READING
GUIDE TO: Hardt M. (1993) Gilles
Deleuze. An Apprenticeship in Philosophy.
London: UCL Press Limited.
Introduction
Post structuralism should be understood as posing
alternatives within modernity, within the
philosophical tradition, as critical and
constructive, not just negating theoretical
foundations and traditions. Post
structuralism opposes not philosophy as such, but
Hegelianism. Hegel had been dominant as the
centre of philosophy and social theory, as
difficult to break with as Plato. It was
essential to confront Hegel radically and actively
reject him, or to be incorporated into the
Hegelian problematic. Deleuze therefore
attempted to confront Hegel and dialectical
thought, not to rescue it, but to separate
completely from it. Even he was not totally
successful, though, and we still find him
addressing 'typical Hegelian problems—the
determination of being, the unity of the One and
the Multiple, and so on' (xi). It is always
a dilemma to attempt to oppose Hegel without
simply offering a further negation which can be
reincorporated. There is an argument that
says that anti Hegelian work is only really an
'unconscious repetition of Hegelian dramas'.
Deleuze has gone further than most.
In particular, he has developed 'a non dialectical
conception of negation and a constitutive theory
of practice'(xii). It is difficult to
separate difference from Hegelian negation, which
appeals because of its connections to
synthesis/resurrection: Deleuzian difference looks
nihilist [and endless], although Hardt claims it
is descriptive, although also 'pure'. It
clears the ground for creation, but not
synthesis. It is also an older tradition,
rooted in skepticism. Deleuze's critique
thus raises the question of what makes reality
possible at all. He retains an interest in
ontological speculation, but insists on
alternatives to Hegel. These are not to be
seen as further speculations about being itself:
Deleuze develops 'a strictly immanent and
materialist ontological discourse that refuses any
deep or hidden foundations of being' (xiii) [until
he gets to chaosmosis and all that?]. Being
is not to be subordinated to thought, or in some
way realised by it. Instead, practice and
power of the key terms—'the complex dynamics of
behaviour… The superficial interactions of
bodies' (xiv). Nor is this only
philosophical or theoretical practice. The
traditional terms such as necessity and reason are
to be rethought.
It is possible to see Deleuze's approach unfolding
as he discusses various authors. Bergson,
for example proposes 'an absolutely positive
movement of being that rests on an efficient and
internal notion of causality', and he introduces
the notion of multiplicity of becoming.
Nietzsche added an 'ethical horizon', by
discussing the affirmation of being as active
expression. Spinoza is also useful, seeing
'the affirmation of practice, or joy, at the
centre of ontology', something constitutive of
being. Together, these represent a
systematic alternative to Hegel.This helps us see
that post structuralism does not just reject
foundations, only certain versions of them.
Transcendentalism is replaced with immanence,
teleology with open practice, final and formal
causes with efficient causes—Hardt wants to argue
that efficient cause is crucial to the whole
discussion of difference. The notion of some
order of being or truth, is replaced by a notion
of organization: 'the coordination and
accumulation of accidental (in the philosophical
sense, i.e., non necessary) encounters and
developments from below, from within the immanent
field of forces' (xv). There is no
blueprint, but a form of composition that is
'always an art'.
So we're going to read Deleuze as developing the
break with traditional philosophy, and exploring
contemporary possibilities.
Preliminary Remark
(on methodology).
Even the earliest work develops the project as a
theory of the institution, to reveal something
positive and inventive. The book on Hume
pursues some of the issues, although it also
introduces 'an extensive ontological detour'before
returning to the original idea (xvii). This
detour to the form of a critique in order to clear
the ground, an attack on Hegelianism and on the
negative. We see in his early criticism of
Christianity, a principle that says it important
to isolate principal concepts, to 'recognise
the object and the terms of the primary
antagonism ('xviii) [that is to recognise
that it was Hegelianism that needed to be
attacked]. Deleuze wanted to develop a
positive philosophy and ontology, 'in order to
establish a positive theory of ethics and social
organization', and the earlier detours through
western philosophy are an essential
beginning. This is not just postmodernism,
despite the clear enjoyment of leaving philosophy
to take on works of art and literature and so on,
but this is no 'line of flight', but rather an
affirmation of a suppressed line of thought—hence
Hardt's second principle 'Read Deleuze
philosophically' (xix). Deleuze does
pursue selective readings of his heroes, choosing
bits that help his own project, although this is
still a rigorous reading. Nevertheless, the
third principle is 'recognise Deleuze's
selectivity'.
Each of these early monographs asks a specific
question, and each one builds on the earlier work
,although this is sometimes obscure. The
books should be read as an evolution of Deleuze's
thought, and not the history of philosophy, and
even here, not a unilinear progression but 'a sort
of theoretical process of aggregation'—an
apprenticeship in philosophy. Hence the
final principle 'read Deleuze's thought as an
evolution' (xx). Even the gaps in his
work can be read as an evolution, for example a
shift from a 'Hume - Bergson axis 'to a 'Nietzsche
- Spinoza identity' (xx).
In any event, the early works are crucial since
they develop a vocabulary and foundation
[sic] that will explain the mature
work. The latter are 'reworkings of the
cluster of problems developed in this formative
period of intense and independent research', 'the
subterranean Deleuze' (xxi).
Chapter one
Bergsonian Ontology The Positive Movement of
Being.
Bergson looks as if he's developing a psychology
or phenomenology, but Deleuze is interested in the
work as an ontology, 'an absolutely positive logic
of being rooted in time' (1). He begins by
seeing Bergson as a source of criticism of the
dominant philosophical tradition, especially
Hegelian logic, which is his own particular
interest. Bergson is interested in
ontological movement and difference as the dynamic
of being, and sees a temporal dimension: this can
be used critically to attack Hegel, and to
contribute to the more positive interests as
above. The interest produced two pieces,
early articles and chapters, and then the book, which
already shows the effects of Nietzsche.
The early work attacks the concept of negative
determinations in Hegel, grounded in the initial
opposition between being and nothingness as a form
of absolute difference. This already
introduces the themes of 'static contrast' and
'dynamic conflict' (3) in Hegel. [This also
led Hegel to critique Spinoza on the grounds that
his notion of being contains no contradictions and
therefore no movement. The active management
of negation is what leads to things being
determined, and this gives a central place to
negation, and a reason why nothingness does not
triumph as a result of sheer indifference].
Deleuze accepts this role for negation, but sees a
need to move from abstract to more concrete and
specific forms of difference [see Difference and
Repetition or D&R].
Deleuze's objection involves the notion of a third
term, first by criticizing mechanicism and
Platonism.
The technique here is to address 'proximate
enemies', before getting to the 'fundamental
enemies' like Hegel. This is a way of
establishing a common terrain for critique in the
first place [by getting agreement that the
proximate enemies are flawed? Also to begin to
work out his own position. Mostly it seems a
matter of invoking the old philosophical technique
of saying that even philosophers disagreed with
other philosophers and surely no-one would want to
go back etc]. Apparently, Mechanicists are
good at explaining the evolution of differences,
but at the expense of 'the substantial, necessary
quality of being' (4). This involves the
argument that for being to be necessary, it must
be indeterminate, [thus cannot be mechanically
determined?]. The difference is spelled out
by seeing determination as only external [sounds
very much like the difference between the
extensive and the intensive, the disregard of
purely quantitative difference?]. Bergson
apparently stresses internal difference, which
cannot be simply determined—some differences might
be accidental or determined by chance. Full
determination implies some exterior other [which
runs the risk of reducing difference to the same
again?]. This is however an unusual argument
which reverses the usual terms—it is not a matter
of how being gains a determinate and
differentiated form, but rather how difference
sustains its being. Difference becomes a
source of necessity for being. Apparently, this
depends on certain Scholastic conceptions of
causality, denying material and final causes as
well as total contingency, since each retains a
notion of cause as external to the effect
[presumably the internal causes are going to be
tied up with expressionism?]. The scholastic
philosophers called this notion of internal cause
'the efficient cause' (5). This produces the
idea that difference is the 'internal motor
of being', so being has a cause in itself.
The critique of Plato again focuses on the
difference between an external and an internal
account of difference. Plato has a notion of
final cause, ultimate destination, the Good.
In Bergson 'difference is driven by an internal
motor (which Bergson calls intuition)' (6), and
there is no logical difference between cause and
effect, and no determining end or goal—'difference
has become the thing itself'. Only this
conception can explain difference in its full
connection with being.
Deleuze likes the distinction in Bergson between
differences of nature and differences of degree
[differences of degree are the quantitative ones
again—but Hardt says there is more]. In
Scholasticism, differences of nature imply
necessity and substance, while differences of
degree imply only accidents. We need to
emphasize the former in order to get to central,
pure concepts of difference. Hegel works
with an exterior notion of difference—a notion of
a 'final cause and teleology', critique via Plato
(7), and flawed notions of determinations and
negative movements in the dialectic, which implies
not an internal difference, but a negative
relation with some other thing, indeed a relation
which is further confined to contradiction,
implying a complete kind of difference with the
other. In Hegelian dialectic, the cause is
external to the effect [another kind of complete
difference as in contradiction], and mediation is
also externally caused. The Scholastic
critique would argue that this means that being
cannot be necessary or substantial in itself, and
that these external movements must therefore be
accidental and contingent [I thought Deleuze liked
accident and contingency? Isn't all that
pants about the throw of the dice introducing an
externality? It's playfully rendered as god,
but what actually is it—the contingent forces of
the chaosmosis?].
