Notes on: Lacan J (1968) [1953]
The Language of the Self: The Function
of Language in Psychoanalysis. Trans and
with notes[and an essay] by Anthony
Wilden. Baltimore: The John Hopkins Press.
Dave Harris
Translators Introduction
The style is described as 'dense and allusive' and
it is not clear whether he 'the spelling out the
obvious or contributing to the ambiguity of the
ambiguous' (vii). Summary is impossible, so is any
attempt to reduce the style: Lacan himself has
said that we have to be very vigilant in the use
of 'the Word'. There are 'few concessions to the
uninitiated' (viii), and 'the characteristic
French carelessness over references, usually
relying on his audience to recognize the echoes
from his own and other works', which gives
problems if you are not located in that context or
tradition. It presupposes deep acquaintance with
Freud and with Heidegger and Sartre,, with a
corresponding 'technical and philosophical
vocabulary' as well as with structural linguistics
and structural anthropology. There is also the
French tradition of precociousness. It should be
read as offering 'brilliant and provoking
intuitions, couched in aphoristic form' (ix)..
The notes refer to some earlier works from the
same period and some technical terms explained.
There is also an essay.
[An intellectual biography ensues.
Apparently, Lacan discovered the importance of
language from his earlier phenomenological
attempts to describe psychoanalytic experience. He
became aware of the important implicit relation
with the other in language, and how the analyst
should be seen as an important listener or
interlocutor. Later transference will be
explicitly described as a dialectical relationship
between subject and subject, with language
offering a clear objectification of the properties
of the patient, partly revealing the analyst's own
prejudices or passions. This notion of
transference, especially counter transference, is
linguistic in origin, appearing in permanent forms
of communication which constitute objects. It
affects both subjects in the analysis. It offers a
series of blocks to further analysis and must be
overcome by a definite technical neutrality,
trying to grasp how patients project their own
past into a discourse, and how the analyst is also
the intended listener, someone who will help with
meaning.
Lacan wanted to initially promote the Imaginary
order '(perception, hallucination, and their
derivatives)' (xii), the Symbolic order '(the
order of discursive and symbolic action)' and the
Real. These were initially found in the mirror
stage as the root of all subsequent forms of
identification. The symbolic order is to be
understood through anthropology, 'especially by
Marcel Mauss and Lévi-Strauss' (xiii). The mirror
stage is the centre of 'Lacan's heresy', although
Lacan claims that it is based on a return to
Freud: he was responsible for reintroducing him in
French, and in staving off existential readings
which were then popular. He also integrated
Lévi-Strauss with psychoanalysis and used the
terms of structural linguistics especially
metaphor and metonym, the signifier and the
signified. He distinguished between 'need, demand,
and desire'.
His seminars have been substantial events,
attended by the Tel Quel group including Roland
Barthes, Foucault, Derrida and Althusser and
students from a number of disciplines. His revived
interest in Freud.
This piece was originally published as a discourse
in a journal, La Psychoanalyse, and
republished in Ecrits. Méconnaissance is
translated as '"failure to recognize"'. Capital
letters indicate special usages. Phantasy is a
standard Freudian term. [According to the Klein
Trust it means 'the
mental representation of those somatic events in
the body that comprise the instincts, and are
physical sensations interpreted as relationships
with objects that cause those sensations. Phantasy
is the mental expression of both libidinal and
aggressive impulses and also of defence mechanisms
against those impulses. Much of the therapeutic
activity of psychoanalysis can be described as an
attempt to convert unconscious phantasy into
conscious thought...{Freud} thought of it as a phylogenetically
inherited capacity of the human mind. Klein... and
her successors have emphasised that phantasies
interact reciprocally with experience to form the
developing intellectual and emotional
characteristics of the individual; phantasies are
considered to be a basic capacity underlying and
shaping thought, dream, symptoms and patterns of
defence.] 'Meaning' or 'sense' implies subjective
meaning, while 'signification' implies objective
[it is the same word in French sens] . Discourse
can sometimes mean a more general form of human
communication as when kinship systems communicate
about marriage. The French terms do carry extra
meaning, just as the German ones do in Freud
although the distinctions are not always carried
over into translation.
[My own
intentions are much less exalted, of course --
to gain a basic understanding of some of it,
especially re the debate with Deleuze and
Guattari]
Prefatory Note
The context for this piece was an early split
between different psychoanalytic movements in
France. A particular turn criticised by Lacan
tried to argue that everything human could be
understood by a single discipline — neurobiology.
Lacan offers many criticisms. Lacan launched
further splits. In one of his pieces for La
Psychoanalyse, he defines discourse as 'a
process of language which compels and constrains
truth' while analytic discourse involves '"the
putting into place of unities which produce and
repeat themselves, whatever may be the principal
it assigns to the transformations of working
system. Analysis, then, properly so-called, is the
theory which treats of concepts of elements and
combination as such"' (xxiv).
There are also implications for the training of
analysts and how to deal with transference and
counter transference, but there have always been
general concerns about 'the status of human
discourse in analysis'(xxv), as opposed to
behaviourism or biological accounts of instincts,
or a medical approach towards symptoms. Stressing
discourse puts 'the status of the subject in
question', which Freud did.
Lacan's presentation of this piece divided the
audience. Some wish to prevent him from speaking.
Lacan was to argue that there were no clear
theoretical principles and psychoanalysis at the
time, not relying on Freud was a better way
forward even though they were ambiguous. He
proposed to clarify them by linking to language as
understood by structural anthropology. At least,
they had to be kept from being submerged in
'routine usage'. Psychoanalysts have to be
discouraged from seeing their own work as
something magical. Schools of psychoanalysis
should not tightly regulate membership.
Psychoanalysts should be much more reflexive about
their own activities. Nevertheless, this piece was
written in haste, but that also shows that the
Word is central to creation, in this case helping
to explain the disorder of psychoanalysis, '"in
order to comprehend [its] coherence in the Real"'
(xxviii).
Modern psychoanalysis has lost interest in the
role of language in favour of an emphasis on the
resistance of the object — for Lacan 'an alibi of
the subject'. In particular, psychoanalysis has
failed to grasp the function of the Imaginary or
fantasies and how objects of been variously
constituted at different stages [note 2, page 92
explains that people experience the Real through
the imaginary and the symbolic functions. The
Imaginary that lacks sufficient power of
distinction, and thus '"inundate singularity", and
so cannot be grasped rationally and has no
"dialectical movement". However, symbols have an
Imaginary support. In dreams, the symbolic becomes
imaginary]. Current efforts to explain the
imaginary seem to wrongly locate it in the
infantile preverbal stage. The second problem
turns on the libidinal implications of objects
[which again ignores the symbolic. Note 3 on page
93 says that phenomenological or existentialist
analysis is particularly being rebuked here to the
extent that it ignores language — and see the
piece on the mirror stage]. The third problem
concerns counter transference and what the analyst
does. The analyst cannot be separated from the
analysis, but their obvious effects have been
sought in the unconscious of the patient. We must
look instead at apparently ineffable stages where
the word emerges, say in childhood training.
Analysts should also stick to their own language
rather than use one which 'offer[s] compensations
for ignorance' (4). This is the proper focus for
psychonalysts — 'the study of the functions of the
Word' (5). Freud himself demonstrates the
importance of language, say when he investigates
children like little Hans by discussions with his
parents, or when looking at Schreber's text,
although he claimed his own was a master
discourse.
Modern psychoanalysis has become a matter of
formal technique, rather similar to obsessional
neurosis, a 'closed circuit' between inadequate
initial definitions and ensuing problems.
