Notes
on: Deleuze, G and Guattari, F. ( 2004) A
Thousand Plateaus.London: Continuum.
Chapter 3 10,000BC 'The Geology of Morals
[geddit?] (Who Does the Earth Think It Is?)
Dave
Harris
Here
are some notes I made after rereading this
section. In between the two readings, I
had read an awful lot of other stuff,
including Guattari's The Machinic
Consciousness, which explains
rather better some of the themes here,
especially in the section on faciality and the
weird sci-fi stuff about signs-particles.
Maybe I am just getting more tolerant of
bullshit?
This section starts off with a literary device
of making 'Professor Challenger' lead off
about the importance of geological
metaphors. This is obviously meant to
parody conventional academics, but it is a
useful persona for Deleuze and Guattari to
adopt as well, since Challenger is going to be
challenged for the offhand way in which he
makes references to all sorts of fields in
which is not a specialist—geology,
anthropology [the Dogon again], and
Hjelmslev's linguistics. Obviously some
critics have made spiky remarks about this
assumed expertise, and had even demanded to
know what specialism Challenger actually lays
claim to. It's a good job it's him and
not them!
The use of the geological metaphor obviously
is going to turn on the notion of
strata. We can see a stratum is facing
two ways—towards the more rigidly formed
layers of rock above, and to the less formed
material waiting to be processed into rock
below [cf sign regimes facing towards the
social strata in one dimension, and towards
the plane of consistency in another, in the
next Plateau] . This helps develop the
concept of 'double articulation'. [We
also introduce the remark that because
everything is doubly articulated, 'God is a
Lobster, or a double pincer, a double bind'
45]. We have met this term already in a
semiotic sense, where it refers to the same
terms being articulated in different
discourses, as in the British sense of seeing
'youth' as articulated in discourse about
generation, but also one about social
class. Here, double articulation means
two stages in the formation of matter.
In the first stage, items are collected
together, and loosely articulated as it were,
and in the second stage, a more rigid
structure is imposed on this loose collection.
We cannot actually explain this in the
conventional terms of form and matter, but
have to turn to the linguistic terms developed
by Hjelmslev, who refers to content and
expression, and argues that both have
characteristic forms. Expression here also
takes on a meaning derived from Spinoza as in
'To express is always to sing the Glory of
god. Every stratum is a judgment of god;
not only do plants and animals, orchids and
wasps, sing or express themselves, but so do
rocks and even Rivers, every stratified thing
on earth' (49). Things or content are
articulated first before expression. Deleuze
and Guattari don't bother to replace god in
this sentence, of course, but rely on us
knowing that Spinoza actually meant substance
expressing itself in various stages, through
modes and so on [see Deleuze's commentary here], and this
enables us to work both ways, from deduction
from substance, and induction of substance, to
use the old terms.
Using Hjelmslev's terms means we can get
extremely abstract, and see double
articulation as working at all levels, both
molecular and molar. There are the usual
weasels so that the distinction between
content and expression are real, unlike the
tautological links between form and substance,
but they also arise only from articulation,
and first and second articulations themselves
are relative—it is always double articulation
of content and expression. There are
also intermediate states between them.
The distinction between them is only
conventional, for Hjelmslev, and we always
find content and expression together We find
them in biology, where a certain chains of
molecules act as messengers [compare with
'components of passage' in Machinic
Unconscious].
The plane of consistency determines what
varies and what does not, including the actual
molecules and their relations between
them. We understand this better in
biochemistry in terms of energy, bonds [and
thresholds]. We understand this through the
work of a 19th century writer Saint-Hilaire,
with his key notion of how molecules are
assembled and aggregated as a result of
various flows or fluids. This apparently
illustrates a single and consistent process of
composition between the different levels, 'a
single machine embedded in the stratum' (51),
with no separation between inorganic and vital
matter. Apparently, he debated this with
Cuvier, and Challenger illustrates the debate
'in puppet theatre style' [that is not
as a proper debate] [you cannot parody
this really. I will continue my
discussion through the medium of mime].
Apparently, the point is to explain the
differences in forms in terms of folding,
literally how molecules fold together to
produce separate vertebra, but the folding
itself depends on particular chemical milieu
[thank god I read DeLanda before
this]. As a result, we can talk about an
abstract animal, realized in various ways [the
opponents are allowed to debate this model in
various ways, including denying that folding
explains the diversity of types]. When
we apply the argument to Darwin and
evolutionism it gets even more complex and
'endlessly proliferating' (53). We have
to see types as expressed in populations,
packs or species, and development taking place
in terms of different speeds and coefficients
[god bless Delanda again], dynamic equilibria
between relatively independent species, where
particular realizations of multiplicities
appear. These are explanations for
consistency among diversity on the 'organic
stratum'.
