice, as a
reactive affect. This can be seen as rooted
in biology. Generally, ressentiment offers a
'nuance of scientific fairness' in the name of
hatred, jealousy, or revenge. However, such
scientific detachment soon evaporates, especially
with affects that are even more important
biologically - lust for power, avarice.
Duhring bases his notion of justice on these
reactive feelings. However, far from
originating justice, they are the last to be
conquered by it. But at the same time, the
ideal of objective and indifferent justice should
not be believed in too readily, and 'aggression
malice or insinuation' (75) soon dispels it, even
for the most 'upright'. Indeed, active
aggression and arrogance is closer to justice than
just reacting, because no 'false and prejudiced
view of the object' is required. The
aggressive man therefore has a better conscience,
and the man of ressentiment has to operate with
bad conscience.
Law has been administered best by the aggressive
and strong rather than the merely reactive.
Only a strong commitment to justice can end 'the
senseless raging of ressentiment among the weaker
powers', and settlements can be imposed.
Mere 'grudges and rancour' are replaced by the
administration of law in general. This
replaces personal feelings based on injury as
technical offences against the law, in a more
impersonal evaluation. So it is the
institution of laws are brings about the modern
notions of justice. Nothing is unjust in
itself, since life itself features 'injury,
assault, exploitation, destruction' (76).
Legal conditions are therefore exceptional to
biology, and offer a partial restriction 'of the
will of life, which is bent upon power'. It
can only prevail by creating 'greater units of
power'. Any legal order that prevented all
forms of struggle [advocated by Duhring,
apparently --is this the same one criticized by
Engels?] would be 'hostile to life'.
The origin and purposes of punishment are
separate. The usual approach takes the
purpose of punishment as its origin, and this is a
general methodological flaw that prevents us from
looking at 'the cause of the origin of a thing'
(77) [you're not going to get to it by
ranting!]. Something, once it has appeared,
is classically put to new ends, transformed 'by
some power superior to it', subdued, and this
applies 'to all events in the organic
world'. [N uses the term 'becoming
master']. Utility can not be used to deduce
origins [we are close to deterritorialization
here]. If something is a purpose or utility,
this is a sign that 'a will to power has become
master of something less powerful', and the signs
may appear as chains, linked by what can look like
'purely chance' [so there is no chance for
N? Merely unexplained interpretation by the
powerful?]. Evolution is not a matter of
logical or real progress towards a goal, but a
succession of subduings, resistance, and partial
transformation. It is hard to establish a
central meaning for such fluidity. This can
applied to the evolution of organisms as well,
including their partial destruction as a species,
which is 'among the conditions of an actual progressus'(78),
some will to greater power pursued at its
expense. The will to power replaces a
historical mechanism, pure fortuitousness or
mechanical senselessness. It is senseless
for us to oppose domination and to hate rule and
government, even though this appears to take a
spiritual form, and even to permeate objective
science, including physiology. What is
missed is 'the fundamental concept... of
activity', and its replacement by adaptation, 'an
activity of the second rank, a mere reactivity'
(79), as in Spencer. The will to power is
the essence of life, however, and 'spontaneous,
aggressive, expansive, form-giving forces' are
central.
Punishment has a relatively enduring element, a
certain drama in its procedures but its meaning
and purpose or expected outcome is more
fluid. Again we should suspect from our
'historical method',[ha! transcendental deduction
at best] that some deeper force lies beneath
the procedures: these have not just been invented
to enable modern forms of punishment.
Certainly the meaning of punishment has changed
considerably, and now contains a synthesis:
indeed, it is impossible to say why people are
punished these days. We could detect the
original synthesizing and entanglement, and see
how they have undergone shifts in value, for
example when deterrence overcame all the other
elements. But there are still uncertain and
even accidental meanings, which include a way of
rendering someone harmless, offering recompense,
restoring equilibrium, inspiring fear as a
deterrent, exacting repayment, expelling a
degenerate [the example is Chinese law apparently,
where the aim is to preserve 'the purity of a
race'], punishment as a festival, as a way of
instilling memory, moderation of revenge, or a
declaration of war. Punishment is 'over
determined by utilities' (81), meaning that
utility alone cannot explain it. The main
value is to make the punished feel guilty,
prolonging and extending the notion of bad
conscience. However, 'all conscientious
observers are agreed' that prisons only make
people 'hard and cold', alienated,
rebellious. If it leads to diminution of the
vital energy altogether, that's even worse.
History tells us that punishment actually hinders
the development of feelings of guilt, prevents
criminals from reasoning about their own actions,
especially if the state demonstrates the same kind
of unthinking violence, or works by bribery and
deception.
The bad conscience is a recent and imported
development anyway, and the guilty persons were
expected to experience pain only when encountering
punishment. Spinoza discuss the problems
when thinking of the 'sting of conscience', having
already proposed a kind of materialism which
avoided notions of good and evil and the
omnipotent god. He saw the importance of an
unexpected sadness, and this has been important
for criminals in the past, who explained to
themselves that something has gone wrong, not that
their moral compass is faulty. They submit
to punishment just as the rest of us do to other
misfortunes, with 'stout hearted fatalism' [the
quality which the Russians apparently still
have]. If anything, punishment heightened
prudence and caution, as a kind of self criticism
of earlier weakness. Punishment tames people
rather than making them better. Luckily, it
also makes people stupid.