This means that Hegelian differences are only
abstract, unlike the concrete notion of reality in
Bergson, which might even combine two antagonistic
concepts [as a multiplicity?] There is also a
problem in explaining how to opposite terms get
synthesized if they are external to each
other—there can only be an abstract synthesis,
since nothing real can emerge [and later, concepts
contain 'no degrees or nuances', which makes them
abstract]. For Deleuze, Hegel has not
analyzed difference, but imposed an abstract
process [so in this sense, Hegel operates with a
certain indetermination. Maybe it is this
that makes him dangerously likely to compromise
with actual concrete social formations like
Prussia?]. However, can Bergson be also seen
as indeterminate, [in the sense of not explaining
the direction of change?]. Deleuze says that
Bergson sees things as making themselves, as a
result of difference, suggesting creativity and
originality in being, and also something
'unforeseeable'(10) and positive.
Hardt insists that this argument, in the early
work on Bergson appears only in a derivative form
in D & R.
The later book on Bergson focuses more on the
multiplicity, already implied in the earlier work,
and understandable as an attack on Hegel this time
on the One and the Multiple. Deleuze attacks
several theories of how the one and the multiple
relate, including seeing them as linked in a
dialectical movement. Again, contradiction
is too abstract a term to describe this relation;
there is the wrongly conceived movement between
concepts and reality, and an ultimate account of
accidental relations; dialectical synthesis
operates with the flawed procedure of combining
one inadequate concept with an inadequate
opposite. [Deleuze actually says combining
two generalities will never produce a singularity
-- 11]. Whether this is real Hegel or not is
disputable, [and Hardt defends Hegel a bit, 11
f—seems to be about rescuing bits in Hegel about
becoming as a result of things relating to their
abstract and multiple others. Again, Deleuze
would argue that these relations are external, and
heading towards some idealised synthesis, and that
concrete reality is insufficiently analysed in the
first place]. Hardt identifies a political
issue in the argument, since the relation between
the one and the multiple in Hegel 'is an
(analogical) foundation for a theory of social
organization, an ontological basis for politics'
(13). The unity of the one and the multiple
serves to provide an organic model of the state,
instead of recognizing real differences [more or
less the critical theory critique]. Hardt
sees this as an emerging political interest
between the early and the later works on Bergson,
advocacy of 'a pluralism of organization against a
pluralism of order' (13). The multiplicity
overcomes this problem, although Deleuze has to
attack those 'proximate enemies' [Riemann and
Einstein] who see multiplicities simply in terms
of numerical or quantitative terms.
Bergson's multiplicity is based on differences in
nature, a matter not of order but of organization
[and Hegel can be replaced with téhis notion of
two types of multiplicity].
The later book also stresses the positive nature
of Bergson, the movement that produces singularity
and specificity as qualitative difference.
Bergson is working towards the notion of the
virtual as 'the simplicity of being, in
itself, pure recollection' (14). This
virtual being is not abstract but real, an aspect
of life itself, containing its own dynamic
differences, animated by the 'elan vital'.
Processes of realization and actualization qualify
and limit pure difference. So the task is to
explain the two levels of reality as a unity and a
multiplicity. In Bergson, the difference
between time and space, duration and matter is
crucial—the former contains differences of nature,
the latter can only accommodate quantitative
variation. Duration shows how qualitative
differences emerge, not just repetitions.
This is used to support the view that substance
has its own causes, and Deleuze uses scholastic
terms to describe
Bergson's distinctions between time and space
[Bergson provides the best examples, but he's just
being used here through Deleuzian
generalization?]. So spatial multiplicities
are quantitatively differentiated, 'a multiplicity
of order' (15), while duration shows us internal
multiplicities, 'a heterogeneity of qualitative
differentiation, a multiplicity of
organization'. The second multiplicity is
more profound, and more unified. This is why
the notion of time as the universal impersonal
force is important.
Bergson talks about differentiation and
actualization as an unfolding or an emanation of
being, as a basic process of life, an unfolding of
difference. This is not to be understood as
a platonic copying of the ideal in the real, but
as a more positive production, a creation, an
outpouring of the 'explosive internal force that
life carries in itself' (16), with no end.
However, actualization is the process in time that
produces spatial differentiation. Bergson
argues this through discussing memory.
Deleuze wants to use Bergson's argument to found a
more general ontology, 'to offer an adequate
critique of the notion of the possible'. To
do this, he has to translate discussions of the
possible and the real into discussions of the
virtual and the actual. This leads him to
argue that virtualities are always real, unlike
possibilities [which have other problems as in Logic of Sense].
Possibilities can never have sufficient reality to
produce actualities, in scholastic terms. Deleuze
wants to suggest that realization assumes
resemblance [to the real] and limitation [of the
possibilities] rather than difference and creation
like actualization does, and so realization cannot
capture creativity. By contrast, the virtual
must be creative in order to actualise, producing
something original. Again the terms order
versus organisation might be implied, the
difference between static and pregiven
multiplicities as opposed to unforeseen dynamic
multiplicities.
Hegel could return however in demanding to know
what the process of continuous formation actually
is—Spinozan emanation would not be creative enough
for Hegel. Bergson has no idea of reflection
as an aspect of movement, and thus cannot counter
the Hegelian argument that actualizations might
involve progressive losses instead of positive
creativity. There is a political problem too
in explaining order [and neglecting sociology], in
favour of organization. This is where
Deleuze needs to go beyond Bergson, to explain
this time how multiplicities can produce unities
as an organizational movement [an ordering
movement, surely?]. Deleuze thinks that
actualizations can converge or intersect.
This implies that being is univocal, since it can
be always 'traced back along convergent paths to
one unique virtual point' (20), but only on the
virtual plane. However, the virtual and the
actual can communicate—in Bergson, these are
movements of memory, the dilating recollection and
the contracting particularity. Yet this is
still one directional in terms of time—can there
be further movements from particularities towards
a new recollection as a kind of future memory?
Deleuze addresses this issue only in the final
pages of the book, trying to explain how human
beings can control the processes of
differentiation and actualization and thus depart
from the plan of nature. Again, he does not
accept a social dimension, since society features
not only intelligence but 'irrational
factors'(21). Instead, he has to depend on
'the virtual instinct', and the ability to create
fables. And there is something else,
'between human intelligence and socialization',
and Deleuze calls this intuition or 'creative
emotion', drawing on some 'cosmic memory', 'a
mystical Bergsonian sociability that is available
to the "privileged souls"… And that is
capable of tracing the design of an open society,
a society of creators' (21). Luckily this is
incarnated every now and then—'a weak echo of the
voice of Zarathustra… creative
pathos'(22). Deleuze needs Nietzsche to fill
out these claims.
Nevertheless, we see in the shift of emphasis
between the two studies, 'the pressure to bring
the ontological to the social and the
ethical'. It also leads to a need for
Nietzsche, a shift from logic to values, a further
step in the development of a positive ontology.
[The argument so far also shows the importance of
the methodological principles]. When
discussing Bergson, Deleuze is interested in
critiquing the dialectic and its negative
ontology, and this produces a selective
reading. It is a mistake to see Bergson and
Deleuze as perfectly in agreement [there is a
critique of some other critics like Rose].
There are also translation problems. [The
specific issue is whether or not Deleuze supports
some natural philosophy, where the elan vital
becomes conscious of itself, as above—Hardt says
no]. Similar disputes arise over the
religious nature of Bergson's thought which really
informs the stuff about going beyond the human
condition, which leads to an admission that
Deleuze 'strains' to unite Bergson and Nietzsche
(24), and a further critique that Deleuze has not
properly interpreted Bergson. [some waspish
stuff here]. The particular problem is that
later Deleuze, as in D&R on univocal
being as nomadic and crowned anarchy is different
from the discussion about univocal being in
Bergson. Hardt also denies that the bit
about crowned anarchy is political, since the
links between the ontology and the politics are
more complex, and require more mediating steps, as
in what follows.
Chapter two Nietzschean Ethics From Efficient
Power To an Ethics of Affirmation
Deleuze moves on from considering Bergson to a
position 'where all the logical issues are posed
now in terms of sense and of value' (26), or power
[in the general humanist sense]. Nietzsche
comes between Bergson and Spinoza, producing an
ethical horizon before considering social
practice. The antagonism with Hegel is still
apparent, but the struggle is also widened, to
include discussing Nietzsche's relation to Kant
[to avoid an exclusive focus on Hegel, to work
through proximate enemies]. Nietzsche showed
the way here in broadening his own critique of
Hegel to include Kant, and Deleuze wants to work
through this stage in order to avoid arranging
Nietzsche as some pure negation of Hegel, or
reaction, driven by ressentiment. This
tactic is worked out by noticing how Nietzsche
shifts couples of opposing theorists in his work
on tragedy, shifting from the proximate enemy of
Socrates to focus on the real enemy of
Zarathustra—Christ. This raises the
possibility of a new kind of negation [which will
be a total one] 'an absolutely destructive
negation this bears nothing from its force and
recuperates nothing from its enemy' (28).
