Notes on: Kipnis, A. (2015) Agency between humanism and post-humanism Latour and his opponents. HAU: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 5(2): 43--58  doi.org/10.14318/hau5.2.004

Dave Harris

Latour is insufficiently critical of capitalism for some critics, but the problems lie in the application of ant especially in its focus on 'painstaking ethnographic research'.

Post-humanism can be defined as 'analytic stances that grant agency to nonhuman entities and that downplay the differences between human and nonhuman agency' (44). Kipnis wants to grant agency to nonhuman's but also emphasise the difference between their agency.

Latour has been attacked from different directions. Gregory [refs in Kipnis] accuses him of being a theological critic of humanism, Martin thinks that post-humanism consolidates neoliberal hegemony in the Academy and the wider world. This might represent a particular British or European context. It is apparently to do with anthropology and its decision to take an ontological turn away from Marxian political economy. — The former is associated with 'certain elite British institutions'.  Kipnis does not see things as so neatly divided, however.

ANT is post-humanist because it has '"a theory of value that attributes agency to things' [citing Gregory] (45). Latour begins with seeing science as a project to construct facts by human actors, and this made enemies, even a 'blocked appointment at Princeton', although he always argued that scientific facts were constructed but not necessarily false, merely that they did not speak for themselves. The black box presented a misleading appearance that processes yielded truth. In the piece on modernity the separation of the social from the scientific further made the point that science and politics are never separate. In the work specifically on ANT, the same critique was applied to social sciences with a critique of their black boxes like society or class: the point is to see what processes are unfolded. The place of the nonhuman also has a role in those. There may be a theoretical shift involved in this choice of targets, and some people have selectively read him, for example to see him as a neoliberal Conservative who is deconstructing society. He is said to be 'cynical and dismissive those with activist inclinations', and he is critical of some forms of radical thought and action that are one-sided. He is critical including toward himself, and has criticised colonisers [apparently in Latour 2010 
On the modern cult of the factish gods. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.]. He is a Catholic but he is critical of religious philosophical and radical thoughts as containing '"factishes"'.

He has been compared to Althusser on anti-humanism, but he does not take a simple view to either deny or enshrine human agency, but takes a middle position [developed via an anecdote about shared control?] (46). He is interested in how things mediate human agency, things of any kind, the water modifying surfing, a musical instrument modifying the player, social relationships which transform individuals: 'all human agency takes place through attachments' (47).

Martin has argued that post-humanist thinking leads to avoidance of the abuse of power by corporations and political apathy, and he blames texts written by Latour. But are the effects of these texts just the responsibility of the authors, or do they have any independent effects as 'disembodied discourse… Shaped by humans to be sure but not human in [themselves]' (48]. Political arguments also 'turn on the agency of nonhuman things' [this sort of agency is undeniable].

'It is not necessary to say that all agencies of the same'. The divisions in academia reflect the notion of different types of agent — subatomic particles as agents, chemical agents, living creatures, artworks, human beings. Particular kinds of agency are to be understood, sometimes in order to manipulate them. There are differences in the agency, for example physical particles do interact with each other in complex ways but 'at least since Newton (or perhaps Aristotle) we have known that there are no unmoved movers. The agency of one particle must be understood in relation to the agencies of others. With life another factor enters the equation. Life actively seeks to persist over time'. Living beings themselves differ according to how they reproduce, whether they can move, how they get their energy and so on. Kipnis also thinks there is a difference between those beings who are self-conscious who can separate themselves from the world they inhabit and thus 'consciously make choices about the course of action', and proposes a mirror test to distinguish self-consciousness.


Latour has a different approach not characterising beings but '"modes of existence", each with its own conditions and types of beings. However agents are placed into these categories as modes of existence. There are different attitudes and therefore different degrees of post-humanism, however.

Different modes of existence are linked to different concepts of truth, 'differing types of felicity and infelicity conditions' (49) [
2013. An inquiry into modes of existence: An anthropology of the moderns. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press] which apply to all modes of existence and beings, technologies, plants and animals everything. We have to extend the idea of felicity conditions away from linguistic notions of truth and more towards 'the ability to reproduce over time'. This however results in 'forms of anthropomorphic fallacy typical of post-humanists'. The differences between human and nonhuman agency are 'flattened'  — human agency is not unique, nor is language and self-consciousness, but concepts derived from them can only be extended metaphorically. Latour for example talks about misunderstanding by technological beings, or mute forms of life enunciating themselves, or mountains reproducing themselves and maintaining their existence [all cited 49]. These are really different types of agencies — mountains persist but not because of their own active efforts. Latour invites us to suggest other kinds of conditions but Kipnis 'would find it impossible to do so'