The origin of the bad conscience to N is 'the
serious illness that man was bound to contract
under the stress of the most fundamental change'
(84), that of living in society and at
peace. All previous instincts were devalued
and suspended. All orientations and guides
failed, leaving only consciousness. At the
same time, the old instincts were still making
demands, although they could rarely be humoured
directly: instincts turned inwards, 'the
internalization of man', the development of a
soul. This proceeded to the extent that
external discharges were inhibited [sounds like
Elias and the civilization thesis].
The 'instincts of wild, free, prowling man'
(85) were turned against man himself.
Men reacted to this 'oppressive narrowness' of
custom, like animals rubbing against the bars of
the cage, 'this fool, this yearning and desperate
prisoner became the inventor of the "bad
conscience"', but this produced 'the gravest and
uncanniest illness'. Nevertheless, this new
notion of the human soul provided so many
contradictory possibilities that divine spectators
were needed. For the first time, men were
'included among the most unexpected and exciting
lucky throws in the dice game' played by Zeus or
chance. Man becomes a source of potential
and promise.
The change involved took place as a 'break, a
leap, a compulsion' (86), even before the
development of ressentiment. Violence was
always involved, not only in oppressing, but also
in forming people. The state is seen as
'some pack of blond beasts of prey', or master
race, organized for war, able to impose its will
on a populace. The notion of some original
contract is sentimental. Command was always
decided by violent mastery. Such people
appear 'as lightning appears, too terrible, too
sudden, too convincing, too "different" even to be
hated'. They are able to impose something
new and give it new meanings. They do not
operate with notions of guilt and responsibility,
but rather with an artist's egoism. However,
bad conscience is an unintended consequence,
something latent, arising from the repression of
the instinct for freedom.
This is not to be totally condemned, because it is
the same active force that we find in the form of
the instinct for freedom '(in my language: the
will to power)' (87), although applied to other
men. [cf Foucault on the affirmative aspects of
power]. This force involved contents and
negativity, even joy in making people suffer,
itself something that will produce further
suffering as an active bad conscience. The
activity involved is also the source of 'all ideal
and imaginative phenomena... strange new
beauty and affirmation' (88). This is
perceived as a delight by those with bad
conscience, although, 'this delight is tied to
cruelty'. So altruism emerged only from bad
conscience, itself the result of 'the will to self
maltreatment'.
'The bad conscience is an illness', but only in
the sense that pregnancy is an illness. One
implication of the original relationships between
debtor and creditor has come to be interpreted in
two notions of the relation between the present
generation and its ancestors. With 'the
original tribal community', duty towards earlier
generations was recognized, and the sacrifices and
accomplishments of the ancestors had to be repaid
with sacrifice and accomplishment. As more
people die, the debt grows greater, especially as
the ancestors confer more and more benefits.
Sacrifice is never enough and eventually becomes
excessive. The fear of the ancestor
increases, just as the power of the tribe
does. Conversely, social decline diminishes
fear of the ancestors. This produces
division between the different tribes [some
lunatic origin of stratification on the national
or racial level? This is implied on
page 90 where struggles between the gods are
supposed to be worked out in terms of struggles
between nations and races, with universal empires
promoting universal divinities]. Soon the
powerful ancestors will become gods, with no need
for piety as a human instinct. However,
later noble tribes developed by reproducing the
qualities that the gods themselves were supposed
to possess.
Back in primeval times, communities developed 'on
the basis of blood relationship' (90), and also
developed orders of rank. The burden of
unpaid debt led to the development of 'dependent
populations', including slaves, who acquired this
'guilty feeling of indebtedness' from their
masters. The Christian god is 'the maximum
God attained so far' and therefore has the most
indebtedness. If Christianity declines
further, so will all guilt feelings are, and
atheism will eventually dispel these notions of
guilt altogether and inaugurate 'a kind of second
innocence' (91). Yet this is far away, and
current reality is still penetrated by the bad
conscience. As that develops, it aims at the
impossibility of ever discharging debt. As a
result, this aim is also internalised in the form
of the bad conscience and a duty, the notion of
'irredeemable penance'[Deleuze likes
this bit and refers to it as 'the judgement of
god' -- Artaud uses the actual phrase].
However the creditor too is burdened with a curse
of original sin, or of evil nature, or of mere
pointless existence, as in 'Buddhism and the like'
(92). The Christian idea that god sacrifices
himself for our guilt, out of love, means that
human repayment can never be sufficient.
The result is self torment and inward cruelty,
driven to 'is most gruesome picture of severity
and rigour', guilt about animal instincts, the
sense of imperfection before God, a denial of
self, 'God the Judge', torments without end.
Humans actually will to find themselves guilty,
they will themselves to be unable ever to
discharge the guilt, and will themselves to create
an ideal in god, becoming 'this insane pathetic
beast—man!' (93). Prevented from accessing
his real beastliness, he develops mental
beastliness. This is sickness, and 'Too
long, the earth has been a madhouse!'. This
is how 'the "holy God" originated'.
There are better uses 'for the invention of gods',
as we can see by looking at Greek gods, who
reflect 'noble and autocratic men', with their
real animal nature. This led to rejoicing in
freedom, staving off bad conscience. They
saw all human beings as led by 'foolishness,
not sin!'(94). Evil behaviour resulted from
being deluded by a god - the gods took on the
guilt.
This could be seen as just knocking down
ideals. But ideals always cost: lies have to
be sanctified, consciences disturbed. One
ideal has to be sacrificed if another is to
flourish. Modern men have long practiced
self torture, seeing their natural inclinations as
evil, and no one is strong enough to reverse all
this. Even the good men would oppose it, as
well as 'the comfortable, the reconciled, the
vain, the sentimental, the weary' (95).
