Notes
on: Deleuze, G and
Guattari, F. ( 2004) A
Thousand Plateaus.London:
Continuum.
Chapter 7 Year Zero:
Faciality
Dave Harris
Summary:
Faces are very interesting and
unusual aspects of our bodies that have been
given all sorts of cultural, artistic and
social significance. They have a political
role too.
NB Try also Guattari's discussion
of faciality in The
Machinic Unconscious ( written
slightly earlier?) . Guattari is slightly
easier without losing any of the ludicrous speculative
quality that we have come to love.
I
read this one next because I remembered
something in Chapter 6 about having to extend
some of the ideas in this chapter (which comes
after chapter 6 though – witty innit?).
I
grew seriously weary reading this though and I
don’t recommend it to anyone really. There is
a bit of an explanation in Dialogues.
I also have a video in my series Deleuze for
the Desperate (transcript
here) The gist, from what I can see, is
that the face represents black holes and white
walls, a signifying system that helps
construct repressive identities:
Yes, the face has a great
future, but only if it is destroyed,
dismantled. On the road to the asignifying and
asubjective. But so far we have explained
nothing of what we sense. [How bleedin’ true!}
The move from the body-head
system to the face system has nothing to do
with an evolution or genetic stages. Nor with
phenomenological positions. Nor with
integrations of part-objects [as some
Freudians think,like Klein] , or structural or
structuring systems. Nor can there be any
appeal to a preexisting subject, or one
brought into existence, except by this machine
specific to faciality. In the literature of
the face, Sartre’s text on the look and
Lacan’s on the mirror make the error of
appealing to a form of subjectivity or
humanity reflected in a phenomenological field
or split in a structural field. The gaze is
that secondary in relation to the gazeless
eyes, to the black hole of faciality. The
mirror is that secondary in relation to the
white wall of faciality. Neither will we speak
of a genetic axis, or the integration of
part-objects [you just said that, mugs!] . Any
approach based on stages in ontogenesis is
arbitrary: it is thought that what is fastest
is primary, or even serves as a foundation or
springboard for what comes next. An approach
based on part-objects is even Worse; it is the
approach of a demented experimenter who flays,
slices, and anatomizes everything in sight,
and then proceeds to sew things randomly back
together again. You can make any list of
part-objects you want: hand, breast, mouth,
eyes . . . It’s still Frankenstein. What we
need to consider is not fundamentally organs
without bodies, or the fragmented body; it is
the body without organs, animated by various
intensive movements that determine the nature
and emplacement of the organs in question and
make that body an organism, or even a system
of strata of which the organism is only a
part. It becomes apparent that the slowest of
movements, or the last to occur or arrive, is
not the least intense. And the fastest may
already have converged with it, connected with
it, in the disequilibrium of a non- synchronic
development of strata that have different
speeds and lack a sequence of stages but are
nevertheless simultaneous. The question of the
body is not one of part-objects but of
differential speeds. (190).
There
are wretched ‘theorems’ obsessively developed:
Theorems of
Deterritorialization, or Machinic Propositions
First theorem:
One never deterritorializes alone; there are
always at least two terms, hand-use object,
mouth-breast, face-landscape. And each of the
two terms reterritorializes on the other.
Reterritorialization must not be confused with
a return to a primitive or older
territoriality: it necessarily implies a set
of artifices by which one element, itself
deterritorialized, serves as a new
territoriality for another, which has lost its
territoriality as well. Thus there is an
entire system of horizontal and complementary
reterritorializations, between hand and tool,
mouth and breast, face and landscape. Second theorem: The fastest of
two elements or movements of
deterritorialization is not necessarily the
most intense or most deterritorialized.
Intensity of deterritorialization must not be
confused with speed of movement or
development. The fastest can even connect its
intensity to the slowest, which, as an
intensity, does not come after the fastest but
is simultaneously at work on a different
stratum or plane (for example, the way the
breast-mouth relation is guided from the start
by a plane of faciality). Third
theorem: It can even be concluded from
this that the least deterritorialized
reterritorializes on the most
deterritorialized. This is where the second
system of reterritorializations comes in, the
vertical system running from bottom to top.