Psychoanalysis might be used on modern
psychoanalysts [note 9 explains that it is no good
to just tell the patient the meaning of his
symptom — the point is to encourage recognition
and to overcome initial misrecognition]. Instead,
criticisms seen as aggression, and technical
issues seem to be decided by voting. Instead,
there are Symbolic, Imaginary, and Real conditions
producing defence mechanisms turning on our desire
not to be isolated or undo what has been done,
classic obsessions and classic forms of
'denegation' [Verneinug]. These features are
apparent especially in the American group.
At the Symbolic level, the characteristic
historical dimension of communication in the USA
is an opposite to psychoanalytic experience [?
Their emphasis on clear simple communication?].
Behaviourism dominates their psychology. Analysis
at the other two levels might also be possible,
focusing may be on the imminence of particular
individuals and their enterprises: Lacan suggests
this may be something to do with the domination of
immigrants to the USA, and the 'distancing'
consequences on American culture. There is an
emphasis on the adaptation of the individual to
the social environment, to wards trying to
establish acceptable patterns of conduct, often
seen as objectified human relations and involving
human engineering. Yet this is a study of the
individual that ignores the unconscious and
sexuality. The consequences been to ignore the
role of language and with the specialist language
of Freud. Underlying motives for conduct are not
sufficiently explored. A return to classic
approaches is required to combat this new
orthodoxy.
The first task is to properly grasp the underlying
concepts, and to do this, we must examine 'the
domain of Language… The function of the Word' (8).
This will require close reading Freud to avoid
seeing his concepts as mere 'homonyms of current
notions', seeing his work on the mythical content
of instinct as a literal theory, for example. The
specific case [identified in note 19 page 97]
shows how it's possible to draw logical
conclusions from 'an original misunderstanding'.
Section 1
Psychoanalysis can only work with the patient's
Word as intermediary. And there is no word without
a reply, even if it is silence. Not realising this
exposes us to the power of the Word all the more,
although this is often experienced as a need to
seek some external reality. Thus some people
analyse the behaviour of the patient in order to
find what the subject is not saying, although talk
is still necessary — however it is still seen as a
substitute for failure to analyse. We should
recast all this as trying to establish some
ultimate truth, expressed in talk about 'humbler
needs' (9). Underneath that is an 'appeal of the
void' found in all attempted seductions of the
other.
It is not a matter of introspection. That really
delivers anything of value, although [particularly
narcissistic] patients like introspection, but can
sometimes experience the results as ridiculous.
Monologues offer a 'mirage' (10). A particularly
forced version of introspection can be found in
the practice of free association. That is real
labour, but practice produces only 'a skilled
craftsman' rather than an analyst. Processes of
'"working through"' are likely to encounter 'the
triad: frustration, aggressivity, regression'.
Intuition risks delivering only the self evident.
In the practice lurks a dubious notion of
affectivity — the very 'stigmata of our obtuseness
regarding the subject' (11), and as dubious as
'intellectualisation' instead of real
understanding.
What produces frustration in the patient? Silence
is not as bad as mere approval of 'the subject's
empty Word'. The very discourse of the subject
often involves going back on words, and the
subject becomes aware of the alienating
disconnection of his being, following mere
tinkering with his words. [Note 27 explains that
Lacan thought it necessary to distinguish the
person in analysis from the person who is
speaking. The listening analyst is the third
person. The 'me' as opposed to the I makes a
fourth person. All this is necessary to understand
neurosis. Somewhere in here is a reference to
discourse about the self producing an image in the
Imaginary]. All this explains that frustration is
central to the ego who will always experience
alienated desire: this alienation gets worse if
the patient is allowed to just elaborate his
discourse. Any attempts to reassert some
authenticity by recalling the patient's initial
image of himself are likely to be frustrated by
the approval and pleasure of the analyst.
Generally, no reply to the subject's discourse can
never be adequate.
The aggressivity of the patient is not just to do
with frustrated desire, which most people can
regulate, but it is rather 'the aggressivity of
the slave' who can only respond to frustration
with 'desire of death' (12). The analysts
intervention is often seen as an attempt to
dismantle the imaginary object being constructed
by the subject. The resulting aggression is
sometimes seen in terms of 'resistance'. [Somebody
specific is rebuked here].
Instead, we have to see that the intention of the
subject to produce an image cannot be detached
from symbolic relations which express it. We
cannot distinguish between the speaking 'I' and
the 'me'in the patient self. The analyst must see
gestures as 'silent notes' to accompany and
narcissistic discourse [rather than as privileged
clues to inner states as in Freudian slips?].
There must be no collusion in the objectification
and alienation of the subject. The certainties of
the subject should be suspended and left to play
out in a full discourse [note 31, page 101, says
the analyst can then point out the vein and
therefore regressive character of these
certainties, at the expense of anxiety].
The patient's discourse should not be seen as
completely empty, however, but rather as a token
or password leading to further understanding via
connections. The discourse is a form of
communication, further confirmation that 'the Word
constitutes the Truth' (13), even if the intention
is to deceive. Analysts are able to respond to
different parts of speech, seeing the 'recital of
an everyday event for an apologue addressed to him
that hath ears to hear', for example. Even pauses
and silences can confirm meaning. Adjournments of
the session should also positively punctuate the
discourse.
The point is to encourage regression, 'the
actualization in the discourse of the phantasy
relations reconstituted by an ego' (14). There is
no real regression. It is a matter of inflection
or turns of phrase in language, sometimes that has
to revert to baby talk. Seeing regression as a
state of present reality is another form of
alienating illusion, or 'an alibi of the
psychoanalyst'.
This is an example of how misleading it is to
think of attempting to contact the subject's own
reality as in intuitive or phenomenological
psychology. The relation between analyst and
patient 'excludes all real contact'. Analysts [the
one who claimed to be able to contact the real?]
really offer a kind of 'second sight', as
instructive for them as for the patient. What is
really happening is that the patient filters his
own discourse, often in the form of 'a ready-made
stereoscopic picture' (15) which the supervisor
can read as made up of several themes
[three-dimensional, like the real?], rather like a
musical score. Perhaps swapping roles would make
this clear [note 35, page 102 points out that the
role of language would be clear if there were a
third analyst involved].
Recommendations for a suitable form of attention
to the subject should stress that focus should be
on the word not on some object beyond it. Focus on
objects would surely involve some other mode of
analysis. The object really involves the Imaginary
relation where the patient appears as a 'me'. This
should be dealt with by selective attention: there
is no other way to approach the unconscious [note
36, page 102, cites Freud on the need for tuning
the unconscious of the analyst in order to pick up
what the unconscious of the patient is saying in
free association].
So far we have been talking of 'the empty Word'
where the patient is not talking about his own
desires. In those cases, the recapture of memory
is a crucial part of the therapy,
intersubjectivity is the focus, and symbolic
interpretation replaces the analysis of
resistance. Here we see the full importance of the
Word.
We know that Freud's method was called the talking
cure by one of Breuer's patients. That patient, an
hysteric, [Anna O] led to their discovery of the
traumatic experience as a cause of the symptom.
Putting the event into words led the symptom to
disappear, as long as recollection was vivid
enough [note 37, page 103, explains that it is the
putting of the experience into words which is
crucial, that speech offers a way out]. The
patient becoming aware through speech is still
much more important than mere accurate
recollection. Freud was also aware that speech
under hypnosis was not a matter of becoming aware.
The same confusion between becoming aware and mere
verbalization also limits behaviorist
applications. Becoming aware enables the
connection to be made between the present time and
the origins of the events, and communicates it to
others. Just as with Greek speech [!], The speech
of the patient here is indirect, placed in
quotation marks, implying the presence of others.