Revealing the origins of all this gives offence,
and it is much easier to go along with what the
world does. Opposing these conceptions
requires 'a different kind of spirit', something
unlikely in the present age. It requires the
experience of adventure and danger, 'the keen air
of the heights', the 'self confident
mischievousness in knowledge that goes with great
health' (96). Indeed, it is precisely a
matter of health. One day in the future a
redeeming man might appear, able to confront
reality not flee from it, able to redeem it from
the curse of the bad conscience, a 'man of the
future', abolishing the current ideal, and all it
produces, 'the great nausea, the will to
nothingness, nihilism'. This man will be
'AntiChrist and antinihilist... victor over
god and nothingness'. Nothing more can be
said because only this man, Zarathustra [thank God
-- I thought he meant Hitler!] has the right to
speak, 'Zarathustra the godless'.
Third essay: ascetic ideals
The ascetic means different things, something
spiritual, an additional charm in women who are
otherwise 'a plump pretty animal' (97), or a
licence for power in the case of priests, a lust
for Glory. It really arises from horror of
the vacuum, in that human will needs a goal, even
nothingness. Let's take the example of
Wagner who became chaste in his old age, but
before combined chastity and sensuality [all seems
to turn on the work he did on Luther's
wedding]. There's always been a balance
between animal and angel, but only 'swine who have
come to grief' worship only chastity. Why
should Wagner celebrate such swine? Perhaps
it was a joke [Parsifal], a tragedian
laughing at himself? That is a better option
than someone who has turned on the senses, or
returns to 'morbid Christian and obscurantist
ideals' (100).
It is better to separate the artist from their
work, seen as something that grows out of some
dubious soil. We should see artists as
people of spirit, not as ordinary aesthetic
men. In artistic labour, just as in
biological labour, there are repellent
aspects. Nor should artists be confused with
their characters. They operate instead
separated from the real or the actual, and this
can cause problems with their 'innermost
existence' prompting a focus on the actual.
Perhaps it is that artists often display
'velleity' ['weak volition'].
Thus in artistic terms, asceticism is of no value
and amounts to nothing. Artists are too
dependent on the world generally, and this reduces
the value of their own stances, which are always
affected by some existing 'morality, philosophy or
religion' (102), or by the need to flatter their
patrons and other powers. Wagner had to prop
up his position using Schopenhauer. But what
did Schopenhauer, and other philosophers, who are
independent, get out of asceticism?
Schopenhauer had a particular stance towards art
[in particular, he seemed to value music as
something independent, 'not offering images of
phenomenality as the other arts did, but speaking
rather the language of the will itself' (103).]
This helps the musician turn into some kind of
priest, 'a kind of mouthpiece of the "in itself"
of things, a telephone from the beyond'.
[Deleuze and Guattari seem rather guilty of
this] This will inevitably lead to asetic
ideals.
Schopenhauer based his position on Kant on
aesthetics, which originally included a prominent
place for knowledge, impersonality and
universality, taking the point of view of the
spectator. However, this assumed that the
spectator would have possessed personal experience
of , and 'surprises and delights' (104) in, the
aesthetic. However, normally the spectator
is seen quite differently, as lacking such
experience, and as possessing definite
interests. We can see this when considering
Stendhal who suggested that spectators are always
anticipating promised happiness, and thus are not
disinterested. The kantian position does
seem absurd when men are expected to view statues
without interest, making Kant as naive as a
' country parson'. Schopenhauer interpreted
the notion of being without interest in a personal
way, as a liberation from sexual interest, and
from general considerations of merit and utility,
a form of redemption from the will [to lust after
women]. His position can be seen simply as
'a generalisation from... sexual experience'
(105), affected by prevailing social
customs. [N quotes from some of his work
apparently showing a delight in being released
from the torments of life]. Thus
Schopenhauer was expressing a personal effect of
the beautiful, in calming his particular will, but
this should not have been generalised: Stendhal
was just as sensual but perhaps better adjusted,
and saw that beauty arouses the will. The
discussion shows how for some philosophers, the
ascetic meant a release from torture [by the
senses].Schopenhauer had to use exaggerated words
like torture, to see women as instruments of the
devil, because he needed enemies in order to keep
up his spirits: he would not have persisted
without them. We could see happiness in this
case taking the form of anger.
This actually is fairly typical of
philosophers who do display 'irritation at and
rancour against sensuality' (106). Every
animal, including the philosophical animal,
attempts to maximize favourable conditions in
which they can expend their strength and achieve a
feeling of power. Everything that obstructs
this attempt is abhored. It is the search
for power not happiness that is important.
Philosophers rarely marry, for example, and even
Socrates 'married ironically'(107). Family
ties are seen as fetters, something oppressive;
avoiding being housebound, and entering the
desert seems the sign of a strong spirit.
Asceticism is therefore the optimum state to allow
philosophers to affirm their own existence above
all.
Philosophers often attempt to free themselves from
as much constraint as possible, including the
'gnawing worm of injured ambition' (108), and
asceticism helps them float above life.
Poverty, humility and chastity are always
associated not with virtues, but 'as the most
appropriate and natural conditions of the best
existence'. The love of life and luxury was
refused. Philosophy still claims asceticism
as a kind of 'dominating spirituality', but 'there
is thus nothing of "virtue" in this' (109).