Nietzsche is seen first to correct the limits of
Kantian critique. The discovery of the
transcendental realm offers 'a refuge against
critical forces', as opposed to a total
critique. By posing this transcendental
field of values, 'Kant effectively grant immunity
to the established values of the ruling
order… [It]… Functions to reinforce
the established values and make us obedient to
them' (29). Even if we overthrow the rule of
god, the state, and our parents, we must still
obey the dictates of reason. Kant is also
accused of being too polite, whereas really
'critique is always violence', and the point is to
discuss its limits. Only with such total
critique can we move to the positive phase and the
constructive moment. Nietzsche says that
Kant never got there, because he was too enmeshed
in traditional values, and thus unable to clear
them away to be replaced by more constructive
ones. To abandon transcendentalism, however,
leaves only the immanent plane, and instead of
absolute interests, we have more specific
ones. 'Therefore, the only possible
principle of a total critique is perspectivism'
(30). Nietzsche makes a similar point when
attacking Platonism and its interest in what
is. The point is to change that question to
a matter of who is or which one is. What is
lead us to transcendental values and ideals,
whereas who is 'is a materialist questions that
looks to the movement of real forces from a
specific perspective' (30). Asking those
questions produces 'the method of dramatization'
for Deleuze, and it clearly extends ontology to a
critique of interests and values.
There is no transcendental space, and therefore
nothing beyond such questioning, no essences, no
formal and final causes, only 'an immanent dynamic
of being, an internal, efficient force of
differentiation'. In an aside, Hardt argues that
this who is question does not relate to
individuals or collectives, but rather to events,
'the forces in their various relationships in a
proposition'[citing Deleuze's only introduction to
the book on Nietzsche]. It is an impersonal
who. Nietzsche himself often seems to use
personalist terms, and this has to be selected out
by Deleuze, 'as a political selection' (31), and
this helps rescue Nietzsche from individualism and
reactionary politics. This tendency also
means that Deleuze has to go beyond Nietzsche
eventually.
Turning to Nietzsche on Hegel directly, Deleuze
renews his critique that the dialectic is negative
and abstract, unable to lead to concrete
determinations. This is just asserted in the
book on Nietzsche, but it clearly builds on the
book on Bergson. Deleuze takes a Bergsonian
line on Nietzsche too, emphasizing practical and
affirmative elements of difference. But at
the same time, Nietzsche are helps Deleuze move
away from logical categories to talk rather in
terms of values, esp. affirmative ones, and the
whole issue of interiority vs. exteriority.
This can be seen in the discussion on slave
logic. The dialectic is going to be seen as
a form of thinking of slaves, as opposed to
thought which affirms and develops
difference. Master and slave become
'dramatic personae representing the two' positions
(33). Hardt wants to argue that this is not
so much a critique of the master slave dialectic
itself, because that would mean that Nietzsche is
reading is inadequate: there is another specific
arguments in Hegel, not the Phenomenology but the
Science of Logic. Deleuze is able to see the
argument as a suitable dramatisation [and there is
a quibble later as to whether or master and slave
mean individuals, or are just names for
events].
The discussion looks as if it is about self
affirmation, the development of consciousness, but
this is the dramatised form. What Deleuze
does is to argue that there is a difference
between the assertions made by slaves and master,
both of whom argue that they are good therefore
the other must be evil. The master's logic
represents a position where evil simply describes
the master's power, it follows logically [follows
from the definition?]. In the slaves' case,
there is a more external operation, which can only
become affirmative indirectly, by positing some
external accidental argument against masters
[arguing, in effect that mastery is
arbitrary?]. Masters are actually performing
an evaluation, and this is affirmative in the
sense that strength is being exercised without
restraint. The slave argument has to divide
strength or force—strength itself is not evil, but
it is if it is carried into slavery. The
slave argument in fact maintains the notion that
power is some abstract or transcendental capacity,
disconnected from the field of forces, purely
formal, only a possibility. The master's
argument insists that power cannot be separated
like this, but must be manifested.
Of course real slaves do have real power [but
we're doing philosophy]. It is simply that
the master is somehow on the side of particular
notions of ontology as productive, active [in
Deleuze and also in scholasticism, and in Spinoza
too]—being and power are one and the same thing,
manifestation is internal to being. [Pretty
much by definition—Deleuze is cited to argue that
'the power of being is necessarily, efficiently
linked to its manifestation, that the force of
being is inseparable from "what it can do"].
Slaves arguments do not recognise [the reality]
the nature of being, and so slave power cannot
express substance, while the masters' conception
does [all this is becoming extremely
apologetic]. So Nietzsche's rants about
slavishness refers to the quality not the quantity
of the power of the weak—Nietzsche 'judges the
power internal to its manifestation as
noble'(36).
This provides an ethics and a politics. The
provision of law to restrain power can be seen as
a triumph of the weak over the strong [which might
explain Deleuze's contempt for social order?].
We are
also close to Spinoza on politics, and his
criticism of the law as constraining.
We're still only doing critique of the law and
of jurisprudence, however [juridicism is the
actual term]. It is also clear that it's
not a direct critique of Hegel, because his
master slave dialectic is about developing
consciousness and independence, staving off
death and extinction rather than fleshing out
values more specifically. Hardt says this
shows that Deleuze is not directly critiquing
for a full account in the Phenomenology, but is
instead criticising Hegel's abstract notion of
logic—the question is who wills this
logic. So this is not a direct attack, but
it does help Deleuze break away from Hegelian
thought.
[All this is typical really -- it's another
example of ideology, the happy coincidence between
the nature of being and the strong. The other
thing is the monotonous reccurence of the
dramatization stuff followed by stern warnings
that we cannot personalize. Really the whole thing
depends on us consenting to what we know of
powerful people -- we use our common knowledge of
leaders who caused problems but launched important
revolutions etc. Also it makes no sense to tie
this to an ethics if we are really only talking
about abstract forces. We are left in the
difficult position of having to argue that Nature
is good if she develops and differentiates -- new
deadly bacteria are good, climate change is good
etc. Stoicism is the only possibility here -- amor
fati. Why struggle to do liberated politics {why
not any politics} if nature is indiffernet. And
all the usual problems with utilitiatrianism --
what if my strength is your weakness, I expand at
your expense etc -- Net sum counts?]
Hardt discusses alternative readings justifying
Hegel against Nietzsche and Deleuze. One
critic says that we still need the idea of
negative logic in order to move things towards
determination, and that the stuff on the
development of the self is neglected. The
defence is that Deleuze sees negative movements as
external ones only, and to insist that they are
always involved is abstract: this is better
developed in the book on Bergson than in the one
on Nietzsche [which just assumes it]. It
might be true that Deleuze does exaggerate the
Hegelian case, though. Deleuze is not
interested either in the development of self
consciousness, which might require negative
dialectics—'Deleuze, on the contrary, wants to
have nothing to do with self consciousness and the
self it gives rise to… He views it as a
sickness, a ressentiment caused by the
reflection of a force back into itself'
(38). He wants a productive exteriority
based on affirmation.
If we do apply the discussion to the master slave
dialectic in the Phenomenology, we might
read Hegel here as arguing for the development of
self consciousness. The slave argument is
not so much that the master is evil, but more that
the slave fears death but must work, and therefore
can claim to be 'an independent self
consciousness' (39). Only when we see death
is the negation of everything can we arrive at the
pure self consciousness, based on an idea of the
purity of being. However, for Hardt, this is
flawed, because death does not negate everything
in thought, 'because it preserves the "essential
nature of the consciousness"'. This means
that Hegel is typically constrained in stopping
negation in a conservative way. Even if we
accept the general mechanism, that the thing about
life is that it resists and opposes death, then
life can still appears to be 'merely
unsubstantial… the result of chance or
hazard'. Further, seeing death in general as
contradicting life in general is too abstract and
imprecise. Overall, the consolation of the
slave 'can only be abstract and hollow'. For
masters, it might be different. They do not
negate but bring things about, in the form of
specific work from slaves. This is the
independent self consciousness the slaves
confront, and they have to work to earn
recognition from their masters. However,
slaves can see the objects of their labour as
alien, and rediscover themselves through
transforming them. This is a permanent kind
of resistance, but one that has positive
effects. It emerges in a sequence after the
first negation of death 'This educational fear
prepares the slave for his work' (40), and in work
lies true self realization.
However, the whole argument is slippery in the
sense that we don't know if masters and slaves
should be seen as real individuals, social
classes, or just 'the logical movement of
Spirit' (41) [a common problem with an awful lot
of philosophy—are slaves meant to be people or
concepts?] Is this some personal political drama
or an impersonal logical one? Perhaps
Hegel's ambiguity should be read as a clever way
of uniting the different aspects [Deleuze does
this all the time -- it is a variant of the
'slippery pronoun']. If he refers mostly to
persons, he can be seen as offering a 'liberal
ethics of mutual respect'. However, there
clearly are generalizations, as when the notion of
the master extends to death as some absolute Lord,
or when slaves gain recognition not from other
people but from their work. This must
involve some impersonal logic. The issue
raised in turn is whether the slave's drama is
personal, a route to personal consciousness, or
again a purely logical development.
In logical terms, master or slave dialectic shows
two forms of negation and how they relate.
The absolute form of negation involves the death
of the slave to suit the purposes of the master,
while the slave negation is more modulated and
more positive because it produces labour [rendered
in Hegel as '"desire held in check"']. We
can translate this into Nietzschean terms.
The first kind is simply destructive force,
'inseparable from its manifestation', while slave
power is something 'restrained from full
expression'(42). For Nietzsche, this
restraint leading to self consciousness is a kind
of interiorization of force, and Nietzsche
disagrees with Hegel in wanting to contrast this
with a fully manifested force '(the will to power
or exteriority)'. Interiorization, for
Nietzsche and Deleuze, has the bad effects of
'pain, guilt, and sin', and this will eventually
be contrasted with the ability to deploy power
fully to gain joy and affirmation. The
slave's second moment, exerting power through
work, 'is not really productive but rather
revelatory', as the slave realizes what he truly
is. Labour alone will not make progress [it
is a limited form of creation—nice implications
for Marxist theory are discussed below]. The
whole analysis makes the slave into a hero, but
this still preserves slavery. Only the
exercise of the master's full negation can clear
the decks with total critique.