This is the sense in which not only the mouth
but also the breast, hand, the entire body,
even the tool, are "facialized," As a general
rule, relative deterritorializations
(transcoding) reterritorialize on a
deterritorialization that is in certain
respects absolute (overcoding). We have seen
that the deterritorialization of the head into
a face is absolute but remains negative in
that it passes from one stratum to another,
from the stratum of the organism to those of
signifiance and subjectification. The hand and
breast reterritorialize on the face and in the
landscape: they are facialized at the same
time as they are landscapified. Even a
use-object may come to be facialized you might
say that a house, utensil, or object, an
article of clothing, etc., is watching me, not
because it resembles a face, but because it is
taken up in the white wall/black hole process,
because it connects to the abstract machine of
facialization. The close—up in film pertains
as much to a knife, cup, clock, or kettle as
to a face or facial element, for example,
Griffith’s "the kettle is watching me." Is it
not fair to say, then, that there are
close-ups in novels, as when Dickens writes
the opening line of The Cricket
on the Hearth: "The kettle began it . .
." and in painting, when a utensil becomes a
face-landscape from within, or when a cup on a
tablecloth or a teapot is facialized, in
Bonnard, Vuillard? Fourth theorem:
The abstract machine is therefore effectuated
not only in the faces that produce it but also
to varying degrees in body parts, clothes, and
objects that it facializes following an order
of reasons (rather than an organization of
resemblances).
As
for these potty little diagrams – you decide O
Reader, because I cannot be arsed...
[On mature reflection, and
after several more readings,a later Dave returns
to this... I think the obscurity of this chapter
tells us a lot about D and G and their private
language. Many of the bizarre sentences
that they deploy are really referring to
particular metaphors or arguments found in
various novels, or refer to their own or others'
comments on paintings or pieces of music.
The only one I can personally track down refers
to their citation of Proust, which is made
explicit in the chapter, but well towards the
end. In the novel, frequent connections
are made between social events or people and the
landscape around the hometown which is recalled
in memory. This is not too obscure
necessarily, and it reflects common observations
about how someone has a typically French face or
whatever. As the narrators [for there are
several] describe their memories, they connect
faces to landscapes, sometimes to particular
journeys through landscapes, and elements of
landscape also have their own capacity to
generate memories of people or of social events
in their turn, by recalling a train journey
through Normandy, for example. All this is
fully explicable, but referred to in a very
condensed way, in sentences that just say the
face or faciality is the same as the landscape
or 'landscapity': if you were unaware of the
allusion to Proust, it would seem just barmy,
and you would be forced to pursue one of those
poetic readings where our readers find their own
connections from their own resources.
While I'm here, I think the face assumes so much
importance because it is a refutation of Lacan
on the phallus as a universal signifier. I
must say, I am on the side of D and G here
because faces do contain two components, they
argue, which makes them useful for binary forms
of communication, whereas phalluses are only
either there or not, and the sexual binary as
the foundation for the social is
reductive. Incidentally, I think one or
two other strange and fussy remarks about the
processes of signification and the role of the
signifier, in chapter 5, are also best read as
an extension of the complaints about Lacan
attributing too much significance to the
signifier.
Doubtless there are all sorts of other allusions
to people and their work that I have
missed. Some of these are indicated in the
notes for each chapter, but considerable reading
and scholarship must be required to get to all
of them. No doubt, it is the highly
educated French professoriate that is the
intended audience for this. Anyway, I managed to
get a little more out of it...]
The date given is year zero, because an awful
lot of emphasis on the face apparently started
with Christianity.
Signifiance requires some sort of screen or
white wall to project signs onto.
Subjectification, on the other hand, requires
some concentration and limit -- a black
hole. Since these two processes are
commonly mixed, we can see that a mechanism
helps regulate them, a system that will have
both the white wall and a black hole -- the face
[that is, a very washed out face, with no other
features]. In a concrete way, actual faces
are also important in signification: there are
'specific faciality traits' (186) that help us
signify for example by registering emotions or
intentions. We can see faces in this
general way, although they are also important in
the normal understandings of subjectivity and
individuality.
[Actual?] faces appear on the wall and in
the black hole. The light reflecting off
them, or the shadows in them, are powerful forms
of communication in film, so in a way, the white
wall [screen] and dimensional areas of darkness
are already there. [I wonder if working
with paranoid or catatonic patients also led G
to emphasize the face as a form of
expression?] To further complicate matters
[!], there are a number of combinations of black
holes and white walls -- such as a number of
black holes distributed on the wall, or a
central place for the black hole, with the white
wall reduced to a thread heading towards it
[which explains those potty little diagrams I
have complained about above]. In other
words, there is 'an abstract machine of
faciality' which produces actual faces as
white walls and black holes, as system. We
are warned 'do not expect the abstract machine
to resemble what it produces, or will produce'
(187).