It is an imagined desert they seek, sometimes
referring to themselves. [Deleuze and
Guattari take note] There are camels however
[Kauffman tells us this is a joke, since a camel
is a silly ass in German]. Being in the
desert means avoiding all the distractions of
noises, newspapers, even a job, preferring to
associate with harmless beasts, even an ability to
'go unrecognized'[become imperceptible], and to
talk to ordinary people. Above all, it means
avoiding 'everything to do with "today"',
everything that does not require the soul to
defend itself. It is better not to speak
aloud, since only orators do that, not thinkers,
people who seek out audiences and are unsure of
themselves.
Philosophers avoid 'fame, princes, and women'
(110), and harsh daylight. They want to to
avoid having to think of themselves, as a kind of
maternalism. They subject themselves to a
'supreme lord'[philosophy]. They avoid
enmities and friendships as distracting.
They do not wish to be martyrs. They avoid
big words [not the ones I read, matey!] for
example 'truth' which 'sounds too grandiloquent'
(111). Chastity leads to the search for
'little immortality' elsewhere. It is not
real chastity any way, simply the result of their
will and the need to devote all their energy to
the work. We can see Schopenhauer in this light,
with the beautiful releasing the energy of his
will towards contemplation. There might have
been a little aesthetic or sensual pleasure, but
the second is really the basis of the first, and
so Schopenhauer has not risen above the
sensual. [At this point, N says he will be
exploring the 'physiology of aesthetics' in more
detail, but Kaufman tells us that he never did
except in the form of hints].
So asceticism in a particular form seems to
combine with will and spirituality, and this is
why philosophers have always been fond of
it. Philosophy began initially as something
unsure of itself. All its acclaimed virtues
- an ability to doubt, deny, suspend judgment,
analyze, while remaining neutral - originally
flouted morality and notions of reason.
Philosophy seemed to be something forbidden.
We could apply all this to the things of which we
are proud today - it can all be seen as
hubris. We use to hold as honorable the
opposite of things we value today, such as our
attitude to nature, the inventiveness of
technicians, the concept of god 'as some alleged
spider of purpose and morality behind the greater
captious web of causality' (113). We seem to
enjoy even experimenting with ourselves, and even
try to 'vivisect our souls' driven by a curiosity:
in a strange way, those that make us sick are more
necessary than those who cure us.
Everything is reversed. Marriage was once
seen as something selfish and antisocial, claiming
a woman for yourself. People used to be
ashamed of mildness; they pursued the justice of
the vendetta and had no time for the power of law,
itself seen as something violent to which we had
to submit . Modern feelings of reason and
freedom were paid with suffering and
martyrdom. But the earlier 'morality of
mores' formed the human character [sic].
Contemplation was originally despised, and had to
go in disguise. This turned into a 'fear of
oneself' (115) [making ordinary people fear
philosophers was a strategy to both 'fear and
reverence' the self]. The community
distrusted them. Earlier philosophers had to
employ a cruelty towards themselves in order to
overcome the traditions, going through hell to
build a new heaven. Disguise took the form
of appearing as more acceptable or contemplative
people, like priests. Philosophers had to be
ascetics, and to believe in asceticism, to pose as
someone world-denying. It is doubtful if
this has changed in modern times.
Asceticism became associated with seriousness, but
that needs to be investigated too, including by
physiologists. It is such a strong
association that attacking asceticism runs
risks. However, ascetics find it difficult
to defend themselves. The key issue is the
valuation to be placed on life with all its
becoming and transitoriness. The ascetic
'treats life as a wrong road' (117). This
has actually been widespread in our history [which
seems to contradict the gloriously joyful
affirmative life described just above?].
There has long been pleasure in disgust at
oneself, pleasure in inflicting pain. The
ascetic priest appears everywhere, and so looks as
if he is universal: asceticism is not confined to
one class, race or family. Somehow,
asceticism must be formed out of 'the interest of
life itself', although it seems totally opposed to
life, seeking power over life itself, a 'force
to block up the wells of force' (118).
It is a kind of perverted capacity for life,
something paradoxical because the more it denies
life itself, the more it achieves its own life
goals.
If we force ascetics to justify themselves
philosophically, they will identify error
'precisely where the instinct of life most
unconditionally posits truth', downgrading
physicality and any other aspect of reality
[including the antithesis between subject and
object]. It must end in a notion of the
realm of truth which excludes reason. Kant
himself comes close to this since the
intellect is limited, and some things are simply
incomprehensible. However, it is valuable to
gain 'a variety of perspectives and affective
interpretations in the service of knowledge'(119),
and we can at least reject some fictions such as
the notion of a pure, timeless subject without
will, and notions of pure reason or '"knowledge in
itself"'. These conceptions ignore 'the
active and interpreting forces' which guide
perception and knowledge. 'There is only
a perspective seeing, only a perspective
knowing', and we can gain complete grasp of the
concept of the thing only by considering 'more
affects...more eyes, different eyes'. We can
not simply eliminate the will altogether.
The apparent contradiction that asceticism is a
life against life really means that the ascetic
ideal relates to preserving a 'degenerating
life'(120). It is a struggle between this
older form and everything that is new. It is
an expedient. What is really happening is a
struggle through death against death. The
popularity of asceticism shows the prevalence of
the sickly or tamed man, their disgust with life,
but also the struggle against exhaustion. Ascetic
priests want to be different, in a different
place, but this very desire makes them captive,
and this leads to the ambition to construct the
'whole herd of the ill constituted, disgruntled,
underprivileged, unfortunate' of whom they can be
the shepherds. In this way asceticism denies
life but also conserves and creates it.