So there is a plane of consistency that
produces the first level of articulation, and
the 'substratum'[differently organized, not
inferior in any sense] acts as 'an exterior
milieu', although this is not really exterior
[!]. Things develop just as crystals
form on the basis of seeds, the latter being
relatively exterior to the form, but then
becoming interior. Another example is
the 'prebiotic soup' which gets
catalyzed. A membrane separates
subsequent elements from the soup. [We
are working towards the idea of a machinic
nucleus]. 'a single abstract
machine… Enveloped by the stratum…
Constitutes its unity' (56).
On
actual strata, this tends to be mixed with
intermediate layers, and flows traverse the
assemblage. Intermediate layers
themselves act as milieu and can be termed
'epistrata'. They act to affect change
and introduce gradations, and construct
centres and peripheries in interaction.
This makes it difficult to radically separate
organic from non organic elements [the whole
point of this biological digression, just like
the discussion of ethology in Guattari].
There is another possibility when organisms
turn to foreign materials as 'annexed or
associated milieu' (57) which have their own
sources of energy, as in respiration.
This requires some sort of discernment to
select a suitable material, and this goes on
at molecular levels as well as molar ones—even
the tick can perceive the sweat of a passing
animal and then decide to drop on to it.
Another example of double articulation is
apparent here [initial perceptions are
collected, stage 1, and the result is a new
relationship between the tick and the host,
stage 2].
We can pursue the issue of not separating
organisms from their associated milieu, seeing
them together as 'a structuration'—the spider
web is as important in morphogenesis as the
spider. However, the milieu can be more
flexible—the form is more tightly coded
[nevertheless, 'milieus always act, through
selection, on entire organisms' (58)].
Milieus can act as epistrata, but also
'parastrata'[which looks like producing
parallel forms]. We find concrete
machines operating on epistrata and
parastrata. We can use these terms to
rework Darwinism. [Somehow], parastrata embody
or 'envelop' [more flexible?] codes for
forms, and can generate new ones, and hence
new forms. They also provide the
potential for decoding. Together this
produces '"genetic drift"' (59) and it is that
produces mutations. All depends on the
'surplus value of code'. This also
explains becomings-animal [in the context of
biology here]. These surpluses are found
in the multiplicity or rhizomes, which
generate epi- and parastrata [I am going
to call both 'substrata'] .
Formed substances however relate to
territorialities and the various movements of
de and reterritorialization on
epistrata. Deterritorialization goes in
'nomadic waves'(60) from centre to periphery
and back again, and generally, epistrata
become more and more deterritorialized, less
stable, better able to cross thresholds
including those between strata. Some sub
atomic particles are particularly good at
deterritorializing, but some chemical
substances themselves have been crucial,
especially sulfur and carbon.
Deterritorialization, for example towards the
outside, is always accompanied by
reterritorialization, towards the inside in
this case [and the examples are the
circulation of components in
embryology]. These processes are
important in explaining what was impossible
before in evolution—communication between
species. Coding and territoriality are
both dynamic factors.
Codes are more random in their effects,
territory determines subsequent selection,
although sometimes modifications can produce a
certain deterritorialization. Together,
these produce 'territorial signs (indexes)'
(61), applying to the demarcation of zones [
ecological niches?] and subspecies. This
subdivision is also associated with the 'line
of flight', which, in this case, will 'enable
the animal to regain its associated milieu
when danger appears'. Another kind of
line of flight arises, however, when the
associated milieu is threatened from the
outside, forcing animals to seek other
territories: that in turn requires an animal
to be 'leaning on its interior milieus like
fragile crutches'. This is how fish left
the sea, carrying their own interior water as
amniotic fluid.
All territorialities have these lines of
flight, as potential moments of
de(re)territorialization. Thus strata
and the substrata are constantly shifting on
the plane of composition, moving either
through decoding or territorial drift.
Strata are being constantly undermined from
within as well as without. There are
heterogeneous speeds, territorializations, and
blocks. There are also the possibilities
of 'absolute deterritorialization, an absolute
line of flight, absolute drift' (62), which
rework the whole plane of consistency.
These can be produced by 'mad physical
particles', or by deterritorialization forces
crossing a threshold [and some might fall into
black holes]. All planes of
consistencies have their relatively unformed
edges. Abstract machines can either be
captured by stratifications and remain on the
plane of consistency, or they can develop in
such a way as to extend or change the plane of
consistency.