[Lots of literary references to Kafka ensue,
followed by references to ballet: the common
theme seems to be mysterious bouncing balls as
a-signifying. These are also concrete
aspects of the abstract faciality
machine]. American psychology has always
stressed the importance of the face, including
the importance of face to face contact as in the
'four eye machine' (188) [specifically
referenced in Guattari's
version of TP]. [Some
American theories are then reinterpreted in
terms of white screens and black holes].
The system which gives us the face is not the
same as the one giving the body, which is much
more to do with volumes and cavities. We
should not see faces simply as heads. The
thing about the face is that it is a
communicating surface [it is more visible and
general?]. Heads are not necessarily
communicating surfaces in this way, but should
be seen as parts of the body. Bodies
communicate in a 'multidimensional, polyvocal
corporeal code'. The face replaces this
with a code of its own [technically an
overcoding, they say] [This replacement is going
to be historically significant as we shall
see]. It is possible to see the body as
simply a surface penetrated by holes [following
overcoding by faciality] , as in certain kinds
focus on parts of the body, including fetishism,
but this does not make it a communicator like
the face. And this expression of the body
reflects a more 'unconscious and machinic
operation' (189), which is not like the one
producing the face.
The abstract machine that produces the face can
also affect other parts of the body or even
other objects [like balls as we saw]. Why
should it produces faces in particular? It
is nothing to do with the characteristics of
human beings because 'there is even something
absolutely inhuman about the face'. In
fact looking at faces and how they communicate
points to this inhuman element. A
political implication follows -- 'if human
beings have a destiny, it is rather to escape
the face', a typically bizarre way of saying we
have to develop human potential away from
repressive signifying systems that work with
binaries, and we are to do this by following all
the other wacky processes we know and love --
become animal, becoming imperceptible and so
on. Only then can we avoid 'glum face to
face encounters' or tedious signifying
subjectivities [a note refers to a passage in
Henry Miller for guidance!]. We must
become a BWO, heading for the 'asignifying and
asubjective'[then the quote about how they have
explained nothing of what they sense].
How did the facial system emerge? It is
nothing to do with evolution. [Freudian]
theories of part objects would not explain it
nor will structuralism, and obviously, nor will
some 'appeal to a preexisting subject'(190)
[except ones produced by the faciality system
itself] . Abstract faciality precedes
notions of the gaze, and the mirror stage in
Lacan. We should start instead with the
BWO and its intensive movements that produce a
role for particular organs. It is 'speed'
rather than sequence at/in which these organs
emerge as part objects. [And a kind of
history of the development of human organs
ensues, 191, phrased in terms of
deterritorialization -the woman's breast is a
deterritorialized mammary gland -- that is, it
is found in an unusual place for a the normal
not-upright mammal]. The face expresses a
slower and more intense deterritorialization,
possibly an absolute deterritorialization, no
longer located on a head, and connected to
signifiance and subjectification.
There is 'the correlate of great importance: the
landscape', also considered as a
deterritorialized world. [This originates
in Proust {my summary here} for my
money as I argued, but] we can see the
correlation in Christian education as well,
which tries to spiritually control both face and
landscape. There are also connections in
artistic especially architectural notions and in
painting, and films treat 'the face primarily as
a landscape'. The two are often
co-implicated in art [examples ensue from
paintings or novels. For those interested,
our heroes define the novel as featuring 'the
adventure of lost characters who no longer know
their name, what they are looking for, or what
they are doing, amnesiacs, ataxics, catatonics',
and 'there is always a Christian education in
the novel'(193)].
Then we get the wretched theorems as
above. Note that face - landscape here are
two terms used in deterritorialization and its
opposite. The others seem to want to tidy
up the importance of faciality against various
psychological mechanisms. Maybe the most
importantbit is in Theorem 3 where faciality
links the organism and significance in the
process of domesticating the BwO?] The playful
approach continues by saying that objects can be
facialized, so that it is possible to say that a
utensil is watching me -- this is not to be
taken literally to imply that it has facial
features, but that it is playing a part in the
abstract process of facialized relations [in
what way? I use it in my signifiance? It becomes
a prop for my personhood? A status symbol? It
binarizes my becomings? It can only be a
metaphor really, surely?].