Everything depends on the prevalence of sickly
men. Man is restless and daring compared to
all the other animals, and his 'own restless
energies never leave him in peace', and he is
always oriented to the future. Periodically,
man indicates that he has had enough, become
nauseous, weary, disgusted with himself [the
example is the dance of death in the 14th
century], but even this produces a new compulsion
to live. Sickliness is normal, and so we
need to protect in particular those who can still
demonstrate 'great power of soul and body'
(121). Strong men are not to be feared, but
those that produce nausea or pity are. If
ever the two qualities were to unite, they would
produce a will to nihilism, and there are some
signs of this union developing, signs of the
madhouse or the hospital in the cultural
domain. The weak undermine everything
including trust, they burden us with sadness and a
sense of failure. Vengefulness and rancour
thrive, secrets and concealment, conspiracy of the
suffering against the well, hatred of the
successful. All this is disguised under a
display of 'grand words and postures', false
submissiveness and humility, claims to represent
only justice, love and wisdom. They claim to
represent best virtue, claiming to be the good and
the just, the only men of goodwill. They
tried to reproach others who are the healthy and
strong as if they have done something wrong for
which they will have to pay - and the weak 'crave
to be hangmen' (123). They are only too ready to
judge. They often appear as beautiful
souls. They can display 'deformed
sensuality', combined with purity, but they are
'moral masturbater and "self gratifers"'.
Sick women are especially dangerous: 'nothing can
excel her in the wiles to dominate, oppress and
tyrannise... She will dig up the most deeply
buried things'.
We see the struggle of the sick against the
healthy everywhere, in families and in
organizations. Occasionally sickness appears
as loud moral indignation, something pretending to
be noble. We find it even in science, as in
the work of Duhring, 'the foremost moral big mouth
today', (124) him and the other anti
semites. They all show ressentiment, they
yearn for subterranean revenge, which they hope to
gain by giving us all a bad conscience, making the
fortunate ashamed. This must be opposed, and
the fortunate should not doubt the right to
happiness. The healthy should not be made
sick. Instead, the sick should be segregated
from the healthy, in the interests of the
future. Above all we need fresh air and good
company, 'our company!' (125). The healthy
should not even nurse the sick - they should be
tended by 'doctors and nurses who are themselves
sick'.
The ascetic priest offers dominion over suffering,
he tends to the sick although he is sick himself,
but must also be strong with his own will to
power, so that he can organize the sick and defend
them against the healthy. He must naturally
despise anything that looks 'rude, stormy,
unbridled, hard, violent beast of prey, health and
might' (126). If he is to fight the beasts
of prey, he has to represent a new kind of animal
himself, animal ferocity. Sometimes he will
need to pass among the strong appearing to be like
them, but possessing more mysterious powers so
that he can sow discord where he can. He
cures the wounds of the sick, but infects them at
the same time. He even defends the herd
against itself, struggling against anarchy and
disintegration which ressentiment constantly
causes. He alters the direction of
ressentiment.
It is common to blame someone else in order to
relieve the suffering. This is the promise
of ressentiment, helping to deaden pain by
arousing affect. This can be seen in
defensive retaliation, but mainly in avoiding
further pain, driving pain out of consciousness by
replacing it with an even more violent
emotion. This trend to blame others might
have a physiological origin too [with some
quackery]. The sick themselves are inventive in
this matter. They've come to enjoy being
mistrustful, dwelling on nasty deeds, scouring the
past to deepen their suspicions and intoxicate
themselves with malice. The old wounds are
opened. Enemies are found everywhere.
What the priest does is to encourage them to
eventually blame themselves, however.
This project requires the use of words such as
guilt, sin, or damnation. Self blame is
useful [functional?] to prevent excessive social
damage by the vengeful. Of course this will
not cure the sickness. The sick will be
concentrated and organized '(the word "church" is
the most popular name for it)' (128), with the
separation of the healthy, even a chasm between
them. It follows that sinfulness is not
itself a factor but an interpretation of
'physiological depression' through the religious
or moral perspective. In particular, feeling
guilty is no proof that you are right: convicted
witches felt guilty. Even psychological pain
involves an interpretation of causes, not even
physiological ones. It is more a matter of
being well constituted enough to deal with
experiences, even tough ones: those who suffer
have a kind of moral indigestion. Although
physiological processes are implicated, N still
wants to be 'the sternest opponent of all
materialism'(129).
Priests are actually poor physicians, because they
do not address the real causes. However, the
religious perspective is extremely flexible, even
a matter of genius, in the way in which it offers
consolation in such variety and subtlety.
Religion generally arises because from time to
time 'a feeling of physiological inhibition' (130)
spreads among the populace, and remedy is sought
in psychology or in morals. The inhibition
might arise 'from the crossing of races too
different from one another (or of classes—classes
always also express differences of origin and
race'. Mixed classes in particular explains
the characteristic European Weltschmerz.
Emigrating to a foreign country can also produce
it, so can 'exhaustion in the race', incorrect
diet, or 'degeneration of the blood' (131) in
malaria or syphilis.
General displeasure is resisted in several ways:
first by reducing 'the feeling in life in
general', reducing expectations, promoting
abstinence, making oneself stupid. This
appears in moral terms of selflessness, and in
physiological terms as hypnosis, something like
hibernation. This can work to really free
yourself from depression, but at the price of
'spiritual disturbances' (132) such as experiences
of inner light or hallucinations and so on.