All this is operated with formal logic rather than
personal content. Introducing content raises
further problems, because it seems to place
servitude centrally—after all the development,
slave labour persists. Even Marxist thought
incorporates this assumption, when it heroicizes
workers and their struggle, 'to affirm the
essential nature of work', and sees class struggle
as an educational drama ending in liberation of
workers, but only by seeing work as essential to
them. Marx rejected this idea, in favour of
a more expansive notion of the essence of the
worker—'not as work but as a force: power, the
will to power, living labour, creation'
(44). But first there must be total
critique, however, even of the values that define
the worker at the moment. Workers must
themselves engage in this critique, as in 'Marxist
workerism'[with reference to Tronti], which is 'a
beautiful means of understanding Nietzsche's "man
who wants to perish and to be overcome"': the very
essence of labour as capitalist work must be
destroyed. Hegelianism would only
reform. 'A total critique is necessarily an
insurrectional critique', and so Deleuze,
Nietzsche and Lenin are all on the same side [!].
Deleuze's reading permits this unusual connection,
and Hardt goes on to discuss Italian workerism and
workers' power, the refusal of work as a radical
critique of the capitalist essence of the worker
[most of this is related through discussing a
novel about an Italian workerist in the
sixties]. Why celebrate work, as Fascism and
the PCI alike do? Better to have a lack of
conventional political values, since at least that
releases imagination and creation. However,
the hero of the novel needs to go on to develop a
commonality with other workers, and to replace the
individual with a collectivity, whose
consciousness increased with their collective
practice. In the novel, it all ends with a
recognition of the joy of being free to create, an
affirmative moment. Here, the collective
dimension is important, a spatial dimension for
the development of the will to power—'The workers
form a powerful assemblage'(47). Workers
also actualize their critique in the form of
political action, and this brings joy. The
whole story raises additional problems for Deleuze
and Nietzsche—how to synthesise forces, and then
how to manifest them in practice. [Why not turn to
Marx or even to sociology -- D turns to Spinoza
instead!]
[It is still a fantasy, a novel! In reality
monopoly capitalists will do total critique of
work and replace it etc]
Deleuze sees Hegel as not grasping multiplicity,
except by contrasting it to the unity of the
One. Bergson's notion of multiplicity was
seen as an improvement, a proper multiple of
differences of nature, which cannot easily be
reduced to unity. However, organization
[actualization?] then becomes a problem.
Nietzsche helps Deleuze here with his notion of
the dice throw, 'Nietzsche's alternative to the
dialectic of the One and the Multiple' (48
). There are two throws of the dice, which
helps affirm chance and multiplicity, as
principles, as arguments for indeterminacy,
emanation, or creative evolution for Bergson, the
becoming of being for Nietzsche. When the
dice fall, we can see this as a matter of
affirming necessity after an initial affirmation
of chance, so that '" being is affirmed of
becoming and unity is affirmed of
multiplicity"'(citing Deleuze, 48). So the
necessary emerges not from simple determinism, but
as 'a moment of the organisation of unity…
The active creation of being'. We need the
idea of the eternal return to flesh this
out. It is the second moment, the result of
the dice throw, but also an implication relating
to the first movement, the affirmation of chance
itself [further dice throws are implied] .
All the parts of chance come together in 'an
original organization… The original elements
of chance in a coherent whole'. In this way,
chance is also seen to return. There is a
'perpetual series of shattering and gathering'
(49). [lots of little bangs].
We have to understand this not just as a pure
ontology, but 'in terms of force and value', moved
by a dynamic will. The will to power is what
makes being from becoming, and it also asserts the
necessity of chance. 'In effect, the will to
power is the principle of the eternal return in
that it plays the role of a primary cause', but
there is an ethics involved, a selective ontology,
because not every will returns. 'in
Nietzsche; being must be willed', and 'the
ethical will is the will that returns… wills
being… The will to power wills unity in
time'. [Only becasue ethics has already been
defined in terms of creative power] This
produces the ethical rule that we should will
events only if we also will their eternal
return. This helps us select by reference to
the eternal return, so even though we are urged to
do what we will by Nietzsche, there is an ethical
principle. [Feeble in practice, another
justification for male heroics]. Hardt argues that
'A Scholastic logic runs through this series' (50)
[from difference internal to things, the notion of
efficient power to bring things about, and now
'the ethical centrality of the efficient
will']. In particular indeterminism and
being are reconciled—what comes to exist affirms
the indetermination of the dice throw. [Classic
philosophical reasoning where things MUST follow
to be consistent with past philosophies, even if
we get daft results like the ternal return. This
'solves' philosophical problems of being and
becoming etc --who cares if it solves any real
social or political ones]
Deleuze now proposes that social critique should
be seen as a matter of a '" transmutation"'.
It should still be total at first, indeed
nihilistic. This might be painful, but it
reveals knowledge of ourselves, and we come to see
that the the will to power cannot actually be
known directly—it becomes a kind of knowledge of
the outside, something 'beyond interiority, beyond
suffering' (51). However, it is at least 'an
active will to nothingness', self destruction, but
also a kind of liberation from conventional ideas
of man [?]. Ideally, it will end in a
movement to creation and affirmation, from
suffering to joy, and this too is beyond rational
knowledge. However, the consolation is that
exteriority is the basis of joy as well, of
affirmation, so that human life is no longer
dominated by 'negativity, interiority, and
consciousness as such'. 'Being is primary
over knowledge'. [Pathos in Nietzsche here --it's
not his fault he was ill etc]
Back to the argument that it is difficult to
critique Hegel because it is so easy to recuperate
opposition [Judith Butler is the reference here],
any attempt to be other than Hegel simply invites
recuperation to become 'an "other" within
Hegelianism'(52). However, Deleuze proposes
not dialectical opposition, but 'a complete
rupture… an unrestrained, savage
attack'. The incompleteness of Kant can also
be remedied in this way [Nietzsche' s explicit
target]. A further implication is that
philosophy proceeds through discontinuity and
disruption, so that Hegel can never be reconciled
with Nietzsche. Deleuze's own break is
revealed to the extent that he does not even use
Hegelian language, but attempts 'to move away from
the dialectic, to forget the dialectic': even the
bits in D&R are just a repetition of
the earlier critique. Hegel has been
exorcised, and this has 'created an autonomous
plane for thought' (53) [that is, a new research
programme] .
'A philosophy of joy is necessarily a philosophy
of practice', and we need to clarify this.
Deleuze's work on Nietzsche is not intended to
investigate consciousness or understanding, not a
new interiority but 'the creation of exteriority
through the power of affirmation'. However,
we still need to introduce a corporeal
dimension. This emerges better with a
discussion of Spinoza and his notion of
interaction between bodies and the power to effect
or be affected. This is a way of
actualizing power, and because it focuses on
affect or sensation, it 'affords
Deleuze… a means of posing inner experience
as a mode of corporeal exteriority' (54).
[So he uses this C17th account rather than
anything more recent?]. This involves a reworking
of suffering as an notion of affectivity, an
attribute of power, where bodily activity becomes
joyful. Nietzsche's conception of joy is
abstract, and he tends to see sorrow simply as a
matter of ressentiment and bad
conscience. This is an insufficient basis
for 'the development of a practical struggle
against the sad passions'. We need to
discuss not only the will, but also desire.
This will reintroduce the notions of practical
agents, however—Spinoza comes to the rescue just
in time by seeing individuals as bodies, corporeal
agents [ocupying points of view?] . Spinoza
also helps Deleuze develops the idea of 'the
spatial or social synthesis' (55) not just the
temporal synthesis of the eternal return.
Chapter three. Spinozian Practice
Affirmation and Joy
Deleuze's big book on
Spinoza was a part of his doctoral thesis,
and is comparatively complex and unresolved, but
develops 'a series of interpretative strategies in
the process of development' (56). We should
see this work again as the completion of an
evolutionary movement towards politics and
practice, and remember that 'Deleuze carries his
baggage with him. Nietzsche and ethics is
Bergsonian ontology transported to the field of
value; Spinozian politics is Bergsonian ontology
and Nietzschan ethics transported to the field of
practice' (57). What this means is that
politics is grounded in ontology. Further,
Deleuze sees Spinoza as operating with two phases,
one speculative and the other practical, and this
helps him deal with some of the traditional
criticisms of Spinoza [especially idealism as we
shall see]. There is also a double movement,
from substance to things, and then operating in
the other direction. Hardt wants to use
German terms for these two movements— forschung
for the analytic and speculative, and darstellung
for both presentation and practice. The
two perspectives influence how we should
understand Spinozian concepts, and each
perspective should be seen as autonomous.
Deleuze is clearly more interested in the second
moment, and to get there, involves a detailed
analysis of the notion of power, both
ontologically, in terms of the productivity of
being, and then developing into an ethics based on
the distinction between active and reactive
passions. With this development, we can get
to practice, and this is the focus of the chapter.
The speculative phase. Spinoza
apparently innocently begins with thinking about
the infinite, and his effort is to establish some
kind of distinction within the infinite.