[Lots more classical allusions ensue to
distinguish this sort of therapeutic memory or
re-memory and the mere recollections derived under
hypnosis].
Becoming aware is located both in the Imaginary
and the Real. The point is not whether it is true
or false exactly, but rather that it offers a
notion of 'Truth in the Word'(17). Its truth lies
in its relation to contemporary reality. Only the
Word can act as a witness to past events however.
The Freudian test of continuity in recollection is
not that each authentic incident should recall the
entirety of the past [apparently implied by
Bergson], but rather a matter of arriving at the
history which balances 'chronological certitude'
with an account of the primal scene, but he wants
to explain 'all the resubjectifications of the
event' (18) in order to explain its effects,
re-structuration is that take place after the
event. The patient had periods where the primal
scene was latent, but Freud ignores those [note
46, page 105 says Freud explained this in terms of
deferred action], even though, these periods
indicate 'times for understanding'. At particular
moments, the patient was able to decide what the
original event meant. Lacan sees these differences
between times for understanding and times the
concluding as functions linked purely logically
[note 47, page 105, relates an experiment where
three prisoners have to discover who is wearing a
black or a white patch on the back. They cannot
communicate directly. They only solve the problem
by putting themselves in the place of the others
and trying to work out deductions by looking at
actions in time. First they wait in time for
understanding — no one moves, so no one can see to
black patches — followed by a time for conclusion
where each concludes that therefore he has a white
patch].
The whole novelty of the Freudian approach turns
on the way in which the patient reconstructs his
history in language addressed to the other. This
account still might show particular
discontinuities, and other methods may be equally
good at treatment, but only the Freudian method
explains the symptom rather than just hoping to
cure it. The result of these admittedly limited
approaches was nevertheless 'to constitute a
domain' (19). The use of the Word is central to
convey a meaning; the domain is the concrete
discourse; it operates in history that is one
which 'constitutes the emergence of Truth in the
Real'.
When people commit to analysis, they accept that
they will be doing it in locution. This in turn
implies a listener or co-locuter. So 'the locuter
is constituted in... intersubjectivity' (20).
Speech and response is the only way to show the
continuity in the subject motivations: this can
only appear in 'the intersubjective continuity of
the discourse in which the subject's history is
constituted'. The subject may vary his account of
his history, for example under the influence of
therapeutic drugs, but only 'psychoanalytic
interlocution'will be effective.
The Freudian unconscious can be understood as a
part of that discourse, something
'transindividual', not immediately available to
the patient in his attempt to reconstruct a
continuous discourse [although note 50 explains
that insights disclosed during psychoanalysis, or
rather transference, are particularly convincing
to the patient].
At this point, note 49, pages 107-8 clarifies
Lacan's elaboration of the notion of
intersubjectivity. It is not just the relation to
the other. The subject has to emerge from
signifiers which '"cover him in an Other"', and
only then can he emerge as a subject with desire.
The emphasis on the thinking cogito confuses the
subject and consciousness in general, which will
be based on misrecognition and the influence of
the mirror stage. Human beings are caught in the
Symbolic order from the beginning. Subjectivity
appears to emerge from consciousness because of
the incompleteness {béance, apparently
implying openness and vulnerability} of the
Imaginary relations toward others. Only the Word
permits a full entrance into subjectivity, as we
see with the fort! da! game. This moment
is constantly reproduced whenever subjects address
themselves to the Other. This Other is absolute,
and can nullify the subject by making him into an
object. This is the '"dialectic of
intersubjectivity"' which runs throughout Lacan's
analysis. It is represented in the famous diagram
Schema L {lambda} ['inconcsient' is the
unconscious. The terms are not translated because
Lacan apparently insists they are not ordinary
words but scientific terms]. The imaginary
relation is what goes on in the mirror stage as a
form of reciprocal objectification:
A more simplified diagram also appears, happily
with some comments.
£ is really R. It seems that
the subject S will depend on what is being
unfolded in the Other, A. What is being unfolded
is 'articulated like a discourse' and appears as
the discourse of the Other, the unconscious which
Freud tried to grasp in a series of fragments or
privileged moments like dreams or lapsi. The
subject has to take part to be involved. He is
drawn to the four corners of the scheme
experienced as 'S, his ineffable and stupid
existence; a, his objects; a' – his moi —
that is what is reflected of his form in his
objects; and A, the locus from which the question
of his existence may be put to him'. The S
or Es is also the id, the It as in 'It speaks'.
Note that the imaginary relation blocks any direct
communication between A and S. An addition to the
scheme in a later article says that 'a and a' are
explicitly the mois of S and A, and the
axes S – A and a – a' are explicitly the Symbolic
axis and the Imaginary axis respectively'(108).
Returning to the main text, the unconscious
relates to a part of a discourse that is not
trans-individual nor at the disposition of the
subject in constructing his own history. It is not
just a matter of unconscious tendencies, because
experience shows that the unconscious also
participates in the formation of ideas and of
thought, as in the discussion of what constituted
unconscious thought in Freud [apparently in the
Wolf Man]. There is a therapeutic implication in
the slogan that there is forgiveness in the word
[in Latin in the original]. Communication between
the unconscious and the unconscious is often
hidden, which makes the subject appear to be
offering a personal history and truth. This
relation is not grasped by any attempt to formally
distinguish conscious and unconscious, but rather
by experimental observation. The unconscious is
commonly censored or appearing as a false
recollection, but the truth can be found somewhere
else. First in 'monuments', like the body in
hysteria; in 'archival documents' like childhood
memories which have to be grasped like any
historical document; in 'semantic evolution', the
ways in which people develop the particular
vocabulary as they live their life; in
'traditions' including legends used to account for
history; in those traces produced by distortions
linking censored sections to other episodes, to be
recognized by 'my exegesis'. (21) these are all
metaphors used in Freud himself, where the
metaphor 'is but the synonym for the symbolic
displacement brought into play in the symptom'
[leading to a whole understanding of Freudian
mechanisms like condensation and displacement as
metaphor and metonym respectively. Freud himself
is quoted in note 53, page 109, referring
to '"words and names"', passwords, or words
that switch affect between different
representations in the unconscious, and sometimes
between those and the body].
[A certain Mr Fenichel is rebuked for discussing
the patient's history in objective rather than
subjective terms, related to the 'laws of history'
in general. Lacan thinks these efforts, including
those of Comte and Marx are hopeless predictors,
at least without constant amendment.] They are
good as ideals, however. Psychoanalysis and other
'sciences of the particular' might need to locate
these facts in 'a primary historization' (23). It
is also the case that historical events need to be
interpreted and have different effects on the
memory, and some remain in the memory longer and
continue to play an important role in the present
— e.g. past revolutions for Marxists. The patient is
taught to reconstruct his history in the
present, but by acknowledging that past events
can be seen as 'facts of history' (23) for him,
either recognized or censored. Any fixation can
be seen as 'a historical scar: a page of shame…
or a page of glory'. The discussion can
be brought to bear in debates about the role of
instincts or drives. 'The instinctual stages, are
already organized in subjectivity' (24), as when
children regard as defeats and victories matters
such as potty training. Psychoanalysts use the
same kind of subjectivity to reconstruct things
like the pre-genital form of love [an important
point against Ettinger?] The alleged biological
stages are founded in intersubjectivity, not in
terms of a maturing of the instincts. It is a
mistake to link human development to that of
animals like this. Sarcastically: 'why not
consequently look for the image of the moi
in the shrimp, under the pretext that both acquire
a new carapace after shedding the old?' (24).