What produces this emphasis on faciality, or the
operation of the abstract machine of
faciality? We can think of concrete cases,
when the mother's face becomes important for the
child, or the face of a loved one, or if the
face of the leader becomes politically powerful,
or film stars' faces become well known.
Behind the individuality of these cases lies the
abstract organization of power and the ability
to signify. [Curiously, they argue that
'this is an affair not of ideology but of
economy and the organization of power', 194 - so
what do they mean by ideology here
exactly?].
Naturally, they want to weasel about whether
faces explain social power or require it (195),
but they do offer us a kind of history,
beginning with 'primitive societies', which do
not have a facial system of semiotic, but rather
one that operates through bodies and their
territorialities, enabling direct connections
between particular semiotic sequences [citing
somebody called Lizot. While they're at
it, they challenge the universality of the
incest taboo, and argue that it is a matter of
appropriate kinds of incest which are connected
with various other forms of prohibitions].
If there are disturbances to these semiotics,
they take the form of 'becomings-animal, in
particular with the help of drugs', leading to a
particular kind of spirituality grounded in
animals and the body. This is to deny the
assertion that such people lack culture, merely
that their codes relate to bodies and their
bodies might connect with souls. Such
'"primitives" may have the most human of heads,
the most beautiful and most spiritual, but they
have no face and need none'.
It follows that the face is not a universal
system of communication, but is associated with
'the typical European', with 'White Man himself'
(196), and with Christ who 'invented the
facialization of the entire body and spread it
everywhere'. The face was then able to
acquire and exercise 'the most general of
functions: the function of biunivocalization or
binarization'[talk about post hoc ergo
propter hoc or some other phrase that
suggests they came to this conclusion because
they define the face as binary several pages
before]. The face as a system produces
both elements and choices. In the first case,
any content is rendered as a binary, a
dichotomy, an arborescence [later defined as a
series of binaries], and these appear as
stereotyped facial expressions in some cases -
the stern judge, the noble child and so
on. The four-eye machine is another
example.
When it comes to choices, these are still
rendered as the basic yes/no type [followed by
an awful lot of literary delirium and other
bullshit about facial tics, submissive
defendants and so on. Sentences like 'The
teacher has gone mad, but madness is a face
conforming to the nth choice']. The point
is that nothing is rejected by the system, there
is no outside, and no 'other' either, and this
leads to a rather interesting argument about
racism, which is not just a simple exclusion of
someone who does not fit white categories, but
rather someone who occupies a place already
defined by the facialized system, for example as
something 'increasingly eccentric and
backward'… 'Racism never detects the
particles of the other; it propagates waves of
sameness until those who resist identification
have been wiped out'(197). [In other words, this
is the 'tyranny of the Same']. There is a
positive side in that painting exploits 'all the
resources of the Christ-face', including
'Christ-athlete at the fair, Christ-Mannerist
queer, Christ-Negro'(198), and paradoxically,
the 'Catholic code' produced all kinds of
creativity in painting.
Of course, modern information theory sees
communication as a series of signifying messages
themselves made up of binary elements, which can
take part in binary messages, with choices as a
matter of a binary again. All this depends
on there being some wall or screen together with
'a central computing hole', however [which seems
to be an additional function for the black
hole]. In other words, the binary system
must have already structured everything.
This has a political function again, because it
protects the twin processes of signifiance and
subjectification from any intrusion from the
outside, any 'primitive polyvocality' or
heterogeneity. Everything must be
translated, and this 'requires a single
substance of expression', some common
semiological screen. Both this kind of
totalized communication, and the necessary 'web
of subjectivities' require a central eye.
'It is absurd to believe that language as such
can convey a message'(199), since it depends on
this prior organization. [Pursuing the
metaphor well past its sell by date] 'choices
are guided by faces'. [Being weaselly
again] there is no direct correspondence between
the binaries of the face and the binaries of
language, 'but the former subtend the
latter'[but this has just been asserted, of
course]. What the faciality system does is
to 'grid' the contents of communications.
Similarly, it does not just supplement
signifiers and subjects, but 'is their condition
of possibility'[another assertion, replacing
solid transcendental argument]. [Having
another go] 'facial redundancies are in
redundancy with signifying and subjective
redundancies'. Similarly, 'faces choose
their subjects', as the figures which programme
signifiers [possibly a third kind of relation
between faces and language?].