Deleuze proposes a Bergsonian reading on the
positive nature of difference. The argument
starts with a critique of Descartes. Spinoza
denies that there are real distinctions between
substances, and sees them only as numerical
distinctions, which have nothing to do with
substance, Deleuze asserts. Numerical
properties only limit the movements of being, and
assumes some additional cause. Instead, the
same substance appears in all the
attributes. This will lead to god as
possessing an absolute infinity of attributes, and
is therefore unique—infinity is not a numerical
matter. This informs Deleuze's notion of
difference which is not numerical either, nor
based on negation, but something in itself, lying
beneath all the other distinctions, found again in
the work on Bergson. This makes difference
absolute, caused only by itself, possessing an
'internal causal dynamic' (62), which produces
real distinctions, or difference in nature.
This is positive difference, difference in
itself. Spinoza defends this approach by
talking of the singularity of being, thought of
first as 'the union of monism with the absolute
positivity of pantheism', something unique which
'infuses and animates the entire world'(62).
In Deleuze's terms, 'Being is singular… In
that it is remarkable', not related to anything
outside itself, but not in different, something
'both infinite and definite: Being is remarkable'
(63), singular, and 'Singularity, in Deleuze, has
nothing to do with individuality or
particularity. It is, rather, the correlate
of efficient causality and internal difference:
The singular is remarkable because it is different
in itself' (63). In this, Spinoza and
Bergson seem to have similar conceptions.
However, Spinoza develops his argument through the
theory of the attributes, which helps us to see
that 'the real distinction is also a formal
distinction'[a strange philosophical way of
arguing that epistemology and ontology are
connected?]. The attributes lead us to the
idea of the univocity of being. Attributes
are expressions of being, they express an essence
and attributed to substance. This is worked
through in Spinoza in terms of divine names,
apparently, for some theologians, the divine
essence always transcends its expression so god
must be eminent and transcendent. For other
theologians god is both cause and essence, but
some argue for an analogical relation between god
and the world, but this introduces
equivocity. God alone must be immanent, or
we would need two substances, and there would be
no univocity [so this is a matter of philosophical
consistency again?]The attribute is different—it
expresses different essences, but has the common
form with the other attributes [so attributes are
immanent in what they express]. Attributes
have a common form. They should not be
confused with properties which are not expressive
in this sense, but are better seen as signs or
revelations, and lacking a common form. At
best they give us grounds to believe.
Expression is different, and here modes
'participate fully in divine substance'
(65). Signs can never be properly
understood, but expressions can lead to greater
knowledge.
Attributes are plural when looked at from the
outside, but common in form internally .
This is expressed as a 'formal commonality
embodied in each infinite attribute'.
However there are also formal distinctions [and
must be if god is to be expressed in an infinite
number of attributes]. Deleuze returns to
Duns Scotus for clarification, to provide a
difference between formal distinction and
ontological identity, two orders of reason and
being. 'Univocity means precisely that being
is expressed always and everywhere in the same
voice; in other words the attributes each express
being in a different form but in the same sense'
(66). [Rather misleadingly, different sense
means ontological commonality]. In Spinoza,
this leads to a clear univocity, a matter of
formal affirmation of being. For Deleuze,
this means that Spinoza argues for the 'full
expressivity of being'[oddly rendered here as 'the
heroic moment of a pure, speculative philosophy'].
So, for Hardt, Deleuze's Spinoza can be seen as
quite different from Hegelian speculation, unlike
most other French philosophers. This follows
from the reading of Nietzsche, and is not
explicitly pursued in the work on Spinoza.
Nevertheless, Hegel had argued that Spinozan
substance could not produce determinations,
because there is no other to negate or limit
it. For Hegel, being is not singular.
For Deleuze, difference persists as a matter of
real distinction, and singular being is not
indifferent or abstract [but 'remarkable'
again]. There can be no opposition between
singular being and determinate being, where a
singular being is somehow indeterminate.
There is no external cause operating on substance:
substance itself produces the real determinations
of the world. Here, Deleuze departs from
Bergson's anxieties about determinations, which
remained within Hegelianism. Hegel saw
Spinozan attributes as a limit on the
indeterminate substance, or a determination, but
argues that Spinoza missed out the role of
negation. Deleuze says that the attributes
'fill the role of expression' (68), not
determination.
Similarly, Hegel saw Spinoza as arguing for
emanation, where specific beings are seen as
degradations of some universal being.
Deleuze wants to argue that immanence is not the
same as emanation. The difference turns on
whether effects are immanent in causes all
along—if so, there can be no degradation.
Immanence again 'demands a univocal being' (69),
with no hierarchical levels. Deleuze
introduces the medieval term 'complication', and
its couple 'explication', to refer to the nature
of expression as both appearing in specific forms,
and, conversely, specific forms are showing
themselves to be complications of an expression
[this is my gloss, having read the small book on Spinoza].
So the speculative phase has produced a notion of
substance as a logical matter, possessing the
qualities of singularity and univocity.
[Somehow] this helps us see that the definition of
god as a real definition, emerging as some
necessary ontological principle. Everything
follows from the original conception of substance,
which, in philosophy, means that 'the principles
that demonstrate the reality of the definition of
God are those of the life of substance itself;
they are the a priori constitution of
being' (70). Deleuze uses the term 'genetic
definition', meaning that being is active, and
somehow 'unfolds' from the principles that Spinoza
has identified. However, speculation like
this can only go so far in producing principles,
and Spinoza has to move on to develop 'an
ontological practice, which is autonomous from the
field of speculation' (70), and here, Spinoza
differs again from Hegel in terms of how valuable
speculation is. Speculation is not analytic
enough. We need an account of power.
This account emerges through a critique of
Descartes. Descartes attempts a logical
proof of the existence of god—an effects must have
the same reality as its cause, the idea of god
must be caused, therefore there must be a real
god. Spinoza modifies this to argue that the
power of thinking is involved—thinking about
objects is limited by their actual power to exist
or to act. This is later extended to further
argument about the existence of god, which in one
case, suggests that: '(1) to be able to exist is
to have power; (2) it would be absurd to say that
finite beings exist while an absolutely infinite
being does not exist, because that would be to say
that the finite beings are more powerful; (3)
therefore, either nothing exists for an absolutely
infinite being also exists;(4) since we exist, an
absolutely infinite being necessarily exists' (71)
[classic philosophical reasoning depending on an
appeal not to be absurd, and then spelling out the
logical implications, which are mostly
tautological]. Deleuze takes this to mean
that power brings essence into existence, raising
the notion of a dynamic project of action
involving power. This might be naturalist in
Spinoza, suggesting that nature is
spontaneous. Deleuze argues that we can also
understand this in terms of materialism—in this
case 'a principle of affection' (72) [a
philosophical notion of materialism]. This
means that power is both active and passive, a
'power to effect and the power to be affected,
production and sensibility'. It follows from
this that god also has the power to be affected in
an absolutely infinite number of ways.
Deleuze makes a link with Nietzsche: 'the will to
power is always accompanied by a feeling of
power', and being affected should not be seen as
suffering, but as playing an active role.
Hardt reminds us that for Spinoza an affection can
be an action or a passion, the formal arising from
an internal, and the latter from an external cause
[so being open to power is also a kind of
power]. In another terminology, internal
affections are called active, and external ones
passive. In the diagram, page 73, power is
first divided into power to exist and an equal
power to be affected, and that power to be
affected is then divided into active and passive
affections [in a kind of logical tree]. We
can't get very far by looking at how power
manifests itself in existence, but we can make
more progress investigating the power to be
affected and its types, both internal and
external, active and passive. This becomes
an ethical or political project to favour active
affections and minimize passive ones. [If we
insist on the active busy role of the modern
individual? We are really close to Maslow
here?]. This is depicted as a last minute,
timely conversion to practice, but it has to be
fleshed out with reference to the original
principles of 'singularity, univocity, and power'
(73).
We have to clear away a perceived subjectivist or
idealist tendency in Spinoza, and offer a strictly
materialist interpretation instead, which could
involve tensions between Spinoza and
Deleuze. We begin with noticing the
philosophical notion of materialism as opposed to
idealism, which asserts the priority of mind over
body. Materialism insists on an 'equality in
principle between the corporeal and the
intellectual' (74). Deleuze wants to go
further [?] and assert the priority of being in
all the attributes, including thought. The
alternative would be to allow dependence on
thought, as in idealism. The problem arises
when Spinoza defines an attribute as something
that the intellect perceives of a substance, and
argues later that it's even possible that the same
thing can be designated by two names, introducing
a nominalism, and the role of the perceiving
subject. The sections have long been
controversial. Hegel takes the idealist
line, seeing the attribute as something in the
intellect that limits substance or determines it,
something external to it. However, the
intellect, strictly speaking, is a mode of
thought, something coming after the attributes,
including the attribute of thought. Hegel
apparently deals with this by blaming Spinoza for
inconsistency. Deleuze's reading is
different, and for him, the intellect plays only a
secondary role, 'as an objective and invisible
agent of representation' (75). Perceptions
offered to the intellect are representations of
the forms as they appear. However, there is
a prior relation of attribute to a substance, an
undistorted ontological relation [only perceptible
to the god-like Deleuze, presumably, and not
dependent on his intellect?]. This preserves
'the ontological integrity of the system and
resolves the contradiction' in Spinoza (76) [so
consistency is the main argument].
We're not out of the woods, though because we
still need to explain this representation and
reproduction—'certainly a very weak conception of
expression' (76). Deleuze simply passes on,
refusing to be sidetracked in Hardt's terms:
preserving ontological integrity is more important
than clarifying the text. Deleuze's
materialist ontology is being developed here.