It is not just a matter of accelerated speed,
as in rapid development, but more a matter of
composition, how many substrata and how well
articulated they are, the extent to which
singularities are generated [and excellent
bullshit, re-rendering what they have just
said, as if lines and segments were somehow
empirically observable and not fictions—this
will depend on whether there is a
'nondecomposable, nonsegmentary line drawing a
metastratum of the plane of consistency'
(63)]. Ultimately, absolute
deterritorialization is generated on the body
without organs, itself the 'absolutely
deterritorialized', and this persists after
stratification—so absolute
deterritorialization is primary, and it is the
strata that are secondary. The issue is
how stratification occurs in the first
place. Abstract machines both stratify
and maintain deterritorialization as a matter
of 'two different states of intensities'.
By this time, we are told, the specialists
have left the lecture in disgust -- too
inflexible no doubt. Challenger decides
to address computers or to deal with axioms
[no nasty controversial empirical analyses
requiring specialized knowledge]. Variations
between strata themselves also depend on their
internal components and how they are
articulated. Some strata have molecular
content, form and substance, but molar
expression, form and substance.
Resonance occurs between them ['the
communication occurring between the two
independent orders'(64)] to produce a
stratified system. Here, expression
amplifies structuration forces and carries
them to the macro level. This is the
sort of system already described with crystals
or geology, but even here, there are several
[?] possible intermediate states, and exterior
forces. We might consider molar forms as
being moulds, 'mobilising a maximum of
exterior forces', or modulations, with minimal
exterior forces. Even these operations
will have intermediate states though.
Exterior forces are always involved if only at
a minimum, so the link between content and
expression can only be a relative distinction.
We can use 'all the subtleties of medieval
Scholasticism and theology' (65) [oh good
--more Spinoza?] to explain the relations
between content and expression. They are
only separated in the most thing-like
phenomena, but not in theory. We can
also distinguish different kinds of formal
distinctions, in scale, in terms of the
effects of formal reason, between particular
forms of things [which are still the same
thing]. However, when looking at organic
examples, the relation between molecular and
molar becomes dominant, in biology and in
chemistry. We understood expression first as a
matter of aggregation until molecules pass
thresholds but there are other forms, where
expression becomes autonomous, and the
distinction between content and expression
therefore becomes real. This can arise
from a 'nucleic sequence' (66), and concerns
the relation between two classes of molecules,
like nucleic acids and proteins. This
relation exists at the molecular and molar
level, and is not just a matter of
aggregation, rather a move in the 'direction
of flat multiplicities'[ and I think the
argument is that some molecules just do
expression, independently of content].
We therefore have a linear form of expression,
a derivative form, irrespective of magnitude.
Apparently, this is important in the power of
the organism to reproduce and also to
de/reterritorialize. First, there is a
deterritorialization of the code into a linear
form, and lines can be more readily
copied. Further deterritorialization is
necessary for organic reproduction. If
we combine this with the distinction between
the molar and molecular discussed above, we
can explain the development of intermediate
substrata. Communication can take the
shape of a 'set of inductions from layer to
layer and state to state' with 'subjugation to
three dimensionality'. This is a form of
territoriality, and will obviously limit
reproducibility, as with crystalline
growth. Organic growth is not so easily
territorialized, and all of its layers can be
linked by communication. Here we are
talking about 'transductions', transformations
of the layers as 'the amplification of the
resonance between the molecular and
molar'(67), not dependent on a linear code.
Other strata can develop forms of content that
are '"alloplastic"', where something in the
external world has an effect. This is a
form of linguistics, involving comprehensible
symbols. Human properties are also
derived from these expressions, and did not
initiate them [the examples turn on a French
analysis of how the ability to couple hands
and tools, or faces and language produced new
human contents. Here, the hand operates
as a digital code, and is able to produce its
own characteristic 'manual form'. The
tool extends this capacity, and can generate
products which can further extend the
operation of tools]. Tools and products
'are organized into parastrata and epistrata'
(68), and this helps humans pass a threshold
of deterritorialization, since their hands are
freed from the more territorial functions of
paws. Other organs can be
deterritorialized as well, and so can the
milieu, as when the steppe is more
deterritorialized than the forest. Other
reterritorializations then ensued [the foot
becomes the major organ of locomotion].
These interlocking processes could be mapped
on a plane of consistency.
Language also appears initially as a set of
formal traits, essentially vocal substances,
but also nonverbal ones including the
face. Mouths are deterritorialized
snouts, lips are deterritorialized mouths,
breasts the same for mammary glands. The
steppe supplied exterior pressures for
selection, for example requiring less loud
utterances than does the forest [then a
classic bit: 'To articulate, to speak, is to
speak softly. Everyone knows that
lumberjacks rarely talk' {they do sing
though}. There is a note to accompany
this major insight, but it is about monkeys
not lumberjacks]. Verbal signs are
linear and this helps them become more
deterritorialized and autonomous, unlike the
genetic code which is much more limited.
