Sociology
of
deviance: Social Disorganisation Approaches
Introduction
This file begins with
discussing
the issue of deviancy - some general points need to be made first about
the awful problems presented by any attempt whatsoever to study
deviancy,
crime or delinquency. The problem really at base is one of
attempting
to be scientific about a very ill-defined issue. Defining
deviancy
presents acute problems - do we take common-sense, legal, or official
definitions,
and can this be done 'objectively '. Definitionial problems produce
appalling
methological difficulties as a result - many studies rely upon samples
of those actually convicted and sentenced (and these may be atypical
deviants
in several important ways -- what of those who commit crimes but are
never
caught and sentenced, for example?).
There are also lots of
naively established
correlations between sentenced deviants and psychological or social
characteristics
- and commentators are too ready to infer that one set of variables
('broken
homes', too much violent TV etc) cause the other ('crime'). Before we
can
do this, though, there are the usual problems to consider. Correlations
are not causal relations -- factors may operate in different
directions,
so that 'criminal tendencies' may predispose people towards family
violence
or a taste for violent TV and not the other way round. Also, there may
be a third underlying variable causing BOTH family violence AND
criminal
behaviour. All these problems are exhaustively discussed in the good
research
-- e.g.in the (much derided) Belson study [see
summary
here].
The usual conclusions from
RESEARCH
like this are that it is difficult if not impossible to establish any
general
propositions about causal factors, that there are enormous
disagreements
between researchers about the whole field. As I have argued
before,
this is a blow for those who expect Sociology to come up with simple
solutions,
and it canlead to a good deal of complaint about the irrelevance of
sociological
studies. However, the implications do not stop at sociological studies,
but apply to all those common sense "theories" of delinquency held by
professionals,
politicians, lawyers, policemen and parents -- these too depend on even
more dubious samples and inferences (often mere 'hunches' or
prejudices)
about causal connections.
'Social
Disorganisation'
theories
These seem at first
eminently common-sensical
- people are deviant because they are insufficiently socialised ('they
do not know right from wrong'). This in turn arises because they are
located
in parts of the social structure where socialisation is likely to be
especially
weak. There are two possibilities here:
- (a)The "Chicago
school". This
involved several theories of delinquency in fact, (including
subcultural
ones), but one emphasis concerns the effects of living in 'transitional
zones' which had been identified in inner US cities. In such
zones,
crime rates, divorce statistics, illegitimacy rates etc. are higher
than
average -- and this can be seen as a sign of social breakdown or
pathology.
There might be some connection between the physical or ecological
disorganisation
of these zones - high rates of mobility in and out, for example - and
social
or moral disorganisation. Thus having a variety of cultural beliefs
about
what is and is not appropriate behaviour (pluralism) can lead to
conflicting
value systems which leads to moral confusion ('anomie' in the weakest
sense).
This view has played a major part, I suspect, in social policies
towards
the cities in both the US and Britain. In research terms, two early
empirical
studies (Morris and Sainsbury, found in a very early collection --
Carsons
and Wiles 1971) indicate some support for this sort of view- but also
present
some contradictory evidence for Britain. There may be good
reasons
for these differences between the US and Britain as we'll see in the
stuff
on subcultures.
- (b) The British
"social
pathology" school.
This approach drew upon common views of the 'cultural deficits of
working class (male) kids, which also lay at the heart of much
educational
research and policy [ as in this file]
. Working class kids were believed to be inadequately socialised into
the
norms of industrial society. This explained a range of problems
like
educational underachievement, 'restricted' cultures and language codes,
low ambitions - and high delinquency rates. Of course, the statistics,
and the working beliefs of professionals confirmed that there were high
rates, at least of officially defined delinquency in working class
areas).
All the factors found in the classsics of the Sociology of Education -
"inadequate mothers" pathological working class values and so on were
identified,
and these were often combined with psychological variables such as
inadequate
child-rearing, rigid conformity and therefore vulnerability to
peer
pressures, delay in the 'normal' development of adult moral codes and
so
on. This work was nicely criticised long ago, in fact, (e.g.in Wootton
1959) in the ways we might expect, including the usual problems of
methodology,
but I think it still persists in the working ideologies of politicians,
priests and policemen.
Anomie theories
These are perhaps the most
famous
(and best?) social pathological models, found in both Durkheim's and
Merton's
classic works.
For Durkheim,
several types
and several explanations of deviancy arise in industrial societies.
Most
textbooks discuss this (e.g.Downes and Rock 1988), but try my gloss on
what I believe are the main implications:
- (a) Deviancy is
undeniably
social. There
are no separate individual or asocial (e.g. biological or genetic?)
roots
or origins -- as with all social facts, deviancy is to be explained
with
social factors. Basically, deviancy arises from contradictory currents
in the conscience collective. As we know, Durkheim went on to explain
suicide
in social terms -- so that 'egoistic' types arise from excessive
individualism
in the conscience collective, 'altruistic' types from its opposite,
that
is excessive commitments induced by the conscience collective, and
'anomic'
types from serious (and possibly temporary) dislocations in the
conscience
collective following rapid social change, leaving the way open to
wobbling
and depressive individualism again Of course, these types of suicide
may
or may not have parallels with other forms of deviance -- can you think
of any altruistic crimes against property (destruction of GM crops?