Hardt notices that this makes Deleuze quite
different from the other French philosophers of
the time, who would have followed the
subjectiviste readings. The differences are
explored through Althusser on Marx [!].
Althusser wanted to stress reading as an
active form of production, to dismiss the idea of
immediate vision and other specular
metaphors. Knowledge has its own domain,
however, but this is prior in the sense that we
need to first consider how things are presented to
us [Hardt says this is similar to
phenomenology]. We never simply perceive
objects. However, Deleuze argues that the
intellect only perceives, reproducing the forms
that it grasps, reproducing, not actively
producing. The primary production is
somewhere else, in being. Hardt says this
might mean that the intellect in its reproduction
is a kind of 'affirmation of the productive role
of being'(78), but the activity of being is
antecedent to the intellect. Deleuze also
has a different domain in mind, not society or
capital, but being and its rather simple basic
principles [whether Deleuze should have analysed
society or capital is the issue here, surely,
especially for a political radical like Hardt?],
and again, he wants to maintain ontological
foundations in Spinoza and in his own work.
Hardt says that Deleuze is interested in other
matters like empirical practice, but says we need
empirical terms to grasp them [so a massive
inconsistency between philosophical and empirical
analysis?]. Althusser still wants to argue
that we need to see knowledge as a production to
fight off idealist views of knowledge, to see it
as theoretical practice. The Deleuzian
position does not examine this practice [!], and
so is an idealist. Althusser
seems particularly good at suggesting that the
normal conception of practice is only the mirror
image of theory in a specular system. it would
follow from this that 'Deleuze's philosophy can
have no practical power; it can merely attempt to
think the world, not change it' (79).
Hardt intends to use this challenge to guide
future analysis of Deleuze on practice.
Deleuze wants to avoid a different kind of
idealism in the work on Spinoza, one that would
assert the priority of mind over body. The
argument proceeds through the notion of
'ontological parallelism' (80). This follows
from the university of being, which implies that
the attributes are all equal expressions.
They are further argued to be autonomous, again
reasserting that the mind is not primary, drawing
upon Spinoza's critique of Descartes. Mind
and body are autonomous. The mind is a
spiritual automaton [at last!] Following only the
laws of thought, and the body is a corporeal
automaton, following only the laws of
extension. As autonomous, one cannot control
the other.
However, attributes are autonomous but also
organized in 'a parallel order', also known as an
'equality of principle'(81). This is to be
understood as having autonomous and equal ways of
participating in being, as being expressed by
being, 'said in the same voice'. From the
point of view of substance, they are the same
expression, properly parallel ontologically.
It follows that the processes of modification to
produce modes is also the same modification [same
process, but down a stage]. An implication
follows for speculation—any proposition about one
of the attributes must be affirmed equally to the
others [remember that we only know two, thought
and extension]: so structures in the mind should
have parallel structures or functions in the body
[Hardt's suggest that if we follow this
consistently, we should be able to identify the
true acts of the body].
This consistent development of parallelism helps
dethrone the apparent priority of thought, even if
Spinoza himself does not argue that. [There
is an attempt to rework Spinoza's apparent
priority of thought as a different kind of
parallelism on the epistemological level] there is
an ambiguity in Spinoza especially in a scholium
accompanying this commentary, which helps Deleuze
try out an argument to be developed later—that
there was an epistemological detour in order to
reach ontological parallelism. Hardt's
suggest that this is 'not very well
substantiated in the text'(83), but Deleuze's
reading is at least possible. Deleuze's
argument further separates powers and
attributes—the latter infinite, but the former
confined to the power to exist and the power to
think. The power to exist 'is the formal
essence of god. All the attributes
participate equally in this essence'(83).
This reasserts ontological parallelism.
However, the power to think is a different
'objective essence of god'[graspable by the
intellect? Something that arises once god
has existed?]. This helps Deleuze argues
that the power to think is only the same as the
power to act and exist, not prior: indeed, Deleuze
wants to argue that the power to think is
dependent on the power to exist, argued in terms
of objective being requiring formal being.
What about the ability of thought to generate
ideas of ideas, to reflect? This would be an
early accounts of the structure of interior
consciousness, threatening ontological priority,
and replacing the dynamism of being with the
dynamism of thought. Deleuze is concerned
'to preserve the ontologically quality of the
attributes'(84). He does this by
distinguishing powers and attributes again, and
then formal and objective powers—the power to
think is an objective power working on ideas, but
ideas are dependent on the formal power of
existing in the first place. Further, ideas
about things involve connections between different
attributes, while ideas take place only as modes
of thought, operating merely with conceptual
distinctions. These are not real
distinctions found in being, not formal
distinctions, mere differences of degree not
differences of nature. Although this might
be an important human quality [and obviously
central to the idea of critical politics], 'this
privilege is ontologically insignificant'(85) [the
moment where the scholastic agenda triumphs?].
Hardt's own view is that another argument is
possible. Negri, apparently has seen an
evolution in Spinozan thought, where the theory of
the attributes becomes less relevant anyway [as
his political commitments changed?] Hardt suggests
another alternative—that thought is privileged
because Spinoza is pursuing an inquiry, and there
is a confusion between 'the form of...
research...[and]... The nature of being'
(86) [the moment when philosophers assume that
they really are speaking on behalf of being and
all the rest of us]. Marx has made clear the
difference between the mode of enquiry and the
mode of presentation [forschung and darstellung],
arguing that you need to work through the material
first and tracked down the inner connections, and
then present the results in a different way.
Spinoza can therefore be seen as discussing the
attributes in order only to get to the connections
of being and its real movement. The movement
also allows a shift from speculation to practice
based on the body not the mind. Again the
notion of power is going to be the crucial hinge.
Deleuze develops Spinoza more positively in his
discussion of the true and the adequate idea,
initially seen as the discussion about the best
way to speculate. Adequacy is seen as a
matter of being as the expression of causes.
The notion of the mind as spiritual automaton that
produces ideas autonomously, helps reject a
correspondence theory of truth, which is rejected
as a mere formal connection, not an account of the
activity of the development of true ideas.
Descartes notion of clear and distinct ideas as
the basis of truth is more promising, because at
least it refers to the content of the idea.
But this is still a matter of representation
rather than the causes of ideas [produced by the
spiritual automaton, so that 'the cause of any
idea is always another idea'(89)]. We can't
see how ideas are connected by simply seeing their
clarity or distinctness. The proper power to
think involves examining the causes of
ideas. [There is also a curious phrase about
the spiritual automaton reproducing reality in
producing ideas in the proper order, 89].
Without tracing ideas back to causes, we have not
explained them, no matter how clear or distinct
they might be. Clarity and distinctness are
only the superficial qualities of true ideas any
way—the issue really is one of 'expression of
causality, production and power'.
Hence the shift to the adequate idea, the notion
of the true relation of an idea to its cause
[proximate cause is another idea, formal cause is
the power to think]. When the spiritual
automaton joins ideas, it produces a 'unity of
logical form and expressive content', a movement
internal to thought. [Some notion of the
automatic development of true ideas?]. Truth
is defined, singularly, like being, as something
which 'envelops and expresses its own cause'(90)
[circularity again, but clearly referring to
adequacy]. This involves a shift towards
ontological truth—'Adequate ideas are expressive,
and inadequate ideas are mute'in terms of their
ability to reveal the structures of being and/or
thought, which is parallel anyway. It
follows that adequate ideas increase the power of
thought by revealing more and more about 'the
structure and connections of being'.
Clearly, this argument depends on ontological
parallelism.
However, most of us don't get that far, and have
to operate with inadequate ideas. Spinoza's
project is to change this situation, to develop
truth and the power to think. Ontological
parallelism means that this will be a project
involving the body, hence the importance of asking
what a body can do.
How can we increase our power to think, or
approach god in theological terms? We won't
get far if we remain with an epistemological
foundation, relying on the activities of the mind
alone. We have to shift to the body and
examine empirically how they are composed.
Again we do this in a characteristic 17th century
way to determine the laws of the interactions of
bodies [why did Deleuze not use more modern
studies of bodies and the origins of ideas?
Hardt's view all along is that he is been modestly
concerned with examining resources for his own
views—why Spinoza? Scholasticism and the
role of the university must be equally important].
Bodies are seen as dynamic relationships subject
to change, and that encounters between them
produce in difference, compatibility, or
incompatibility, as in the action of poison
etc. An examination of these activities,
'Spinoza's physics' will provide an ethical
foundation. The question of what a body can
do is to be seen as a question of what powers it
might have, not the power to act spontaneously but
the power to be affected. Again, being
affected involves being influenced by active and
passive affections, and increasing power means
developing more active ones. Passive
affections, including suffering, express nothing,
and are to be seen as 'the lowest degree of our
power to act'[quoting Deleuze's big book on
Spinoza, 92]. So asking what the body can do
is really a question about what powers might be
achieved. Spinoza's notion of conatus
is central [here, it is defined as striving,
rather than some attempt to persist].
Conatus is 'the motor that animates being as the
world'(93), but it is also a sensibility driven by
passions [only for humans?]. In most cases,
we are filled with passive affections, since the
power of nature is greater than our own power
[early modernist project?].