Language is superlinear [can be repeated and
include redundancies?], and this helps us to
overcode and also to translate, representing
all the other strata as in scientific
conceptions of the world, and linking the
strata. However, we should not allow
linguists to develop 'imperialist pretensions
on behalf of language'—it is a matter of the
organization of the substrata and their
tremendous powers of 'immanence' that mark
human language, but 'all human movements, even
the most violent, imply translations'(70).
So we now have different forms of content and
expression with humans, to include
technological content and semiotic
expression. The technological social
machine can be exploited once humans develop
hands and tools [it 'preexists' humans].
Human expression can now develop as an entire
'semiotic collective machine', 'regimes of
signs' again with nonhuman components.
Power relations and linguistic structures
determined and select usages and
communications, so humans extend the reach of
machines. However, we can still
understand this as another 'intermediate state
between the two states of the abstract
machine' [that is, not fully abstract, a
subset, not universal, not natural].
Human beings suffer from an illusion that
their language is the same as the machine, [as
in 'who does man think he is?'], because they
can overcode, but they still operate with
technological expression, formations of power,
symbolic expressions, 'characterized by face -
language relations', (71) and the operation of
a more abstract semiotic machine. Human
language is autonomous only because of the
particular characteristics of the substrata
that form it. The human world is also
likely to be populated by different strata,
different regimes of signs and different
formations of power [so that we can allow for
political autonomy?].
Thinking of implications for current human
dilemmas [and current debates about brains],
it is clear that the 'cerebral- nervous
milieu' is a common exterior milieu, stemming
from the organic substratum. But there
is no simple determinism. That
substratum 'constitutes the prehuman soup
immersing us', producing hands and faces as
two poles [apparently used by a French
commentator, Leroi-Gourhan, LG, as a major
development and distinction to explain
humanity—he has been used in the above
discussion as well]. There are therefore
two types of articulation, manual and facial,
but these are linked reciprocally.
However, this distinction has become very
important in culture, says LG, including
providing the basis for divisions between
categories like things and words. The
particular articulations help us connect
content and expression again in different
ways. Hands create 'pluridimensional
symbols', and these are the basis of writing,
while faces, or at least voices, produce
phonemes as 'linear significant
segments'(72).
['Challenger wanted to go faster and faster,
no one was left, but he went on anyway'!] He
wanted to further develop the notion of the
animal elements in human beings. The
first problem is what is a sign—there might be
'indexes (territorial signs, symbols
(deterritorialized signs), and icons (signs of
reterritorialization)'. We have to
acknowledge that signs exist on all the
strata, while resisting linguistic
imperialism: there is no universal system of
signs, 'not even in the form of semiotic
"chora"'[with a note referring to
Kristeva]. Signs implies some
categorical difference between forms of
expression and forms of content, but it is
only real once we reach the semiotic level
[maybe]. Until then, abstract machines
do not actually write, nor generate
deterritorialized signs. However at the
semiotic level signs can also be treated as
particles, something real.
It seems wise to reserve the term 'sign' for
the semiotic level, but here, we have to avoid
linguistic imperialism, especially in the form
of the domination of the signifier, where all
signs becomes signifiers, and 'all signs are
endowed with signifiance' (73). This is
an illusion arising from a particular notion
of the abstract machine, and has the happy
illusion of making the signifier connect with
all the other strata in a generalized way [
denying pre-human communication]. The
conventional approach sees the signified as
not autonomous from the signifier, and this
permits significant redundancy, 'Hence its
incredible despotism'. All expression is
reduced to the signifier, yet this assumes a
constant relation between content and
expression, and ignores distinctive
relations.