[Another theorist is also sarcastically criticized
for claiming to have found a biological plan to
explain human culture — the development of armour
links to the development of crustacea]. There is a
problem with these analogies. They're not as
precise as metaphors, and Freud avoided them.
Analytic symbolism is opposed to analogical
thinking. [More problems with instinct theory are
explored page 25, complete with Freud's own
objections, again in the Wolf Man, page 26]. The
cure, a form of grace, is the 'fruit of an
intersubjective accord imposing its harmony on the
torn and riven nature which supports it' (26).
The subject is a lot more than what is experienced
subjectively. The truth of our history is not
entirely contained in our script: we have to
investigate the signs of disorder and discomfort
in that history. In particular, 'the unconscious
is the discourse of the other' (27) [note 59, 110
notes that this increasingly becomes the big O
Other]. We see this in the occasional convergence
between the patients remarks and those of the
analyst, or sometimes another patient. This is not
telepathy but 'resonance in the communicating
networks of discourse'. Human discourse is
omnipresent, and is the only field where
experience provides an apparent two-way relation,
although that is inadequate for psychoanalytic
theory [as the diagrams indicate].
Section 2 Symbol and Language
We have to avoid any analysis that relies on
homonyms between analytic terms and everyday ones.
Conventional psychology tends not to grasp the
highs and lows of common experience.
Psychoanalysis also typically ignores these
aesthetic sensitivities or impulses, 'the vivacity
of his tastes' (29). We should investigate the
positive aspects of experience, but not as is
commonly done in conventional psychiatry [which
seems based on some idea that pleasures and
desires lie beyond language in object relations].
We want to develop a more scientific approach by
returning to the work of Freud.
In the work on dreams, the dream 'has the
structure of a sentence', in particular, that of
'a rebus'[The Oxford Dictionaries Online
give 'A puzzle in which words are represented by
combinations of pictures and individual letters;
for instance, apex might be represented by a
picture of an ape followed by a letter X']. Thanks
to the 'laws of the signifier' [as note 65, page
111, puts it], the elements can provide both a
phonetic and symbolic use as with Egyptian
hieroglyphs or Chinese characters.
Further interpretation and deciphering is
required, however, a 'translation of the text',
the 'rhetoric' of the dream. Here we will find
forms of 'syntactical displacement' – ellipsis and
pleonasm, hyperbaton or syllepsis, regression,
repetition, apposition' [haven't bothered to look
them all up] , and 'semantic condensations' —
'metaphor, catachresis, antonomasis, allegory,
metonymy and synecdoche' (31) [these are explained
in formal linguistic terms in note 67, page 113.
Metonymy connects words to words in a signifying
chain, signifiers to signifiers, and this
'represents the subject's desire'. Metaphor
substitutes one word for another and here the
first signifier becomes a signified, still
connected by metonymy. Lacan apparently represents
this in another diagram. He connects it to Freud's
work on the dream specifically. For example
transposition or distortion is understood as 'the
sliding of the signified under the signifier,
always in [unconscious] action' [possibly as
intentions and motivations develop or reactions
occur?]. Condensation involves the superimposition
of signifiers and is central to a general poetic
function. Displacement is the transfer of
significations and is used 'by the unconscious to
foil the censorship'. The mechanisms in language
and in dream work are identical, except for their
dramatic staging {mise en scene} . Lacan was to
argue later that this connection between
signifiers permitting elision, is what invests an
object with desire which it originally lacks. It
does this through a process of referring back].
Freud argued that the dream expresses desire, even
where the patient dreams specifically in a way to
contradict his theory. This episode shows us
precisely how the wishes of the other are
generated by the first speaker, and Freud also
noticed the role of the desire to contradict. Freud was to
realise that the sign of transference was the
appearance of provocation, avowal or diversion
from the analytic discourse. We can
generalize from this to insist that 'man's desire
finds its meaning in the desire of the other… the
first object of desire is to be recognized by the
other [note 68, page 114, tells us that Lacan gets
this idea from Hegel, that desire has always to be
mediated, increasingly in a dialectic. Lacan
elaborated his ideas later to argue that desire is
an effect of a discourse, that it operates via
signifiers. Since the Other is where the Word is
deployed, '"man's desire is desire of the Other"'.
The whole thing depends on the
opening/vulnerability {béance} of signifiers which
permit the structure of the subject's desire and
the representation of the Other. Human subjects
are commonly unaware of the role of the Other in
structuring their desires, however].
This is best demonstrated in transference. The
patient's dream becomes a matter of
'provocation... avowal... or diversion' according
to the analytic discourse and, as transference
proceeds, dreams become more and more related to
this dialogue. Similarly, a parapraxis is 'a
successful discourse', a particular phrase,
affected by a stifling of speech. Again we see the
power of the Word which will convey a meaning
other than the literal.
Freud also examines beliefs about chance, found in
subjective number associations, for example.
Numbers arrived at through particular
manipulations should be seen as symptoms, 'already
latent in the choice from which they began'.
Superstitious people think that these figures
determine their destiny, but this is an effect of
the particular language expressed in these
combinations of numbers, appearing as unconscious
to the subject. There are other unconscious
structures revealed by philology and ethnography
[the latter meaning Lévi-Strauss?]
A symptom is always overdetermined by a double
meaning, one relating to the past conflict and one
to a present one. Free association is a technique
to locate the point at which verbal forms
intersect with this underlying structure. The
whole thing can be understood as an analysis of
language. [Again, note 70, page 115 tells us, it
is understanding the ambiguity of language as an
orchestral score. The connection between the
symptom and the underlying structure is like the
link between a rebus and a sentence. This
ambiguity is not the same as overdetermination of
symptoms, except that both refer to relations of
signifier and signified. The symptom is always a
signifier, unlike medical symptoms: it is not just
an indicator, but an effect of language, here
understood as actual spoken daily language.
Signifiers and signifieds are related 'as system
to system', not just as simple terms, so symptoms
display a whole structure of significations, not
just an isolated one].
Freud demonstrates the effect of the unconscious
in his work on jokes where a particular phrase or
word is the turning point of the joke, making the
meaning 'sufficient to the wise' (32). The whole
effect depends on the ambiguity engendered by
language, and where nonsense is allowed to
challenge the usual view that consciousness
dominates the real. Human speakers lose mastery.
It is not that the joke somehow engenders its own
logic, or that sophistry controls humour. Instead
we discover a certain conditionality of
subjectivity. If there were nothing foreign to my
consciousness, they would be no pleasure in
discovering it. There is always an implicit third
listener, sometimes indicated by making the joke
turn on indirect speech. The truth by contrast
looks like a platitude. Turning away from the
language of symbols is actually a change in the
object of psychoanalysis – activities like jokes
constantly remind us of the creative power of
language.
The law is also a law of language. Ancient Greek
travellers initiated 'symbolic commerce' which
eventually turned into an exchange of signs. The
gift already implies a pact, and we rapidly
developed purely symbolic exchanges like goods
that were not actually very useful. This activity
might be seen in giftgiving among animals like sea
swallows, and if their gifts really are the
equivalent of a human celebration, they are indeed
using symbols. So the origins of symbolic
behaviour might indeed lie 'outside the human
sphere' (35).
But we must not over elaborate the sign. In one
example, a behavioural psychologist has managed to
reproduce what looks like neurosis in a dog by
varying the rewards that arrive with the bell.
This is supposed to show the links between signals
and symbols. It is certainly true that you can
condition animals and humans with signals.
However, humans can react ambiguously to signals
[the exact example implies the use of a command
word like 'contract', directed at eye pupils; the
same word in other contexts would not produce
pupil contraction]. This involves distinguishing
the signifier and the signified, and this in turn
implies that words makes sense only by being part
of a given set, pre-existing any individual
experience. Freud centrally maintained the
importance of relations to the Symbolic order
and the sense that results. With trained
animals, there is always the danger of 'an
irrelevant humanism' (38) which misunderstands
the intersection of conditioning with the
deployment of words.