Passive affections themselves can be
divided. They arise from encounters which
can be random or driven by chance, and this can
lead to positive or negative relationships
depending on how 'composable' the bodies
are. Positive relationships tend to be seen
as good or useful and to produce a joyful form of
affection. This increases the power to
act. Negative relationships produce
sadness. Actual encounters 'are more
complicated than either of these two limit
cases'[as the utilitarians discovered] (94), but
we can produce a new chart. The power to
exist equals the power to be affected. The
power to be affected has two components active and
passive affections, and passive affections
themselves are divided into joyful and sad passive
affections [so we have already simplified by
leaving out the mixed cases]. Because the
passions affect us differently, it is difficult to
reach agreement 'and the large majority of chance
encounters are sad'(95). But is Spinoza
downhearted? This pessimism leads to a
practical project to become active, as in
Nietzsche. Spinoza, however adds the
dimension of social experience to maximize joy.
Here we have to move from speculation to practice
[or politics]. It should begin with joy, as
a practical equivalent to philosophical
affirmation. We might begin by minimising
sadness [by withdrawing from contact with most
plebs?]. More positively, we should
investigate bodies to see if they can produce
common relationships with us, seek out compatible
encounters. [Already it's looking pretty
conservative]. We should be guided here by
the formation of common notions, which always
depend on 'an idea of the similarity of
composition in existing modes' (96). Again,
there are different types, some more universal
than others, some turning on a general similarity
of human bodies, and, more useful less universal
common notions, involving local points of view and
specific interactions. Common notions will
be adequate ideas, formally thinkable, and
materially indicating expression [not unlike
Weber's idea of adequacy]. Adequate ideas
develop from an initial recognition of something
in common. However, the tests of adequacy
should still remember the material or biological
dimensions, and should be seen as fundamentally
practical regardless of their speculative
qualities, even though they are presented
speculatively in early Spinoza.
'The experience of joy is the spark'(98) for the
development of further ideas, moving through the
idea of a common notion. However, joy can
still be a passive affection and we must go
further, to develop common notions until they are
adequate, to get active joy, 'substituting an
internal cause from external cause; or, more
precisely,… Enveloping or comprehending the
cause within the encounter itself' (99), a
combination of corporeal and epistemological
logic. [This looks awfully like
rationalising what happens anyway, deciding to
choose and celebrate the options you're
provided with, as with Bourdieu]. We seem to
develop the active joys when we develop
adequate ideas rather than joyful experiences,
when we grasp commonality, overcoming passive
passions. Deleuze really rates this
argument. Hardt says it involves seeing
being as a composition of possibilities, capable
of producing more powerful relationships, more
powerful bodies as processes 'envelop'
causes. [It is the old argument that
knowledge and only knowledge is power?].
Another chart, on page 100, shows a dynamic
relation: there are active affections and passive
affections, and passive ones can be either sad or
joyful. This time, however joyful passive
affections can lead to the development of common
notions which will feedback and become active
affections. This is an analysis from below,
as it were, complementing the speculative analysis
from above. Conatus 'animates this entire
operation', which adds desire to the analysis of
motion and rest. Deleuze identifies in this
whole analysis a learning process, learning to
become active, '"an educational process"'.
Hardt describes this as 'an apprenticeship in
power, an education in virtue'.
Practice produces a parallel epistemology,
complimenting the formal epistemology of the
earlier work: an activist interpretation of common
notions as opposed to a logical one. Now,
'The formation of common notions is the practical
constitution of reason' (101). Hardt says
this particularly material notion of the intellect
also owes something to the birth of modern
industry, and the development of tools—there are
intellectual tools as well which can improve our
productivity. Spinoza therefore has different
kinds of knowledge—imagination and opinion,
reason, and finally intuition. These are
organized in a hierarchy, and we should begin with
the first kind, even though it is necessarily
false [because it does not speculate about
causes?], and even though most of our knowledge is
of this kind. Reason will not guide most of
every day life. We must build on opinions,
which involves the recognition that they might be
partially true. This is because they are
formed from signs rather than expressions,
implying that they are externally caused.
However, the imagination can reveal the
possibility of forming common notions. In
the first place, experience provides us with
'indicative signs' (102): opinion and revelation
only offer us 'imperative signs'whose origin is
obscure. Imagination can be influenced by
future corporeal encounters. Common notions
originate in imagination, and reason should be
seen as linked to imagination 'on a continuum as
different stages or planes in the process of
intellectual constitution' (103). However,
we shift to reason when we begin to consider
things not as contingent but as necessary [having
a necessary cause?]: This enables us to build a
permanent and consistent understanding, a
deliberate construction of the common notion,
based on '"necessity, presence and
frequency"'(103) [we know from
Durkheim's discussion of social facts that
necessity and frequency involve really two
different sorts of arguments]. Common
notions can preserve affections even while
developing reason, moving from contingency to
necessity.
This is an epistemological practice, demonstrated
in another diagram, on page 103: there are two
kinds of knowledge, the first kind involves
opinion and imagination, but imagination can help
to develop a common notion, which will then
produce the second kind of knowledge
[reason]. This is a way of demystifying
reason, seeing how it is produced, and linked to
common knowledge. Again, this is not the
dialectic of the progressive movement, where the
common notion does not negate imagination but
preserves it, and there is no total split between
reason and imagination.
Hardt can then return to the Althusserian
critique. Deleuze finds in Spinoza 'an
extended drama' (104) about the relation between
theory and practice, or between speculation and
ontology [through the difference between
investigation and presentation as above—a kind of
model to link theory and practice? However,
practice is very theoretically constrained, and
seen as an embryonic theory?]. This is not
too far away from Althusser—theory draws from
practice, and practices dependent on theory in the
classic Marxist work, and it is not dissimilar in
Deleuze's Spinoza, given the change from
speculation to the idea of constitutive
practice. In an interview with Foucault,
Deleuze talks about relays between theory and
practice: '"Practice is a set of relays from one
theoretical point to another, theories are relayed
from one practice to another. No theory can
develop without eventually encountering a wall, a
practice is necessary for piercing this wall"'
(105). Theory provides the terrain on which
practice can arise, and vice versa: 'Each provides
the conditions for the existence and development
of the other'. However, Althusser
finally gives the priority to theory, as when the
October revolution was based on Capital.
Even in his later self criticism , he does not
really repent, despite his acknowledgement of
theoreticism, which failed to connect
philosophical struggles to class struggles.
This is because he remained 'too Hegelian'(107).
For Deleuze there can be no synthesis of theory
and practice and no priority, and the two
activities are 'autonomous and equal in principle'
(106) [but then he is not interested in
revolutionary overthrow and the development of
revolutionary consciousness which will never
emerge from common notions, for Marxists.
Hardt and Negri are going to disagree with
this of course]. Deleuze corrects his own
theoreticism with his insistence on materialist
philosophy, in the sense that thought is not
privileged [Scholasticism is not corrected].
The relation between theory and practice can be
understood exactly as the relation between body
and mind, as above. There might be 'a
theoretical automaton and a practical automaton as
expressions that equally refer back to the power
of being' (107).
However, these are really polemical positions, to
avoid subordination of one by the other, and to
deny the sufficiency of theoretical reasons for
revolution. In 1917, for example there was a
'an accumulation of desires, imaginations, and
powers that coincided and bec[a]me necessary in
the event', a process that turned joyful passions
into action. This is only polemical, but
nobody yet has realized 'what practice can
do'. There is a need to bring bodies back
in, to rescue practice from recuperation as
theory, to see constitution as having a different
logic, a different form of accumulation of
elements from below with creative and
unforeseeable consequences, 'an open logic of
organization'. [You can see the elements of
Autonomism and the later work with Negri].
Politics emerges as an issue for bodies, and
Deleuze realizes this through Spinoza's discussion
of the power of the body and the development of
common notions 'in terms of the logic of
assemblage' (108), as constitutive. 'the
common notion is an ontological mechanism that
forges being out of becoming, necessity out of
chance'. Joyful passions turn into adequate
reason. We therefore have an ontological
account of politics, which in Spinoza turns into
an argument to defend the theory of right—what
bodies can do involves 'natural right'. This
develops first through considering the lowest
forms of social organization—no one is born
rational and no one is born a citizen, but we have
to work with what we have, including a fundamental
weakness of the human condition. At least
this means that it is pointless to impose some
order based on transcendent elements, including
ideas of duty or morality.
We must begin with power and its expression, to
develop the utmost of what we can do, how we can
escalate our powers beyond limits, free from
external order. This is 'the open expression
of multiplicity… the freedom of
multiplicity, the freedom of society in anarchy'
(109). We must move away from the existing
state of sadness and limit, by organizing more
productive encounters, and this is the role of the
civil state, to permit us to combine and extend
our power. This builds on natural right,
which is preserved and rationalised.
'In this transformation the multiplicity of
society is forged into a multitude' (110) [and
note 20 says this 'Spinozan conception' is
discussed further by Negri in The Savage
Anomaly]. The multitude is
similarly 'open to antagonism and conflict',
(110) but is struggling to develop its power and
develop its civil right. 'And the rule of
the multitude is democracy', a form of a 'anarchy
in democracy… The absolute role of the
multitude through the equality of its constituent
members'(110), arising from increased positive
encounters. There should therefore be, in
politics, a parallel process to the
epistemological development of common notions, 'a
corporeal common notion that serves to organize
the… encounters of social bodies into
coherent, adequate and joyful encounters' (110),
and which will develop reason in the form of
community.
Thrilling as these ideas are, we can only get so
far by developing a theory, as Deleuze does in his
reading of Spinoza. 'Only social practice
can break through this wall by giving body to the
process of political assemblage' (111).