These dubious explanations are enthusiastically
propagated. The final stage of redemption
itself can produce repose at last. It is
treated as a great mystery, a liberation from
illusion, truth, release from all nasty desires or
actions, something beyond good and evil as in
Buddhism. In a way, these beliefs are true,
realistic, because hypnosis works. You can
gain redemption through increasing your virtue,
say in Indian philosophy, but N has less support
for the notion of spiritual union as a dreamlike
state [Indian religion is cited here quite a
lot]. Nevertheless, a hypnotic absence of
suffering obviously takes a positive value and can
easily be seen as 'the positive as such' (134).
[Oh dear I am wearying of this ranting
stuff. Never mind. Nearly through]
Intellectual stoicism is also a form of training
against depression, which at least involves
activity, as in work becoming a blessing [he
doesn't mean nasty manual work of course].
You fill up your consciousness with mechanical
activity, regularity, obedience, routine, a
certain impersonality. You can also engage
in 'petty pleasure' as a medication (135), in the
form of doing good to others helping your
neighbour. This is a typical activity of the
ascetic priest, because this is is a life
affirming drive in a way even if a cautious one -
it is still 'the will to power' combined with
feeling happy about slight superiority. It
is certainly better than hurting each other.
Christianity began like this in the Roman world,
as a matter of mutual aid, assistance for the poor
and the sick, attaining this petty pleasure.
Actually combining into a herd is the next step, a
significant advance against depression, and the
source of new interests for the individual so that
they can get away from themselves. Belonging
to a herd overcomes a feeling of weakness, and
this is realized by priests. Coming together
like this provides genuine enjoyment for the weak,
unlike those actions of the strong which are
strictly aimed at satisfying a will to power
without organization: this is how oligarchies turn
into tyrannies.
All the means of developing love of neighbour and
herd instinct, can be seen as innocent means
deployed by priests, but there are more guilty
ones, usually in the form of 'an orgy of feeling'
(136). Priests build upon enthusiasm, but we
should not deal with euphemism
['tartuffery']. Innocence and moralized
forms of speech often conceal mendaciousness, and
proper psychologists [philosophers] have to face
this even if it means a greater nausea. In
the future, we will see these modern developments
as displaying 'moral mawkishness and
falseness...innermost feminism that likes to call
itself "idealism"' (137). It is not that
educated people actually tell lies, because this
would insist that they distinguish the true and
the false. Instead, most people claiming to
be good have to engage in dishonest
mendaciousness. We can see this with
biography, and how difficult it is to write about
oneself honestly. We can also see catholic
reactions to the reformation [in Janssenism]
as overly simple and bashful, apologetic about
Luther. Ranke [usually called a positivist
historian] represents a classic type of a modern
man, prudent and realistic. However, it is
difficult to shake and mistrust of ourselves ['us
psychologists', that is, 139], since we are still
infected by contemporary morality. For
example we wrongly learn to mistrust first
impulses.
Now we can proceed to examine the real affects of
the ascetic ideal in producing orgies of feeling,
so intense as to alleviate all gloom and
depression. All the great affects can do
this, and all have been pressed into service,
under a religious interpretation and justification
of course. These orgies are always pursued
with a good conscience, even though they usually
lead to subsequent increases in depression.
The main technique involves playing on a sense of
guilt, which gets exaggerated by priests into sin
and given a religious interpretation, becoming so
oppressive that men have to turn toward sorcerers
or priests for counsel: the answer always is to
seek the cause in themselves, which only confirms
their dependence on the priest.
The invalid becomes a sinner, and they are
everywhere, with no attempt to understand
suffering, always with a bad conscience, which
often becomes 'morbidly lascivious' (141), leading
to punishment of the flesh. People even seek
more pain, hair shirts, torture chambers,
endlessly inventive punishment, all justifying the
ascetic ideals of the priest. It is doubtful
if any of these are orgies of punishment actually
benefited anybody, certainly not in the sense of
improving people, more like taming them,
emasculating them, making people even sicker,
adding 'a shattered nervous system' to existing
illness. After waves of repentance, we get
'tremendous epileptic epidemics' like St Vitus's
dance in the middle ages, hysterical outbursts,
'death seeking mass deliria', destruction.
'The religious neurosis appears as a form of
evil'(143) because the asetic ideal and its moral
cult produces orgies of feeling 'under the cover
of holy intentions', and has left indelible
marks. This is 'the true calamity in the
history of European health', as bad as alcoholism,
which the Teutons have spread, or as bad as
syphilis.
Health has been ruined and so has taste, for
example in taking the Bible as the 'basic book of
Christian literature'. This book became
promoted against all the old classics, and even
claimed to be able to replace them, even the
literature of the Greeks. The new testament
is actually dislikable, although this requires
courage to say so. The old testament is
different, more heroic, a celebration of the
strong heart. In the new testament there is
'nothing but petty sectarianism, mere rococo
of the soul, mere involutions, nooks, queer
things, the air of the conventicle not to forget
an occasional whiff of bucolic mawkishness'
(144). It offers a combination of humility
and self importance, vehemence rather than
passion, 'embarrassing gesticulation; it is plain
that there is no trace of good breeding'.
