Notes on:
Valentine, J. (2005) 'Ranciere and
Contemporary Political Problems'.
Paragraph 28 (1): 46-60.
Dave Harris
[Discusses the more political texts such as On
The Shores of Politics and Disagreement:
Politics and Philosophy. Also cites a
useful looking text by Zizek (2000) The
Ticklish Subject: the absent centre of political
ontology. London: Verso].
There is a relation between political philosophy
and politics, since each sees a struggle between
an 'originary unity', and 'persistence of conflict
and division'(46). R thinks that philosophy
has put an end to the political as a separate
area, because the two now coincide exactly.
This is seen in the idea of 'the police' which
maintains individuals in particular allocated
places: R's philosophy sees that [conventional]
politics as an activity does this too, so that his
philosophy is the basis of a new kind of
politics. The argument is intended partly to
deny that philosophy is somehow an underlabourer
compared with politics.
Politics in this sense refers to 'irreducible
conflict' between the police on the one hand, and
something which always resists it on the other,
the '"part which has no part"', the prolific
people who live and work outside the symbolic
order [sounds very much like De Certeau]. The
police order is constantly limited or exhausted in
its efforts to fit everything within its symbolic
orders. Valentine sees this as a difference
between a mathematical notion of equality, where
'each is one and only one', and a geometrical
principle which introduces hierarchy, where some
ones are more important and powerful than
others. The symbolic order represents this
hierarchy, and tries to demonstrate that 'each one
finds its place [only] within the unity of the
One' (47). R wants to restore
mathematics. He also refers to notions of
'"the non place as place"'[which seems to be like
the empty square in Deleuze's
account of structuralism - this empty square
is the only thing that produces novelty and
innovation inside what is otherwise a well ordered
structure]. R also invokes an older language
to refer to the Greek ochlos, 'the
turbulent, disruptive and indeterminate mass' as
opposed to the demos [that fraction of the
mass that is involved in politics?]. The
existence of the ochlos 'demonstrates that the
demos is not one or One'.
This implies that the political in R's sense
arises from something which cannot be symbolized,
or if it is, only as something anonymous [empty
category]. It is perhaps even necessary if
some categories are to be brought into some
symbolic order [maybe the argument is that the
symbolic order itself depends on there being some
notion of political rule]. However, this
implies that political disagreement is only a
matter of objection to being overlooked or
misnamed [describes modern identity politics?],
which means less than a fair share of advantages:
this is the 'relational notion of the political'
and it implies that it can be dealt with simply by
renewing some consensual notion of recognition.
This is apparently the view by Deranty of R's
politics -- originating in a denial of recognition
by the dominated. However, there will be a
problem because recognition will involve losing a
disruptive status and [appearing as a conventional
subject, something interpellated?] accepted into
the symbolic order merely pragmatically, not as
'"ontological entities"'(48). [what we're
talking about here is legitimized otherness?
Valentine sees them as poised between integration
and outsiderness 'Not one and not the other'].
However, this implies that the political is no
longer ontological and symbolic, but rather
'aleatory'. In other words, it is no longer
just a matter of access to the symbolic
order. Zizek offers a critique of R along
with Badiou, Balibar, and Laclau and Mouffe - all
share an Althusserian legacy. R risks
problem with marginalist politics,
[probably] something to do with consisting
of momentary outbursts which are excessively
radical and which must fail to undermine the
existing order. If the political is to be
radical, it must stay marginal 'as the
demonstration of its own authenticity', but this
means it actually needs the police order to define
itself as something that it opposes.
However, totally subverting the order is
'"proto-totalitarian"'. Mathematical
equality 'needs a place within' geometrical
hierarchy after all, for Zizek. [I think the
implication is that all normal relational politics
does as well].
Can a 'new positive symbolic order be established
instead'? (49). It might start by
recognizing that the existing symbolic order is
[arbitrary], produced by 'a prior political
moment'. The argument would then be to
struggle over 'which one is the better One'.