Chapter four Conclusion An Apprenticeship in
Philosophy
We have red Deleuze's work as a progressive
evolution, with the intention of showing that
metaphysics is not dead and that it contains
radical alternatives 'still very alive in the
contemporary problems we face' (112). This
is also Hardt's own apprenticeship. There are four
major themes
Ontology. This is grounded in the
notion of difference and singularity in Bergson
and Spinoza. Deleuze gets the notion of the
positive movement of being from Bergson, and it is
distinguished from mechanicism and platonic
difference. Above all, it opposes hegelian
difference and its abstractions, including
causality and contradiction, which are classically
external. Bergson operates with efficient
causality so that 'the cause always inheres within
its effect' (113). In Spinoza, this
positivity of being is described as its
singularity and univocity. Singularity means
that 'being is different in itself' and thus able
to express other distinctions. This makes it
remarkable. It requires no external
reference and thus is singular for all stop being
expresses itself in its movement, and thus
expression can be seen as a form of internal
causality. It also implies univocity.
This puts it on the highest plane. Deleuze
is work shifts 'from negation to difference'(114),
avoiding the dialectic. In this sense, Hegel
is being rebuked by an appeal to earlier work that
he thought he had transcended. The
'efficient difference' of being produces real
multiplicity. Only materialism can grasp
this, leading to arguments to reject the priority
of mind over body and replace it with an
equality. 'Deleuze's ontology requires a
materialist perspective because any priority
accorded to thought would weaken the internal
structure of being'[and we can't have that, given
all the earlier work to establish it]. Being
lies behind both thought and matter—'it is both
logically prior to, and comprehensive of thought
and extension equally'. [Luckily],
expression means that 'being is always already
actual… Fully expressed in body and thought'
(115). Overall, Deleuze establishes the
alternative tradition to the one we're used
to. Hardt also likes it because 'A positive,
materialist ontology is above all an ontology of
power'
Affirmation. This has long been seen
as a bad thing by the Hegelian tradition including
the Frankfurt School who saw it as a matter of
passive acceptance or naive optimism.
Contemporary Hegelians like Butler still think the
power of negation is important to critical
thinking. However, although Deleuze rejects
the Hegelian form of negation, he still has an
alternative conceptions of critique.
'Affirmation is intimately tied to antagonism',
especially the total critique that will alone lead
to proper construction. This negation is not
dialectical and is thus more complete [affirmation
fully destabilizes reified patterns?]
We first saw this argument in Nietzsche's critique
of Kant [repeated later in difference and
repetition?] that says that Kantian critique is
partial because it still preservesthe
transcendental, the 'suprasensible as a privileged
terrain' (116). As a result 'Kant can treat
claims to truth and morality without endangering
truth and morality themselves'. This
leaves conventional values intact. Total
critics are 'always insurrectional' by comparison,
refusing any relation, even a dialectical one,
with the conservative attitude, and certainly not
attempting to recuperate the real essence of its
enemy. It is the force of the critique is
total, however: 'This is not to say that all
that is present is negated'[a weasel here
surely? Reoccurs in Maasumi's radicalism
about the destruction of all categories?]. The
point in Deleuze is to open the possibility of
affirmation, the release of creative forces,
breaking with repetition. [For the second
time, this is argued with a reference to an
obscure bit about Nietzsche and the relation
between Ariadne and Dionysus! The point is
to argue that this is real affirmation, 'the
affirmation of affirmation itself']. At the
same time, there is an notion of vulgar
affirmation, which Deleuze is not supporting—'The
yes of the ass, the yes of the one who does not
know how to say no… only the one who knows
how to wield the power for negation can pose a
real affirmation' (116-7) [only philosophers
then?]. There is also a certain release from
responsibility for what is, not to bother with
existing values but to create new ones [so to
ignore Marxism in favour of some vague values to
come?]. For Deleuze, 'affirmation is
actually the creation of being'(117), which is
handy because this links ontology to ethics.
[I have just notice that in Empire,
Hardt and Negri suggest that this is their main
role as revolutionary philosophers, to provide an
ontology of the multitude. As if revolutions
happen as a result of philosophy —which,
incidentally, Hardt has denied earlier himself in
the bit about the October revolution]
Practice. Ethics must enter the field
of practice, and here the conception of joy in
Spinoza helps. The joy that practice brings
complements the affirmation of philosophy
[speculation is the Spinozian term]. This
leads Deleuze to investigate power again based on
the productivity of being. Deleuze
distinguishes active and reactive forms of power,
fleshed out in the discussion on Spinoza as a
matter of adequacy and inadequacy. Only the
adequate 'gives full view to both the productivity
and producability of being'(118). [I think
the argument here is that being produces actively
but also has a power to be affected—by
politics?]. Back at the human level,
the power to act and exist looks like inexplicable
spontaneity, so we need the additional
classifications of power into joyful and sad
passive affections. Sad passive affections
dominate human life, but this is realistic rather
than pessimistic, introducing the need to increase
our power to become joyful. This leads to
the mechanism of chance encounters, some of which
agree with us and increase our power, and this
passive joyful perfection, or passion can be made
more adequate by forming common notions—'they are
the raw material for the construction of the
common notion… [which]…is already latent in
the joyful passion' (118) [only a definitional
matter really, turning on how you define
joy?]. Common notions are adequate in the
sense that they comprehend the cause of the
affection, and this also makes them active, 'no
longer contingent on the chance encounter…
the joy that returns' (119).
This is the link with ontology, and its notions of
composability of being—'Being is a hybrid
structure constituted through joyful
practice'. Common notions help us create new
assemblages by comprehending the cause, and these
are 'ontological assemblages, and thus the active
constitution of being' (119). [So much to
unpack here—is this connection between human
politics and the modes of being workable? Surely
it is only an analogy? What are the
political implications? We have to operate
with being, but luckily being is really
constructive and creative, much more creative than
bureaucracies or capitalism? The main role
for an activist is to make the point about
operating with being, to encourage activism by
arguing that it is supported by modern philosophy?
We have no choice long term anyway because no-one
can hold off being for long?].
Constitution. This has arisen in
the U.S. in terms of debating the political
consequences of post structuralism, obviously with
different possibilities as with all
philosophy. We can manage this by asking
'what can Deleuze's thought afford us?… What
are the useful tools we find in his philosophy for
furthering our own political endeavours?'.
Hardt sees Deleuze as offering 'tools for the
constitution of a radical democracy'. The
multiplicity of organization is to be contrasted
with the multiplicity of order, and the notion of
power as an assemblage with actual deployments of
power. This can look at first as if it were
liberalism, an advocacy of an open society driven
by the activities of its members. However,
'this political refusal of teleology leads
directly to a philosophical refusal of ontology,
because ontology itself is presumed to carry with
it a transcendental determination of the good'
(120). This shows the residual power of
Plato and Hegel.
However, there are ontological radical
alternatives, as Deleuze has discovered.
'Deleuzian being is open to the intervention of
political creations and social becomings', which
are to be seen as the producibility of being [so
human agents are required after all? Or is
human politics merely a subset of the general
producibility of being which goes on somehow
without them as well?]. Hardt again argues
that the power of the society also means that it
has a power to be affected. Overall, power
involves, as an expression 'the free conflict and
composition of the field of social forces'[getting
to be a kind of conflict sociology?].
However there can be no plan or blueprint, only 'a
continual process of composition and decomposition
through social encounters on an immanent field of
forces' (120-1) [the immanent field of forces is
interesting—as a limit? As a long-term trend
towards democracy rooted in being itself—assuming
this process of composition and decomposition is
democracy]. This means that radical change
is possible in principle at any time. The
normal vertical structure of social institutions
also 'receive a strictly immanent determination,
and thus remain always and completely susceptible
to restructuring, reform and destruction'[and the
Communards are admired here]. To the
transcendent construction of social order from
above, correspond the assemblages, 'the mechanisms
of social organization from below' (121). At
this level, practice is 'the motor of social
creation', another necessary connection between
productivity and the producibility of being.
Practice will also bring about destruction and
decomposition, however. 'The model of this
constitution is the general assembly, the absolute
and equal inclusion of the entire immanent plane'.
The notion of social assemblage exceeds
individualism, and promises constant change in
relationships [a new and better kind of individual
relation to the collective]. The
'development of joyful social relationships moves
instead between multiplicity and the
multitude'. [Almost defined here as a social
body or plane of composition that is 'ever more
powerful, while they remain at the same time open
to internal antagonisms']. The multitude has
'a common set of behaviours, needs and
desires'. Multitude emerge from 'the dead
forces of social order', just as labour reemerges
from its exploitation by capital for Marx.
In this way, the constitution of the multitude
'raises the multiplicity to a higher level of
power' (122).
However, we only have hints here which we need to
flesh out, 'a general orientation' that might
guide research into contemporary social
assemblages. There is also an embryonic
political programme to construct assemblages from
'social bodies with compatible internal
relationships, with composable practices and
desires'. This involves investigating 'the
material mechanisms of social aggregation that can
constitute adequate, affirmative, joyful
relationships', and Hardt thinks we might be able
to find these 'in the existing social practices,
in the affective expressions of popular culture,
in the networks of laboring cooperation'.
Thus 'Filling out the passage from multiplicity to
multitude remains for us the central project for a
democratic political practice'(122) [Reads better
as a programme for the liberation from constraint
of the restless culturally equipped new petit
bourgeoisie?]
back to Deleuze page
|
|