So the abstract machine of faciality is
triggered in particular social formations ['and
also landscape', as an afterthought, 200, with a
reference to a French writer on the political
significance of landscape]. The old
systems of polyvocal coding collapsed at
different times, and the new semiotic of
signifiance and subjectification appeared,
'crushing' the old forms. Communication
now becomes 'superlinear' rather than
multidimensional, although homonyms or
ambiguities present short term problems.
The new linguistics 'can tolerate no
polyvocality or rhizome traits', as we see with
children who prefer play or dancing to reading
and writing 'and will never be a good
subject'. Some of the old systems do
remain 'in well defined enclosures'.
It is not just a matter of semiotic systems,
since there are assemblages of power which
'impose signifiance and subjectification' as
their characteristic forms of expression.
In particular, 'there is no signifiance without
a despotic assemblage, no subjectification
without an authoritarian assemblage'.
These assemblages make the new semiotic system
all powerful. For example, bodies are
disciplined, reducing their communicative role,
'becomings-animal hounded out' [see what they
did there? Hounded!]. Organic strata
are displaced by the structure of signifiance
and subjectification relying on a single
substance of expression, the faciality
system. {Asserted as a single foundational
substance of expression now] [Feeling it time to
inject new life into the tired old metaphor,
they remind us why it is called facialization --
if you decode bodies, it implies overcoding by
the face. Landscape gets to trot out again
-- here it organizes 'corporeal coordinates or
milieus'(201)].
Clothed bodies take part in facialization,
demonstrating for example 'buttons for black
holes against the white wall of the material' [
try that on Paisley prints!] , and so do masks,
which instead of concealing the face of and
making it part of the body, now represent an
abstract face. This relation of the face
to assemblages of power consolidates the
argument that 'The face is a politics' [poor
grammar? No -- philosophy!].
It is been argued before [probably in chapter 5]
that signifiance and subjectification have
different principles and regimes, the one
irradiating out, and the other following a
segmentary line, and, apparently, the first
depending on generalized slavery, while the
latter relies on 'authoritarian
contract-proceeding'[or maybe the other way
around - I have not read chapter 5 yet].
Neither begin with Christ, and there are non
European versions. For example
authoritarian subjectification is demonstrated
best in the history of the Jewish people [more
in Ch. 5]. The mixture makes them
imperialist - signifiance always implies
subjectivity, and all subjectification has
remnants of signifiers. Similarly, all
walls include holes, and all holes scraps of
wall - apparently, this grounds the mixture of
the two semiotics [well, weaselling seems to
apply to both]. The nature of the mixtures
can vary, however. The advent of Christ
and Europeanism is important because the mixture
became a matter of 'total
interpenetration'. In other mixtures, one
element might dominate, however. We're
going to depict this as more potty little
diagrams of types of faces on 203.
In one cases, black holes move across walls and
can multiply. Circles can be drawn around
these holes. Eyes can be placed within
them [carried away with their own visual
metaphors], borders increase the surface over
which holes slide ['operate' would be better],
and indicate 'a force of capture'. We can
see this really clearly 'in popular Ethiopians
scrolls representing demons'[of course! I
know them well!]. There is a certain
redundancy of frequency in this multiplication
of eyes, giving the impression that 'the despot
or his representatives are
everywhere'(203). This implies implacable
destiny. Some close-ups in film indicate
this, as when 'the hands of the clock foreshadow
something'. In another case, the white
wall unravels and becomes a thread, one black
hole dominates, and the landscape also becomes a
thread. These threads coil around the
hole. Our heroes take this to mean
'reflexive, passional, subjective destiny.
It is the maritime face or landscape'(204) [I
still reckon this is an allusion to
something, not poetry]. Faces appear
either in profile, or facing each other, or turn
away for each other 'swept away by betrayal'
[see potty diagrams above]. Here, a film
close-up would indicate 'a scale of intensity',
as faces get closer to the black hole
[Eisenstein's close-ups showing developing
emotions are cited].
Sometimes the two roles for the close-up can be
combined. Sometimes they have similar
characteristics, because white walls and black
holes always go together although one can
dominate. Similarly, all black holes seem
to have different regions of intensity [which is
what the borders do, perhaps]. The black
hole is never in the eye, but the other way
around. To add to the sophistication [!],
we need to remember that deserts can also be
seas. Apparently, we can identify the
themes in certain paintings of Christ (205).
Then an example I can manage - Proust and how
he makes 'the face, and landscape, painting,
music, etc. resonate together'. When Swann
falls in love with Odette he is doing
signifying, seeing her face as screens and
holes, but connected to other things [like
classical paintings -- this is how aesthetic
gentleman fall in love: 'a face must "recall" a
painting or a fragment of a painting'
(206)]. Pieces of music do the same.