Why are routine petty lapses so important - 'who
gives a damn? Certainly not God.' Why do
these 'little provincial people' want
eternal life? Does the 'Heart of
Being'really concern itself with them? Can
God really be invoked in the most petty
troubles? This is a sign of appalling taste,
'this perpetual familiarity with God! This
Jewish and not merely Jewish obtrusiveness of
pawing and nuzzling God!'[Tell it like it is
Friedrich! Don't hold back mate!]. Some
despicable pagan nations display more tact in
reverence, not even sounding the name of their
god. Compare this with Luther the peasant
and his tone on the saints of the church and the
Pope, 'the attack of a lout' (145), wanting some
typically German form of discourse with God,
informal and direct.
Asceticism has never produced good taste or good
manners, because it lacks a sense of
moderation. Asceticism has ruined many other
things, too many to enumerate. It has come
to power, it has been allowed to flourish and not
resisted. It should have been opposed by
another will expressing an opposing ideal.
The ascetic ideal wants to become universal,
denying or rejecting any other interpretation and
submitting to no other power. What can match
it? Science has been conquered by it,
despite having the potential courage and will to
oppose. However, this is developed in a
superficial way, and 'today the scientific
conscience is an abyss' (147). Practicing
scientists actually do not believe in science[as a
way of life] , and take the form of the ascetic
ideal after all [as we see below] . Scholars
similarly tend to be only 'modest and worthy
labourers', happy with their lives, 'content with
things today' especially with science and its
applications. There is no overall goal or
will. If anything, science 'is a hiding
place for every kind of discontent,
disbelief...bad conscience'; it lacks ideals, and
practice conceals this lack behind 'heedless
industry'. In this sense science becomes 'a
means of self narcosis'. Scholars often are highly
sensitive and easily wounded, posing as sufferers
refusing to admit to themselves what is going on,
refusing calls for them to regain consciousness.
But there are some counter idealists and
unbelievers, although they still rely on a strong
faith in something pretty improbable. Of
course they offer strength and support, but 'we
deny that faith proves anything' (148), and any
strong beliefs should be suspected.
[Kaufmann adds in a note that this refusal to
question everything is what is objectionable to
Nietzsche - but of course he has to accept some
premises, even if it is only the benefits of
questioning everything]. Intellectual
cleanliness, severity, and abstinence is what
characterises these atheists, sceptics and anti
Christians [he also calls them ephetics, meaning
people who suspend judgement]. Some can be
redeemed because they do at least retain an
intellectual conscience, [whereby they simply
cannot believe things without good reason, and the
most noble men and women still retain such
conscience, as do the occasional free
spirits]. However, even these free spirit
still have faith in truth. Much better were
the order of assassins, who apparently believe
that '"nothing is true, everything is permitted"'
(150) [the everything here presumably includes
rape and murder?], but few Europeans or Christians
have ever got that far. European free
spirits remain unconditional in their faith in
truth, and this makes them as rigid as anyone
else. Philosophical abstinence and
intellectual stoicism expresses the 'desire
to halt before the factual' (151), to indulge in
petty fatalism [which can also be translated as
powerlessness in the face of petty facts.
This comes over in French scholarship as 'general
renunciation of all interpretation' underneath
which is the asetic ideal, the belief in
'metaphysical value, the absolute value of truth'.
Science can never operate without presuppositions,
but this makes it 'paralogical' (152) in that it
must operate with some basic faith to direct it
and give it the right to exist. It would be
absurd to place philosophy on a scientific basis
for this reason. That is why in Gay
Science, there is a section that says that
it is necessary to pursue scientific truth by
affirming 'another world than that of life, nature
and history', which in turn means denying the self
sufficiency of this world [this would be good for
Deleuze, though, to go beyond objectivism?], and
embracing metaphysics. It is necessary to
question the very foundation of disbelief,
especially if it involves faith in God.
Science certainly requires justification, and this
is a difficult question and may have no
solution. Even the will to truth itself
requires justification. That this has been
little explored so far shows the power of the
asetic ideal with God as the ultimate source of
truth. Once we deny this, there is a major
problem concerning the value of truth. In
particular, 'the value of truth must for once be
experimentally called into question' (153).
This is argued further in Gay Science. So
science is not the natural antagonist of
asceticism, because it requires some notion of
value itself, so that it can believe in itself in
the service of some greater power. Science
opposes all the appearances and exteriors of
asceticism, like its dogmas. However,
together, science and asceticism strengthen the
same foundation, the overestimation of truth:
'they are necessarily allies' and must be called
into question together.
With art, it is different, because there there is
an open lie and will to deception, but with a good
conscience. The points have been already
argued in the discussion of the opposition between
Plato and Homer [in Birth of Tragedy].
Physiologically sciences and the ascetic ideal
both embrace 'a certain impoverishment of life',
with lower levels of affect, slowed down tempo,
'dialectics in place of instinct' (154),
seriousness. When scholars are at the
forefront of social life, this is always a sign of
exhaustion and decline, 'the predominance of
mandarins always mean something is wrong; so do
the advent of democracy, international
courts...equal rights for women, the religion of
pity'. Science is the best ally of
asceticism because it is unconscious and
involuntary. Both emphasize the poverty of
spirit [both are called 'hectics', which Kaufmann
tells us means consumptives]. Scientific
victories, for example in astronomy, merely helps
to make the asetic ideal more elusive, stronger,
even more spiritual.[N thinks his own philosophy
will escape? -- rather ironic in the
circumstances?]