Merton
(below) is the theorist here, of course). Let us punch home this
rigorous
sociological line with two additional implications. One is that even
politically-inspired
or deeply thought-out deviancy obeys social pressures and social
forces,or,
as
Durkheim put it "the principle of rebellion is the same as that
of
conformity". Another is that deviancy can be a good thing, with
positive
functions to discharge, such as inaugurating a period of necessary
social
change.
- (b) Deviancy is
normative,
with no 'objective'
defintions (except a statistical one). 'Pathological' behaviour
can
only defined against average types of conduct,and, as we would
expect
with averages, we can always find deviants at both ends of the
distribution.
Again, there are some thought-provoking implications. First, we will
always
have deviants -- even if we kill or expel the existing people at the
end
of our distribution, those closer to the middle will simply occupy the
places at the ends and become deviants from the new average. All groups
have their deviants -- even selective schools classify the weakest even
of their students as 'failures', even monasteries have deviants, even
though
the range of behaviour would be seen as perfectly acceptable outside.
And
even deviants have deviants -- as prison life demonstrates, so that no
self-respecting thief would dream of befriending a sex offender. These
examples indicate that deviancy is socially necessary and even useful
in
enabling the rest of us to clarify and demonstrate our own 'normality'
-- the great theatrics of a sensational criminal trial show this
happening,
of course, but on a more mundane scale, learned academics love
discussing
student mistakes and failures at examination boards for the same reason
(so we can show how clever and civilised and well-educated we are by
comparison).
Of course there are problems with this relativist position -- some
crimes
are so awful and genuinely anti-social that no group or society would
tolerate
them? This sort of calm acceptance is horribly distant from and
unsympathetic
to the real victims of crime?
- (c)Reactions to
deviancy
are social
too. Reactions, including concern and a desire for punishment,
are
also inspired by the conscience collective. This is a useful insight, I
think, to explain later developments in deviancy theory -- there are
social
reasons to explain why labelling takes place, for example. Durkheim
sometimes
comes over as an old reactionary for insisting on the social origins of
and need for punishment, but there is an implication that punishment
need
not necessarily be draconian or excessive -- there is no need to
inflict
suffering beyond the level necessary to reassert the conscience
collective.
Looking back on this, I found myself thinking of Foucault's influential
work on punishment and its evolution (from massively brutal physical
retribution
to some sort of reparation, and then to the notion of individual
supervision
and internal reform), and the similarities to and differences from
Durkheim's
work --no time to pursue it here though
Merton's famed
discussion
(in Part II of his Social Theory and Social Structure) set in
the
broader context of attempting to rescue functionalist theory and
respond
to its critics (many of which Merton himself had read and embraced). I
mean to imply no adverse motives here. I like Merton a great deal,and I
think he is a much better theorist than those usually chosen to
represent
functionalism (like Parsons). In fact, I think myself that Merton did
for
functionalism what Althusser or Habermas did for marxism -- tried to
turn
it (back?) into a study of concrete forms, moving away from the
certainties
of abstract theory (see also Sztompka 1986). Merton is interested
in establishing how universal goals and values actually are, rather
than
just assuming they must be universal, or how psychological mechanisms
actually
do convey cultural goals to individuals, or what concrete sources of
strain
and social conflict actually do exist and how culture responds to
strain,
instead of theorising away these strains as temporary, as the result of
evolutionary lags or whatever. Merton also attempts to move away
from the value-laden implications of terms like 'function' and
'dysfunction'
(often associated before with simple support for the current status
quo).
His work sets out to investigate social conformity instead of assuming
it, and argues, famously, that there can be unintended and ironic
consequences
of action in matters like 'self-fulfilling prophecies'.
The chapters on anomie
theories and
deviancy open with attacks on psychological accounts (especially
Freudian)
and utilitarian/social contract views of punishment and
conformity.
Deviance is not psychopathological -- it is instead a normal response
to
abnormal conditions, which have been produced by definite social
pressures.
What are these social
pressures?
They arise from strain provided by discrepancies between approved goals
and available means in US culture. Thus high levels of achievement -
especially
monetary success - are stressed as goals for all. There is, however, a
relatively weaker emphasis on the legitimate means to achieve these
goals
- and general ignorance about the quite limited availability of these
legitimate
means in practice. The USA has a popular and widely appealing view of
itself
as an open society, where anyone may rise 'from log cabin to White
House',
but in fact life chances are very unequally distributed. This
discrepancy
between goals and means induces strain - and individuals adapt in
different
ways, including 'deviant' ways. The usual way to depict these different
options is to draw them in a table.