This whole effort of signifiance only leads to
Swann's 'passional subjective moment', however
[the idiot gets self-obsessed], and 'Odette's
face races down a line hurtling towards a single
black hole, that of Swann's Passion'. The
same goes with all the other little indexes,
producing several borders. Swann finally
has a strange revealing moment when he becomes
aware of his tendency to see the faces of real
people in disaggregated fragments, and he also
begins to understand the musical phrase.
The latter leads to 'a still more intense,
asignifying, and asubjective line of pure
musicality'[or in plain English, he sees the
power of the music is autonomous, affecting him
directly, and not just as representing
Odette].
Is this the only way to gain salvation, through
art? How did Proust the narrator escape
the limits of his own early memories, 'the black
hole of involuntary memory'? [Deleuze's book talks
of Proust developing a machinic grasp of time]
How do you get out of a black hole and dismantle
the face? Generally we find no answers in
French novels which are descriptive of crises,
and also '"critical of life"' (207).
Salvation through art is still 'catholic
salvation', the consolation of eternity.
Anglo American novels are different, though,
where heroes are urged to break out, travel,
journey to other civilisations or take
drugs. Even there, they know how tempting
it is to lapse back to something fixed
[literally a face in the piece quoted from a
novel by Miller, 207]. This is a breakout
in real life. It is difficult to avoid
powerful signifiers, however, and 'Christ
himself botched' his escape. It seems
easier to fall back into inertia.
We can become animal or even become flower, or
become imperceptible, even 'a becoming-hard now
one with loving'[another phrase of Miller's
apparently]. We need to look behind the
eyes, using 'all the resources of art' (208) [I
thought that was consolatory]. However 'it
is through writing that you become animal, it is
through colour that you become imperceptible, it
is through music that you become hard and
memoryless, simultaneously animal and
imperceptible: in love'. Art is only a
tool, however and it should lead to real escape
not to a refuge. There is a definite
danger of madness, as we see when schizos lose
their sense of face, landscape or language.
Some faces show signs of struggle, between
inadequately articulated faciality traits - this
is what a facial tic can be, the face blocking a
line of flight and reimposing
organization. Perhaps the best approach is
to locate and understand your own black holes
and white walls, and only then to construct a
line of flight. The usual health warnings
follow: we can not just return to some more
primitive stage [with a lot of delirious stuff
making the same point about impossible returns,
or living with the savages in Typee].
We cannot go back, the facial machine is an
impasse and must be fought. It is possible
to develop 'lines of asignifiance' that deny
signification and interpretation, but only on
the wall of the signifier. You have to
enter black holes in order to try to find
something nonsubjective but still living,
including genuine love. You have to
encounter faciality traits to release them, to
reconsider their connections with landscapes and
other codes and to recombine them, just as
painters once worked with the face of Christ but
followed their own desires. [DH] Lawrence
offers some useful examples.
The abstract machine can be taken up in strata,
where its deterritorializations are only
relative, or if absolute then only
negative. However, sometimes it operates
on a plane of consistency and acts as a diagram:
deterritorialization leads to new possibilities
[new kinds of faciality?] . Similarly,
although the faciality machine mostly forces
things into systems of signifiance or
subjectification, it can sometimes break
through. It does this by developing
'something like probe heads' (210). The
result can be defacialization: trees can turn
into rhizomes, flows can become creative
flight. Strata will disappear, so will
black holes and walls. Redundant and
limited connections between faciality,
landscape, painting or music will disappear, and
each faciality trait can form its own
rhizome. New connections can be creative,
not 'simply evoked or recalled',
reterritorialized. Connections can appear
like those between the wasp and the orchid
[again]. Rhizomatic potential replaces
arborescent possibility.
So. Faces are inhuman, necessarily because
they are produced by a machine and controlled by
apparatuses of power. There is no return
to a more genuine primitive human head, because
'In truth, there are only inhumanities' (211)
[so the mood swings back to pessimism after the
optimism of the paragraph above]. Yet this
inhumanity can be positive if it takes the form
of the probe head, which can lead to new more
positive deterritorializations, even 'strange
new becomings, new polyvocalities': 'Become
clandestine, makes rhizomes everywhere, for the
wonder of a non human life to be created'.
Perhaps there are even more stages than
primitive head, Christ-face and probe head?
menu page
|