Perhaps it is that as life itself becomes more
'arbitrary, beggarly, and dispensable' (155) in
the current social order, the possibility of a
transcendent solution to the problem of existence
is less desirable. Belief in the dignity of
man, his 'irreplacability in the great chain of
being' has been diminished and man has become a
mere animal. The acceleration into self
belittlement is the 'straightest route to'
asceticism. All science, including non
natural science ['the self critique of knowledge']
dissuades human beings from respecting themselves,
seeing it as 'bizarre conceit' (156). The
self contempt produced by science no longer works
against the ascetic ideal. Philosophical
victories over dogmatic theology [including Kant],
have failed to budge transcendentalism. They
have actually provided a 'secret path' towards
transcendentalism and asceticism, this time with
scientific respectability, and placing the
responsibility on personal initiative.
Agnostics are no better, since 'they now worship
the question mark Itself as god', admiring
the unintelligible instead of just admitting that
it might be unknown. The argument is
still that everything in normal society and
life both fails to satisfy desires, and even
contradicts them. However, the solution lies
not in desire but in knowledge. In effect,
there is a nonsensical syllogism: '"there is no
knowledge: consequently - there is a god"'.
What about modern historiography? These days
it rejects teleology, refrains from judgment, and
'considers this a sign of good taste' (157).
It puts description at its peak. This is
both ascetic and even nihilistic. The
historian surveys the past as an Arctic explorer
surveys the wilderness. More modern
historians want to flirt both with life and with
asceticism, posing as an artist. They are
worse than ascetics. Duhring gets it in the neck
again for his display of the latest incarnation of
the beautiful soul [advocates of which are further
defined as an anarchic species 'within the
educated proletariat']. Contemplative
armchair historians are worse [other popular
historians of the time are cited]. These
offer highly selective commendations of episodes
in history, which offend both taste and patience
and encourage voyeurism. [With a sarcastic
aside about the Greek poet who worshipped the
wonderful limbs and organs of animals - Nietzsche
says god also gave him a foot to kick out at this
rubbish]. It is worse to conceal the asetic
ideal with coquettishness, to generalize to
infinity, to aspire to wisdom and
objectivity. People who do so are 'at bottom
only tragic buffoons'(158). They include
anti semites, who use cheap rhetoric to rouse the
'horned beast elements in the people'with their
moral attitudes and their 'Christian - Aryan -
bourgeois manner'.
The German diet is dominated by 'newspapers,
politics, beer and Wagnerian music' (159) and this
leads to national vanity, belief in Deutschland
uber alles, and paralyzing modern
ideas. Europe tday seems to need ever
better stimulants, 'this most potent brandy of the
spirit', and this produces a 'repulsive,
ill-smelling, mendacious, pseudo alcoholic air
everywhere'. All the quacks, forgers and
sham idealists need to be exported to regain fresh
air. These ideas can even be made into a
business, with the project of idealizing the the
whole earth. It would not even require
courage.
Leaving aside these curiosities, the problem
remains to deal with the ascetic ideal, and this
is to be done in subsequent works including Will
to Power. At the moment, the only
threat to the ascetic ideal comes from the
comedians of it, who arouse mistrust.
Everywhere else it is triumphant. It even
masquerades as atheism, but that is simply a
disguise of its ideals. The kernel remains
the will to truth: this is not some remnant from
the past. Proper 'unconditional honest
atheism' (160) is not the antithesis of
asceticism, but one phase in its evolution.
'2000 years of training in truthfulness' means it
is deeply forbidden to deny a belief in god.
The same might be said for the development of
Indian religion, where original challenges were
made into a religion themselves [Nietzsche almost
gets close to Weber here on the need to develop a
practical work ethic,and again fails to foresee
his own value for practical Nazism]
The only thing that can conquer the Christian god
is found in Gay Science. Here it is
argued that Christian morality has penetrated all
notions of thought, and so everything becomes
interpreted as a sign of the goodness of god, the
existence of a moral order. However, such
views are now clearly seen as belonging to the
past, out of tune with modern conscience and
experience, seeming these days increasingly as
'indecent, dishonest, mendacious, feminism,
weaknesses, cowardice', at least to those with a
more sensitive conscience. We can rely on
everything to end in its own destruction, to
overcome itself, to see self-overcoming as in the
nature of life itself. There are always
contradictions to be opened, for example in
demanding that Christian leaders operate Christian
ethics themselves. Christian morality can
destroy Christian dogma and will itself be
overcome, once it properly articulates the
question that is lurking: 'what is the meaning of
all will to truth?' (161). What would happen
if this became a problem? Morality as we
know it would perish, and this is going to happen
in Europe for the next two centuries, producing
spectacles that are terrible but also perhaps the
most hopeful.
The ascetic ideal gave man and meaning that raised
him above animals. Men could not answer the
question of their own existence, since they lacked
their own sense of will. Asceticism filled
the void. It gave people answers and stopped
them suffering from this particular
uncertainty. As a result, man even came to
desire suffering, as long as it could be said to
have a meaning. The meaninglessness of
suffering is the main problem confronting human
beings, and asceticism offered a plausible
meaning, the best one in the circumstance.
It helped people interpret suffering, offered a
way out of 'suicidal nihilism'(162). The
interpretation brings additional suffering of its
own, however, all the tortures produced by
guilt. Nevertheless, it appeared to save man
by giving him a meaning, a sense: a will at least
within limits. The consequence was 'hatred
of the human, and even more of the animal...horror
of the senses, of reason itself, this fear of
happiness and beauty, this longing to get away
from all appearances, change, becoming... a
will to nothingness, an aversion to life'.
This only goes to illustrate that 'man would
rather will nothingness than not will'(163
back to social theory page
back to Deleuze page
|
|