Animals cannot reproduce the social
world, completing a symbol. Symbols need to be
liberated from specific uses in the here and now,
and this is possible only if it behaves like a
concept. Freud saw this in the Fort Da game, where
an absence can give itself a name, and when it is
only the relation between the terms that
constructs particular 'universe of sense in which
the universe of things will come into line' (39).
In this way, 'the concept… Engenders the thing'.
The world of words creates the world of things
which appear in the here and now as confused,
still connected with the becoming of the whole,
localised.
The exchange of gifts including the exchange of
women and the reciprocity implied shows how the
symbol 'has made… Man'. Things like kinship names
help construct a preferential order. This remains
unconscious, but there is a whole underlying
'logic of combinations' (40) [Lévi-Strauss]. As
usual, we only think we are free in these matters
because their permanence lies in our unconscious.
The same might be said of the Oedipus complex,
which involves unconscious participation in the
movement of marriage ties, but we become aware of
it only through symbolic effects in our individual
existence, in this case in the form of a
'tangential movement towards incest'. The
'primordial Law' [of incest prohibition] is
necessary because our nature offers unrestricted
copulation requiring cultural regulation. The
conscious warnings about incest are only a
'subjective pivot' and can help to explain 'the
modern tendency' to focus restrictions on mothers
and sisters. Overall, the law prohibiting incest
'is revealed clearly enough as identical to an
order of Language', for example in requiring
kinship nominations. Breaking the law would
produce unendurable confusion of roles. Even
remarriage with a young woman of the same age as
one of the sons can produce problems 'as we know
was the case of Freud himself' (41). There is a
further 'dissociation' of Oedipus when people
believe that they are reincarnating ancestors.
The paternal function when represented by a single
person therefore 'concentrates in itself both
Imaginary and Real relations, always more or less
inadequate to the Symbolic relation which
constitutes it essentially'. Hence the 'name of
the father' is an eternal support of the Symbolic,
identifying the person of the father with the
figure of the law. When we analyze cases, we have
to remember this function and distinguish it from
the Real relations: harmful confusion results if
we do not do so.
[Referring to Rabelais], we see the same
[paternal] relations in the notion of an
omnipresent spirit, a divine mystery. This brings
with it an 'inviolable Debt' (42) which guarantees
the continued circulation of women and goods
[possibly some sort of common value? Note 97 cites
a certain Panurge as seeing debt as the mainstay
of the human race, '"the great Soul of the
universe"', presumably because it is crucial in
exchange and social obligation? 127]
Lévi-Strauss was to refer to this underlying
notion as the symbol zero, making the power of
speech a matter of an algebraic sign. [Note 98,
page 127, explains that for Lévi-Strauss the
spirit was an overabundant signifier, with a kind
of surplus signifying value permitting symbolic
thought. This surplus value, the floating
signifier, is represented by mana or spirit, which
may take any number of specific forms. Mauss was
to argue that its real function was in symbolic
exchange, that mana was being exchanged regardless
of economic advantage. Lévi-Strauss wanted to see
it as a symbolic zero partly as a nod towards
Jakobson and the notion of the zero phoneme which
exists as a standing opposition, to replace the
simple absence of phonemes. For Lévi-Strauss, mana
is 'pure form without specific content, pure
symbol, a symbol with the value of zero']
The interlocking network of symbols exist before
any individual. It seems to provide people with
meaning, with a destiny. However, universal
meaning is subject to local variations arising
from both 'interferences and pulsations' within
language, a 'confusion of tongues' and sometimes a
contradiction of perceived orders. These preserve
the role of desire, but desire must therefore be
recognized in symbols or at least in the
Imaginary. In the case of individual patients,
this takes the form of a pathological
intersubjective experience. It follows that
everything turns on 'the relationships of the Word
and Language in the subject' (42).
As a first paradox, among the mad, we can see both
the freedom given to words which no longer need to
be recognized, and a delusion which objectifies
the subject in a 'language without dialectic' (43)
[note 102, page 129, says that Lacan initially saw
this in terms of a general structure of
meconnaissance/misrecognition. He insisted from
the beginning that a form of misrecognition
is common in everyday life as well, as when people
take themselves seriously. A language without
dialectic is found in schizophrenic language:
words are treated like things, so the binary
differences between them are not anchored in the
symbolic end – 'all the Symbolic is Real' (130),
so there is no dialectic or dialogue, since words
have no shared meaning. This 'deficiency of
signifiers' means there can be no real contact
with the (Symbolic) Other, but only with the
(Imaginary) other. Since human reality is
symbolic, schizophrenics and psychotics find it
hard to locate themselves in the 'human Real'.]
The language of the psychotic is stereotyped,
symbols are petrified, appearing rather as do
myths for us. They are not recognized in the usual
way. It might be possible to see such people
occupying particular places in society?
In the second paradox, psychoanalysis has
discovered particular elements such as symptoms,
inhibition and anxiety. Again the Word is not
available for concrete discourse by the patient.
Instead discourse is the result of organic
stimulus, or perhaps marginal images from the
social world: at best it relates the inner world
of the person to the outer subjective world. Some
signified was once related to a signifier but this
has been repressed from consciousness, and can
only appear through 'semantic ambiguity'[note 107,
page 131, explains some of the cultural allusions
to Roman religion and goes on to say that the
apparent 'lack of being' in psychotics is, in
Sartre, the basis of desire for the self — it
seems to be that personal liberty is possible only
once we have escaped necessity, that this personal
liberty belongs to our desire for selfhood, but
that what is lacking is this 'desire of being',
possibly meaning a way of reconciling possible
liberty with social reality?]. The banishment of
the Word also banishes 'the discourse of the
other' which is included in it from the beginning.
Understanding these original meanings led to Freud
grasping the importance of basic symbols which
still have a role in current civilization. All the
symptoms of neurosis and psychosis can be seen as
'hermetic elements' (44), equivocations,
artifices, containing sense in prison, in a
palimpsest. Restoring the Word and its suppressed
elements offers both a mystery and a 'pardon'.
In the third paradox, subjects can lose themselves
in objectified discourses as a kind of 'profound
alienation of the subject', very common in
scientific civilization. [Typically obscurely]
common speech once referred to 'that which I am'
and now refers to 'it is me'. This 'psychological
objectification' is characteristic of modern man
[and may be paradoxical in that modernization
involves disorder of the old harmonies? Or
possibly that the desire for fellow feeling, the
beautiful soul, is contradicted by an interest in
individualism?]. A delusional discourse offers a
way out. We now have a form of communication based
on objectification which allows people to forget
the paradoxes of subjectivity and enables them to
still contribute to the common good and find
pleasure and forgetting in the profusion of
cultural materials. It is only when regression
reminds subjects of their limits, perhaps back at
the mirror stage, that this capacity is
questioned. Psychoanalytic discourse itself breaks
the illusion by referring to a trinity of ego,
superego and id.
Patients commonly display a barrier in their
language resisting the Word and preferring instead
the sort of 'verbalism' (45) found in normal life.
We see this also in the tremendous output of
modern culture and we might study questions of
language in that output. Psychoanalysis, by
insisting on the truth of the Word, threatens
further alienation [Lacan defends himself, says
note 116, page136 by implying through Pascal that
it is sometimes necessary to be mad if
civilization is itself, that there is a connection
between madness and sense, and that madness
results only when the normal forms of
understanding one's personality as dependent on
others breaks down. Thus madness has both a human
and the philosophical value, telling us about
"signification for being in general". Madness
arises from a permanent paradox of managing self
and other, and is a companion to liberty, perhaps
a limit of liberty].