Modes of adaptation |
Culture/goals |
Institutionalised means
|
Conformity
|
+
|
+
|
Innovation
|
+
|
-
|
Ritualism
|
-
|
+
|
Retreatism
|
-
|
-
|
Rebellion
|
+/-
|
+/-
|
This table tells us quite a
lot about
deviancy, I think, even though additions can be made to it (eg Hopper
(1981)
makes it 7 types of adaptive response). Even so, I think it does
illustrate
many of the developments Merton makes to functionalism which I have
listed
above -- eg it does help generate concrete and more complex results
than
the usual simple split in functionalist thought between conformity and
deviance. In particular, note that 'innovation' is labelled in
this
way to indicate some doubt about the distinction between professional
crime
(the usual exemplar of this category) and capitalist enterprise in
general
-- capitalism allows some innovations but not others. Also there is
anti-social
behaviour which is not actually criminal -- ritualism. Merton estimates
that this sort of adaptation, which might be thought of as 'going
through
the motions', pretending to be managing an enterprise (or college)
while
in practice doing nothing of the kind but pushing paper around instead,
is actually very damaging to the US economy and can cost a fortune --
but
it is not illegal!! Marxists were not the first to draw attention to
'white
collar crime' as a neglected category, and Merton's is still a powerful
critique which has been little developed -- I happen to think that
ritualism
of this kind is rife in Britain, for example, and I would love to
research
it..It connects with other interests of mine like how students cope
with
university life.
More generally, anomie is
unevenly
experienced. Much depends on alternative sources of prestige
(e.g.
artistic achievement) which can mitigate the effects - but it is
possible
to deduce the most likely locations of the innovative response
(professional
crime, which people were quite keen to study in Chicago in the early
part
of the century!) - lower strata deprived ethnic minorities, even
families
where high ambitions are transferred to kids while remaining basically
unaware of the limits to the real opportunities. (So maybe those low
ambitions
identified among working class British kids were not so harmful after
all?)
In Chapter V, Merton goes
on to extent
and develop the notion of anomie a bit more. He distinguishes
types
and degrees of anomie (from slight confusion to acute dislocation). As
a good sociologist, he is well aware of the problems operationalising
the
concept (neither psychological feelings nor objective data like
marriage
and divorce rates etc. are really good enough) - yet he insisits the
concept
must be testable. In particular, research (never systematically
done
to my knowledge) is still needed on:
1. rates and
amounts of
exposure to goals and norms;
2. degrees of acceptance of
goals
and norms;
3. life chances (which may
vary
--the emancipation of black people and women is one example of a
change);
4. particular discrepancies
between
goals and life chances;
5. degrees of anomie;
6. the rates of deviant
behaviour
(not just criminal behaviour -- oh for a systematic study of
ritualism!).
Discussing problems, Merton
offers a
possible extension into subcultural theories. He admits that, in
pure form, anomie theory seems not to apply to working class boys, as
Cohen
argues (see file)
- their deviancy is
negative, non-utitilarian, and expressive, rather than a 'normal' and
understandable
approach to strain. Yet Merton says that while the forms of the
responses
might well be subcultural in origin, the underlying source of this
behaviour
lies in social strain nevertheless. Anomie theories explain
the distribution even of subcultural responses. In the spirit of
pursuing
concrete complexities which characterises his work, Merton has two
further
suggestions. First, an anomic core of individuals might well be capable
of socialising less anomic individuals within delinquent subcultures
(raising
very interesting questions about the structureof subcultures -- see
below).
Secondly, delinquency itself strains the mainstream culture, so that a
kind of deepening crisis can occur.
Finally, Merton's work has
been influential,
although not always acknowledged as such. Thus later work, associated
with
gramscian accounts of youth subcultures ( such as Hall and Jefferson
1976
or even Willis) saw deviant behaviour
largely
as a matter of rebellious 'style', focused among young working class
males.
Yet at the heart of the work lay a social strain theory, not dissimilar
to Merton's -- capitalist society provided such young men with social
problems
('real' ones like unemployment or school failure, and more 'imaginary'
ones like loss of status). Again the response was not so 'rebellious'
as
was hoped -- instead of engaging in 'real' (i.e.socialist) politics,
such
men took to symbolic politics as an 'imaginary solution' to their
perceived
tensions, and began 'acting out' their feelings as various challenging
'styles'.
References
Carsons W and Wiles P (eds)
(1971)
The Sociology of Crime and Deviancy in Britain, vol 1, Oxford: Martin
Robertson
Downes D and Rock P (1988)
Understanding
deviance: a guide to the sociology of crime and rule-breaking, 2nd
edition,
Oxford: Oxford University Press
Hall S and Jefferson T (eds)
(1976)
Resistance Through Rituals, London: Hutchinson
Hopper E (1981) Social
Mobility,
Oxford: Basil Blackwell
Stzompka P (1986) Robert
Merton:
an intellectual profile, London: Macmillan
Wootton B (1959) Social
Science
and Social Pathology, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul
|