Valentine says that R seems to assume some
miraculous coincidence between a political moment,
establishing the authority of the symbolic, the
capacity of the police to maintain it, and 'the
philosophical elaborations which support it' [I
think this is R's position - it is not clear if
Valentine means R or Zizek, or Zizek's reading of
R ].
Zizek assumes that the symbolic order is necessary
to reproduce social order, although it also
produces 'pathological consequences'. What
the symbolic order does is to connect to the
general with the particular [then a strange bit
where Zizek somehow merges Hegelian
romanticism with Durkheimian anthropology].
The symbolic order appears as an objectivity which
is misidentified as subjectivity, relying on
Lacan. Ideology is therefore necessary and
eternal, just as in Althusser.
However, R criticises
Althusser precisely for trying to reconcile
historical materialism and bourgeois sociology in
this matter, relying on Marxism itself to deny any
eternal structure in which the subject is linked
to a system of representations.
Nevertheless, the later material on politics is
ambiguous.
R gives three reasons for the development of
politics: in the naming of things itself,
especially in a naming of the people; in the
selection of groups to represent the people
because they are always too numerous to appear
completely; in the attempt to relate the name of
the people to the name of the community itself, or
rather to manage the split between the community
and the part of it that is the people [my gloss on
a quote from R (50)]. In this schema, the
people become both the community and only a part
of it. Another contradiction is that the
economy of signs once established offers many
'possibilities of signification' and can never
close off its own privileged ones. The issue
is whether this is an ontological
contradiction. R seems to imply that the
last development 'interrupts' (51) the first
two—the division in the last aspect of politics is
not logically implied by the symbolic order, nor
is anything which lies outside of it and which is
not symbolized. As a result, a grievance
relying on the second contradiction is not
logically predictable. It might arise if we
see, for 'metaphysical' reasons, seeing some
necessary connection between non symbolization and
social division. Alternatively, the
empirical example itself shows us the weakness of
the symbolic [as a counterexample] and questions
its ontological status—'symbol is subordinated to
allegory'.
The last option is suggested by R's argument about
the third reason for politics. R borrows an
argument from Lefort about the origin of modern
politics and its connection with earlier notions
of monarchy. It all turns on the
'circularity of divine right'—the King is both the
temporal and spiritual leader, and people owe the
King allegiance just as they owe allegiance to
God, a classic 'geometrical role of order'(51):
[the idea of a community united under God] offers
both mathematical and geometrical notions of
equality. However, it is not that the King
is somehow doubled: instead, a political order is
required to show the distinction between spiritual
and temporal properties and how they are
linked. The link will seem arbitrary,
however, and the king's body will always be
split. It is a politics that adds the
arbitrary dimension, not something internal,as in
double embodiment. Politics also introduces
a distinction 'between the symbolic and the real'
by making a necessary distinction between
spiritual and physical, which renders both of them
as 'empty markers without positive properties'
(52). Lefort says that in modern politics,
power necessarily appears as something empty,
exercised by mere mortals who have occupied
positions of power rather arbitrarily. There
are no fixed laws beyond contestation, no
foundations. Gap or emptiness can not be
symbolised, 'because it is a literal event which
symbolises nothing'. The exercise of power
can therefore not be simply symbolic either, and
politics becomes merely a polemical discussion of
'the symbolization of power'. This might be
a democratic virtue, although it can also turn
into 'the totalitarian menace' involving a
resymbolization of power. To prevent this,
'democracy is all about preserving the gap between
the symbolic and the real'.
R amends this argument by examining the attributes
of the people not just the institution of the king
[through the contradiction between part and
community?]. However, this still doesn't lead us
to a political struggle over power and
authority—why would this contradiction produce
grievance? The issues seems to be that this
division is never named. Somehow, the
'spontaneous experience' of living together
becomes a symbolic order of its own and this
'reveals the difference between the name and its
referent, the general and the particular'[I am not
at all sure why, except that people can perceive
the difference between the actual communities in
which they live and the phony invocation of
community by national politicians?] The political
constantly attempts 'a polemical relation' (53)
yet this somehow 'reveals the difference between
either of these names' [so apathy wold result,
surely, as often as rebellion?] .
|
|