However, subjectivity does play an important role
both in renewing symbols and it 'continues to
animate the whole movement of humanity' (46). At
the same time, it only works as something
symbolic. Even revolution gets 'reduced to the
words which signify it', while established
religion finds its power increasingly in Language.
Psychoanalysis has also done much to develop
notions of subjectivity, although it must not be
grounded as a discipline among the sciences,
formalised, in some misleading attempt to catch
up, to develop misleading experimental methods.
Instead, the Symbolic function needs further
investigation [possibly hinting that the progress
made by structural anthropology might be a model].
The need is to reverse positivism with its
emphasis on the experiment, to go back to an
earlier model. The developments in linguistics and
its links with anthropology can guide us. The
discovery of the the phoneme is the basic unit
formed by oppositions of semantic elements can
even take on a mathematicized form. All languages
can then be seen as combinations of small numbers
of phonemic opposition. Psychoanalysts need to
explore the implications just as ethnography has
in the study of myths and mythemes in Lévi-Strauss
[with an interesting note 120 on page 137, which
tells us that Lacan explicitly grasped the Oedipus
complex as a myth]. Lévi-Strauss is cited as one
of the 1st to combine the structures of language
with social laws on marriage and kinship.
Investigating the symbol will provide a new
science of man and subjectivity. The Symbolic has
a double movement [rather like Berger and Luckmann
here, as well as Hegel]. Human beings objectify
their actions but that objectification becomes a
grounding — 'action and knowledge alternate' (48).
As one example, education shows us how to
objectify in cardinal numbers things that have
been counted, but once we have these numbers we
can see that they can be added; in another example
human beings see themselves as producing social
relations, but can also threaten those social
relations in the name of some deeper belonging
[the example is the proletariat going on a general
strike]. Both instances involve regularities —
mathematical laws and 'the brazen face of
capitalist exploitation'. Both show us how our
social life takes on a reality, as inversions and
reversals dominate the concrete, and how
subjective investigations can grasp reality. The
old distinction between exact and conjectural
sciences is undermined.
The apparent exactitude of experimental science
really comes from mathematics, while its relation
to actual nature remains problematic. [With an
irritating citation of a poem producing
speculation that the unusual link between humans
and nature might actually tell us about the
movements of nature itself], whereas physics 'is
simply a mental fabrication whose instrument is a
mathematical symbol' (49): it measures the real
but does not really define quantity in real
substances. We see this in the measurement of time
which still depends on particular assumptions [an
historical example argues that an efficient clock
was developed before theoretical work that would
supply a concept]. There is another kind of time
which is intersubjective and which structures
human action [not Bergson and durée though] but a
stochastic notion best understood through game
theory strategy. Human time is rooted in action
oriented to the actions of others with all the
hesitations, certitudes and final decisions, and
the eventual notion of past and future which are
implied. The other is crucial here in confirming
the understanding or final decision of the subject
as a matter of truth or error. Boolean algebra or
set theory might do a better job of grasping the
structures.
Historians suggest another route, where they
identify their own subjectivity with that which
constitutes historical events. Psychoanalysis is
similar, with added notions of 'curative efficacy'
(50). We also realize the effects of historicity
which enables us to subjectively reproduce the
past in the present. Freud understood this better
than Jung's notion of neurotic regression.
From linguistics we can also grasp the difference
between synchronic and diachronic structure and
see how this works when discussing resistance or
transference. Freud anticipated these borrowings.
We might fit them within the 'epistemological
triangle' [the zigzag link between s and a?]. We
might add other topics rooted in language —
rhetoric, dialectic, grammar and even poetics,
which might help grasp witticisms.
Psychoanalysis belongs with the liberal arts,
focused on privileged problems rather than
formalization, helping to grasp humanity against
the 'arid years of scientism' (51). The task still
remains to grasp human experience, intersubjective
logic, human temporality and the symbol.
Section 3 Interpretation
and Temporality
The importance of symbolic interpretation seemed
intimidating and then embarrassing to early
psychoanalysis, which persisted in the early
scandalous reception of Freud. Subsequent
disagreements are unsurprising. Current
practitioners seem to want to develop completely
objectified approaches and they can attract
enthusiastic support. However, they seem to be
based on growing misrecognition of the subject.
If we return to Freud's cases like the Rat Man, we
can see that many of the subsequent criticisms of
omission were anticipated. Freud understood full
well that he was encouraging his patients to go
beyond their experience and explore their
Imaginary. The patient's distress at recounting
the torture episode revealed to Freud the
patient's horror at his suppressed pleasure and
saw that the psychoanalyst could be identified
with the original sadistic storyteller. Freud then
appears to continue with the game rather than
overcome the resistance, but Lacan interprets this
as joining with the patient to explore the
symbolism of the word, implicating the subject
himself. Freud also skilfully manages the
subsequent conversation where the subject got
evasive. The example shows that analysis 'consists
in playing in all the multiple keys the orchestral
score which the Word constitutes in the registers
of Language and on which depends the over
determination [of the symptom]' (55). [Note 128,
p. 139 explains that the score was a good example
of something that could be read horizontally and
vertically]. At the same time, the cure requires
that the analyst's response is 'particular to
him'. We have to rediscover these principles
rather than literally apply Freud's terms.
The principles 'are none other than the dialectic
of the consciousness–of–self', developed from
Socrates to Hegel, based on the assumption that
all that is rational is real and ending eventually
with the scientific judgement that all that is
real is rational [note 129, page 139 talks about
needing to conjugate the particular to the
universal, subordinating the Real to the rational,
in the process of which the subject will be seen
as having a role in constituting the object, as in
Hegel's phenomenology. The note adds that the
slogan above about the real and the rational
should be understood as the rational being actual,
'or effectively real' and vice versa, and again
there are links with Hegel]. The process whereby
the subject establishes this truth involves a
'decentring' from self-consciousness, with
implications for the view that the conscious
faculty alone establishes reality.
Hegelian phenomenology has structured
psychoanalytic technique, specifically the master
slave dialectic, the dialectic of the beautiful
soul, and the general relations between objects
and subjects, the 'fundamental identity of the
particular and the universal'. Psychoanalysis best
shows the ways in which subjective identity
becomes a matter of [technical] realization, with
a further implication that there is a deep
connection between one and the other, masked by
the intrusion of individualist notions of the
subject [in ordinary people as well as in
psychoanalysts]. However, this has been forgotten
by recent developments. The very notion of
analytic neutrality implies an Hegelian stance
that the truth is to be discovered already there,
despite how much it is confused and covered. We
can also learn from Socrates and Plato [pages 56 –
57 — pretty technical but contains a sentence: 'we
analysts have to deal with slaves who think they
are masters, and who find in a Language whose
mission is universal, the support of their
servitude along with the bonds of its ambiguity'].
The point of analysis is to 'liberate the
subject's Word' by showing that he is using the
Language of desire [note 135, page 141 explains
that subjects never really talk about themselves
initially, but rather talk about the moi.
Resistance shows this, where patients attempt to
repress or censor the social origins of
connections between signified and signifier. What
the analyst does here is to introduce new
discordances to establish the original censorship.