The boundaries do need to be redrawn now and then between types of agency — chemists change their idea of agency when chemical reactions involved electrons, and anthropologists 'became defensive' after sociobiology. Nevertheless, both specialisms retained 'enough specificity to the objects of their research'. There may be further work that changes this, but until then, it is quite possible to argue that 'humans, like all species, have unique characteristics' and 'anthropomorphic ascriptions of agency [are] a fallacy'. Other things have agency but not human forms. It's common to ascribe human forms, as an acknowledgement of the complexity of interactions with objects and their attachments.

Latour has been compared with Bourdieu and 'practice theory', which has a concept of '"agency" as an abstract capacity held by particular individuals and opposed to the social "structures" that restrain those individuals' (50). The two are linked in a zero-sum game and the first should be increased. Agency here is conscious and individual, but fails to explain how individuality arises. It also has problems when people voluntarily submit to structures, as do 'pious Muslim or Christian women'. However, 'to become an agent must submit to something' [Althusser!], to the demands of academic discipline, for example, to peer review, to the discipline of the political cause.

Kipnis cites Laidlaw on ethics as involving blame or responsibility to humans, statements that involve 'cause, intention, state and response' (51), all of which modify agency. State of mind is particularly important for agency, involving choosing, as we see in law cases, although states of mind might be caused or influenced by factors including culture or structure. The attribution of human agency is already difficult! Latour is no more difficult than others, although it still needs to avoid anthropomorphism.

The link with political activism is also difficult. Some theorists have become activists despite the implications of their theoretical commitments — Bourdieu and Foucault spring to mind. Latour has attacked climate change deniers. Nevertheless, theory does contain limitations for any politics, despite the inclinations of the theorist.

For example there are implications for critical ethnography. [There is a lengthy example of the invention of a fictitious machine that enables considerable manipulations of the stock market, and the most seemingly neutral ANT analysis of that black box would obviously involve critical questions about legality and the behaviour of those who would use it.

There is also the issue of whether researchers would ever gain access. This is the main practical problem with ANT, that and the requirement to do 'slow, painstaking, and careful ethnographic research'. It would require cooperative research subjects, with a fair degree of reflexivity, and clearly powerful people would be unlikely to cooperate. Latour gives insufficient emphasis to what is hidden, evaded. It faces the problems of any ethnographic research. What is required is an additional element of critical research, which does not involve the cooperation of subjects.

Latour perhaps does not pay enough attention to economic inequality, as in his 2013 anthropology of the moderns'. There is a lack of discussion of capital and power, and thus of one of the main modes of existence. There is no discussion of capital as 'instituted agency', how it excludes some people in moral calculations, the workforce that have produced the goods, classically.

There is also insufficient attention to the concept of power, which might well usefully substitute for the idea of felicity conditions as the primary dimension to differentiate types of agents. Power is both quantitative and qualitative, both a form of strength and a form of enticement. As well as coming in different quantities.

Back to Marx's critique of commodity fetishism, where people misunderstand ownership as a matter of relations between persons and things rather than between people, and how this obscures relationships between class. Gregory says the same thing goes on with ANT, but this might be excessive — property also has other effects, other relationships between people and things, [some of them liberating I think he is arguing], intermixing. There is much to be said for Hertzfield: 'I "would prefer to avoid the rather arid debate about whether objects have agency"' (55). [Avoids the key issue of animals and their rights, Gaia and the like]

Instead, we can grant agency to everything, acknowledge that everything can affect us, but allow for different types of agency. Those with human beings, 'life and self-consciousness', are worth differentiating, so are the issues of ethics and choice and are effects on other human beings. The same time we might acknowledge that there are no unmoved movers even with human agency, rather like Marxist view that men make history but not in circumstances of their own choosing. This is not anti-post-humanism but a compromise, and we can still take political positions without adopting extremes of voluntarism or determinism.

Agency needs to be differentiated from power. Instead of increasing the agency of certain groups, it is preferable to empower them 'for analytic precision' (56). We see human agency at work best in 'that contradictory space we experience whenever we attempt to make a decision about the unknown', when we don't know the outcomes of particular decisions. This is not the same as power, however — power is undoubtedly distributed unequally [although experiences of indecision might be far more common].