In this way, the 'subject of the unconscious' the
'true subject' can begin to address himself to
himself as he comes closer to the truth contained
in the Word]
Language is universal but it also realizes itself
in particular desires of the subject. We can talk
of a primary language, discovered by Freud and
extended by Jones discussing symbolism [he seems
to have argued that the thousands of symbols can
all be traced back to the body, kinship, birth,
life and death]. When symbols are repressed
[unconsciously], they do not indicate their
regressive or even infantile nature. They still
make themselves heard, however. We see this in
reactions to symbolic acts in normal as well as
neurotic people [and then a diversion into Hindu
traditions via a particular story, 58 – 59].
Primary symbols resemble primary numbers.
We need to investigate symbolic displacements as
in things like metaphors [note 139, page 143
explains that metaphors work by substituting one
signifier for the other, making it take its place
in a chain of signifiers, sometimes as a metonym
referring to other parts of the chain. Later work
talks of 'a latent signifier' as one term replaces
another, in effect making the first one a
signified]. This requires a full knowledge of the
resources of language. Freud himself was well
acquainted with German literature as well as
Shakespeare. Interest in the classics and in
current anthropology would also be useful, but
recent psychoanalysts have not followed the same
road [some English psychoanalysts seem to be
rebuked here, practising ego psychology in a very
limited and literal way]. [Explains his own
literary style?]
With symbols, words transform the subject by
acting as a signifier. That's why we need to
understand language and not see signs as simply
the names for objects as in simple notions of a
signal in a code. [However, note 144, page 144
notes that as Lacan pursues the notion of the
signifier 'the less one hears about the
signified']. This partly explained the recent
interest in gestures or body language as
supplements to the word. Can we find evidence for
this in the behaviour of the honeybee and its
dance? This is an example of coding and
signalling, but not necessarily of a Language
because there is 'the fixed correlation of its
signs to the reality which they signify' whereas
in a Language signs relate to each other and can
show 'lexical sharing out of semantemes' (61). Nor
is the message ever retransmitted, but remains
fixed, permitting no detachment of the subject.
Language by contrast 'defines subjectivity' by
necessarily referring to social action or the
discourse of the other. It invests a person with
new realities by naming them. It is dialectic in
this sense, requiring a response from the other
even if inverted: in this sense, 'the Word always
subjectively includes its own reply' (62). When
Language is reduced to the functional, to
information, or to the particular, it loses these
characteristics. The value of Language lies in the
'intersubjectivity of the "we" which it takes on'.
We see this in the residual redundancies of
language even that which is intended just to be a
matter of communication — what is redundant
indicates [something surplus] the necessary
'resonance in the Word. For the function of
Language is not to inform but to revoke' (63).
The Word evokes the response of the other. My
question constitutes me as a subject, but the
question is already based on a desire to be
recognized by the other and will include something
like a name for the other. Thus as we identify
ourselves in Language, so do we lose ourselves by
becoming an object. Our understanding of the past
is not an accurate recollection of what was but
the form of 'future anterior of what I shall have
been for what I am in the process of becoming'.
Responses can never be predicted as simple
reactions. To see a response as a reaction to a
stimulus is a metaphor. A similar one attributes
subjectivity to animals. The metaphor is glossed
over by using technical terms. Human beings do not
learn by experimenting with stimuli in order to
get the right result — desire guides the response
[the fulfilment of desire is the real response].
Similarly, responding to others really involves
'to recognize him or to abolish him as subject'
(64).
Language has a materiality as a body. Words appear
in corporeal images as we see with neurotic
patients who associate words with bodily fluids.
They can accomplish 'Imaginary acts of which the
patient is the subject' (65) [the reference is to
the Wolf Man case. The examples seem to involve
the ways in which the names of things like wasps
transform into people's initials]. Whole
discourses can become eroticised. They clearly
involve suppressed pleasures in the speaker. Words
become Imaginary or even Real objects for the
subject, often condensing the broader functions of
Language. Analysis by contrast seeks the 'true
Word' and explains its relation to the history of
the patient. This is dialectic, never
objectifying. Freud even used suggestions
strategically, whether they were materially
accurate or not [again linked to the Rat Man. The
goal was to help the subject rediscover in his own
family history and other memories, the endless
nature of the symbolic debt which he felt unable
to repay and which developed the neurosis [note
152, page 156 equates the Symbolic father with the
actual dead father of the patient, another example
of a contradiction with simple reality]. We also
see the useful role of an Imaginary person in the
process of transference [apparently a daughter
which the Rat Man fantasizes about marrying,
knowing it was not reality].
The first step is to recognize where the ego of
the patient is, already defined by Freud as
'formed of a verbal nucleus' (67), the source and
the object of the question posed by the subject.
Only then can we focus on the desire of the
subject and the object to which it is addressed.
In hysteria, there is 'an elaborate intrigue'
where the ego is found in the intermediary object
enjoyed by the subject. Hysterics genuinely act
out, outside themselves Obsession involves
dragging objects into narcissism, a form of
staging a spectacle. Both of these are examples of
the crucial importance of the relation between the
I and the me, remembering that these are not the
same as individual subjects. Ambiguities have
arisen in Freudian terminology here [pages 68 –
69]. Discussion includes an understanding of
psychoanalysis as a matter of two bodies in
relation. The analyst teaches the subject to see
himself as an object, with an illusory link to
subjectivity; the Word is used as part of a search
for lived experience; the subjectivity of the
analyst is different from normal, however,
unrestrained, and this leaves the subject open to
every analytical use of the Word [very difficult
material here].
This is what Freud meant when he said that
everything in the id must be grasped by the ego;
it must be a suitably compliant ego to assist the
analysis. In other words the ego must continually
split, although the egos of patient and analyst
never fully coincide [since analysis itself is
never ended?]. However, analysts also assume that
all the formulations of the patient are defensive.
Freud's discussion of Dora shows that the
analysts' prejudices can themselves intervene in
countertransference and that this can prevent the
moves on the part of the patient to grasp the
processes [Freud continually insisted that Dora
really desired Herr K]. The case also shows
considerable 'intersubjective complicity' when
Dora, after a break, engages a second stage
pretence to conform to Freud's understanding, by
claiming she was pretending to be rejecting his
analysis.
A guilty conscience is apparent in some of the
recent developments in psychoanalysis, especially
if the disappearance of symptoms looks like magic
rather than science. They want to reassert the
traditional distance between themselves and the
patients, assuming that they have a scientific
grasp. This is quite opposite to Freud's own
approach where careful listening and no
condescension led to his discoveries, including
the wider significance of the Schreber case.
Analysts instead should rely on the qualities of
the Word and how it permits understanding,
agreeing that some things might not be immediately
apparent [but that does not mean they are somehow
prior to language]. And if we see these as not
depending on language, we are left not knowing how
to translate them, and a form of suggestion is
often what results. The relation between analyst
and patient becomes rather 'phantasmatic'. The
illusion that sees a reality behind language is
actually shared by subjects who believe that the
truth lies outside them and that the analyst can
discover it. However, Freud himself never saw
transference as simply explicable by the neurosis:
it had an element of reality. In practice,
transference is 'the normal error of existence'
(73) found in the very common 'love, hate, and
ignorance', real sentiments.
Further clarification of Lacan's own terms are
required to avoid misinterpretation. Reality in
analysis can often appear in a negative form and
as something encountered when we attempt to
actively intervene — although a refusal to reply
can also be an element of reality. This sort of
'pure negativity', not tied to particular motives
(74) shows the junction between the Symbolic and
the Real: in effect the analyst is insisting that
all that is real is rational and it is up to the
subject to disclose this. The question may not
involve the true Word. When it does, there is a
reply already contained in it, so analysis only
demonstrates the 'dialectical punctuation'
involved.
The Symbolic and the Real are also involved in
time as we saw. The duration of the analysis is
indefinite. We cannot predict the moment of
comprehension. There is also an implicit
'spatializing projection' based on the assumption
that the truth is already present, although this
must not confirm the original understandings of
the subject [maybe]. Real patients like the Wolf
Man may never fully grasp the place of a primal
scene in their history. Symptoms like paranoia can
be understood as a form of self alienation. [More
detailed discussion of the Wolf Man and his
subsequent treatment, apparently discussed at
length in a seminar, pages 76 – 77].
There is also the issue of the length of the
session [very brief sessions particularly pissed
off Guattari]. There is a professional issue here
since the length of the session is working time,
but there are also subjective dimensions.
Insisting on a standard time is a way of glossing
what is really a problem for analysis. Can the
actual time required be quantified? Why should
objective time dominate when it is subjective time
that matters both in the construction of a
symbolic object and in the momentary relapse where
an analyst ignores it? There is nevertheless both
labour involved and symbolic exchange [note 168,
pages 148 – 9, adds a dimension of time associated
with debt and its repayment, through some
association with a bond as lasting word, some
constant commitment. This persists even though the
names of actual ancestors who need to be
reimbursed may be forgotten — the pledge is what
remains, and this 'maintains the integrity of
social life', 150].
There is also the way in which the analyst
controls the discourse towards truth. Ending a
session is always experienced as a kind of
punctuation in his progress for the patient,
another of the delays or evasions in his
discourse. Punctuation always fixes the sense, and
this can prevent the conclusion of a discourse or
the fixing of a misunderstanding. It is entirely
inappropriate to make the ending of a session a
matter of routine, although it seems to bolster
the neutrality of the analyst. Routine can even
assist the patient who is always ready to see the
labour of psychoanalysis as forced. There is the
danger of connivance with the patient, especially
with obsessives who tend to see everything as
forced labour. Via Hegel, we can extend the notion
of the relation between masters and slaves which
involves waiting for the master to die, another
link with the procrastination of the obsessive,
often seen in anxiety or fear about the death of
the analyst. This waiting for the other is a form
of double alienation since the slave also is only
waiting for the master's death instead of living
his own life, a form of death itself. The whole
case is an example of how patients can work
through their problems in order to seduce the
analyst. Disdain for such activity can actually be
positive. Lacan also claims that one effect of
short sessions is to bring to light certain
fantasies of males, emerging only after lengthy
verbalism was interrupted. In this sense, the
short session has 'a precise dialectical sense'
(80).
[There are links with Zen, another example of
creative disdain which breaks discourse in order
to deliver the Word. Freud himself has talked of
the benefits of a negative reaction to therapy].
There is a link to the discussion of the death
instinct in Freud. This work has been rejected by
those who want to operate with rational
conceptions of the ego [and by Guattari] and
by Reich's attempt to analyze organic expressions
beneath language. Instead, the death instinct is
linked to the problems of language. We see this in
the way in which it has to join together two
contrary terms, to both preserve and then destroy
life. However, we find in very early work in
biology the notion that system equilibrium
requires a compound of life and death. For Freud,
the death instinct was linked to repetition,
automatism, clearly showing that it was not just a
matter of biology.
We can get a clue from the central role of
contradictions in Hindu myth [! Page 82. Further
discussed in note 177, page 152 — it all turns on
poetic meanings which can be added to apparently
mundane phrases]. Freud also deploys poetics in
his analysis of the unconscious and its
dialectics, which will explain the importance of
the death instinct. He identified two underlying
and conflicting principles similar to work by
Empedocles, which can generate myths of the dyad.
This is what has produced a systematic negativity
in the judgements of modern patients. It is like
the compulsion to repeat, classically understood
as a matter of 'the experience of transference':
the death instinct 'essentially express[es] the
limit of the historical function of the subject',
an absolute and unconditional end rather than the
more frequent comings to term with life, or final
realizations of the historicity of the subject, a
final existential possibility for Heidegger. It
can be extended to a notion that the physical past
is also finally over, not forgotten or not living
on in its implications: this is what can only be
reversed by repetition. Repetition really
represents the mastery of subjectivity: it also
produces the 'birth of the symbol' (83).
We see this in the Fort Da game and its repetition
as an early attempt to master the child's
environment with activity, to overcome the
passivity of the usual presences and absences of
the mother. This is the moment where 'desire
becomes human', a second level of desire, and it
is no coincidence that it is also the moment where
the child 'is born into Language'.. The subject
'destroys the object' by making it express desire
only as a 'provocation' of absence and presence.
Desire becomes its own object. The basic binary
opposition between Fort and Da also become
symbolic. The two phonemes become integrated
diachronically and then synchronically and the
child begins to engage in concrete discourse by
saying the words. [Note 183, page 153, cites later
Lacan to make an even more explicit link between
the dyadic needs and the register of the signifier
— '"the synchronic register of opposition between
irreducible elements and the diachronic register
of substitution and combination"'. Note 184 cites
an early linguist on the crucial importance of
binary oppositions to order psychic moments, and
thus '"Duality has proceeded unity"']. We also see
from the game that the desire of the child 'has
already become the desire of another', already
subject to domination. The game can easily be
applied to partners either Imaginary or Real.
Given this shift to desire and objects as
provocations, 'the symbol manifests itself first
of all as the murder of the thing' (84) [note 186,
page 153 says this originally arises from Kojeve
on Hegel, and uses phrases such as '"the mind… Is
the great slayer of the real"', and argues that
the mind actually continually subtracts aspects of
reality from Being itself when it forms concepts
as a kind of residue to explain what remains].
Humanity develops its first symbols in relation to
death as soon as it grasps history. This helps
human life persist, through the 'perpetuated
tradition of subject to subject'. This is uniquely
human, since individual animals are simply
reproduced in invariable types [so another
departure is required for Deleuze and Guattari on
evolution eg in Plateau 3].
Any explanation of individuals deriving from a
phylum 'must [still] be integrated by a
subjectivity which man is still only approaching
from outside'. Comparing the individual
distinction between rats with the legendary and
memorable acts of human beings.
The notion of liberty should always be understood
as something going on within a triangle of
renunciation [as with master-slave stuff above].
The desire of the other is limited by death,
whereas serfdom can be seen as pleasurable
[jouissance, even] as a kind of 'consented–to
sacrifice of his life' which will end in triumph
with the death of the master. In this way, we must
understand the death instinct as 'that desperate
affirmation of life', a final escape from the will
of the other.
Thus we see death as something 'primordial to the
birth of symbols' (85). An awareness of mortality
provides 'a centre exterior to Language', a
structure of symbolic logic, perhaps best modelled
as a three-dimensional torus relating peripheral
exteriority and central exteriority. Subjects
realize their subjectivity both in 'the vital
ambiguity of immediate desire' and 'in the full
assumption of his being–for–death'.
We see here that dialectic [in psychoanalytic
encounter] is not just individual. A resolution
must satisfy all the dimensions of human
undertaking, no less than a relation between care
for the individual and relating to 'absolute
Knowledge'. It requires a full knowledge of
dialectic operating at the symbolic level, amidst
linguistic discord. [Then some wonderfully lofty
and self-important stuff about psychoanalysis
looking for 'the putrescent serpent of life' amid
the darkness of the world, page 86].
Freud was leaning towards a biological basis for
his discoveries, whereas this orients itself to
culture, but these must be considered together,
joined by an inner contiguity. Nevertheless,
psychoanalysis has restored the role of Language
as a law, and uses poetics to explain the symbolic
mediation of desire. It is only through the Word
that 'all reality has come to man and it is by his
continued act that he maintains it' (86).
[Typically, we end with a quote from early Indian
religion where gods provide humans with sacred
texts stressing 'submission, gift, grace'].
|
|