Advocates of the signifier take the relation
between words and things as the essential
one. Foucault has offered us a way to
criticize this: a thing like a prison is a
form of content [social practices?] related to
other forms of content like schools, and it
relates not just to the word 'prison', but to
a lot of other concepts such as
delinquency. Delinquency should not be
seen as another mere signifier, however, but a
form of expression, 'a set of statements
arising in the social field considered as a
stratum', while the content is not just the
thing, but 'a complex state of things as a
formation of power (architecture,
regimentation, etc.)'. We could argue
instead that there are 'discursive
multiplicities of expression', and 'non
discursive multiplicities of content'
intersecting together. Prisons also have
specific forms of content and expression,
which are not found in the notion of
delinquency, and delinquency also achieves
autonomous content. We can understand
the relation as 'the shared state of the
abstract machine, acting not at all as a
signifier, but as a kind of diagram' (74), and
that also produces schools, barracks,
hospitals and so on. Content and
expression here are fitted together in a
concrete assemblage, a whole 'organization
articulating formations of power and regimes
of signs' (75), operating on the molecular
level as disciplinary power. There is no
one overall signifier for institutions, even
schools, but rather 'two distinct
formalizations in reciprocal presupposition
and constituting a double pincer[ continuing
the stuff about God is a lobster etc] : the
formalization of expression in the reading and
writing lesson [in schools] (with its own
relative contents), and the formalization of
content in the lesson of things (with their
own relative expressions)'. Social life
is not just a matter of signifier and
signified, but stratification.
So we
can argue that there are forms of expression
without signs as in the genetic code.
Signs only appear in particular circumstances
as subsets of language, particular 'real
usages or functions of language'. Signs
do not indicate the presence of the thing, but
rather arise from 'deterritorialization and
reterritorialization', when certain
thresholds are crossed – so we can even talk
about animal signs. Signs need not be
signifiers. Signifiers and the notion of
signifiance are again only subsets of possible
regimes. There can be 'asemiotic
expressions', without signs, and asignifying
signs or regimes. Signifiance is not
necessarily even the most interesting regime,
although it is more imperialist
['cancerous… and more steeped in
illusion'] (76).
Nor can we reduce everything to base and
superstructure, say by seeing [economic]
content as primary. Expression does not
just reflect content, not even if we allow it
to be relatively independent or
reactive. Contents and expressions
develop their own formalizations, and these
can interact, but they are both parts of an
abstract machine and related by machinic
assemblages. It is not just a relation
of conventional abstraction. Nor are
assemblages just superstructures [to get more
explicitly Marxist], with regimes of signs as
another tier, ideology. Language is more
heterogeneous and contradictory.
Particular forms are not ideology: '(ideology
is a most execrable concept obscuring all of
the effectively operating social
machines)'. Power is not located in the
state and is everywhere, wherever we find
formalizations of content and expression and
their relations. Nor can content be
exclusively reduced to the economic, or to
some dominant signifier like the phallus.
We also have to avoid the notion of some sort
of evolution between the strata. But the
different combinations of content and
expression are not stages. Nor can we
conveniently defined spheres like the
biosphere—there is only 'the same
Mechanosphere' (77). All strata are
organized even the substrata, and are not
separated by degrees of organization.
The more organized can also serve as a base
for the development of other strata, as when
technical phenomena help to provide the basis
for the development of new bacteria.
Strata communicate in a way which is not
preordained.
On the plane of consistency, semiotic
components of all kinds are found, chemical,
electronic, genetic and so on, and some
systems emerged like wasps and orchids.
We should not consider these elements as
metaphoric, because 'all that consists is
Real'. On the plane of consistency,
there are no extensive differences including
those between content and expression: these
emerge only with strata. But how can we
apply general names outside of strata and
territories? There is no dualism between
these and the plane of consistency, however,
especially as strata are just thickenings of
planes of consistency. The abstract
machine constitutes both plane and strata
simultaneously, and forces on the plane carry
with them some sort of memory from
strata. However, the plane of
consistency can be understood as a series of
'continuums of intensity' extracted from the
forms and substances. And the plane or
machine 'emits and combines
particles-signs'[pretty much borrowed from Machinic
Unconscious here, and pretty well
incomprehensible without reading it?],
including asignifying signs, and this is the
source of deterritorialization. In this
way, concrete indexes become 'absolute values'
[very abstracted ones that can be reapplied
and/or overcoded?]. Intensive forces are
congealed into discontinuous forms and
substances ['conjunction'].
Destratification is clearly also
involved. The processes are not random,
but nor are they governed by external rules.
So abstract machines produce 'different
simultaneous states', but they also produce 'a
concrete machinic assemblage', again on the
plane of consistency. These developments
can remain on the plane, or take place within
a stratum which envelops the abstract
machine. However, machinic assemblages
are different. They operate on strata to
link segments of contents and expression, to
produce substrata of both types, and put into
relation substratum and stratum. They
also have to stay 'in touch with the plane of
consistency'[definitional arguments here,
merely rephrasing what earlier discussions
have alluded to, only in obsessive detail—must
be Guattari's bit]. Assemblages are more
localized, and articulate elements of a
stratum or relate swtrata, or produce an
organism [weird anthropological and
mythological examples involving Dogon and
Amazons, 79]. Assemblages unify
elements, and permit a connection between
'states of force and regimes of signs'.
Overall they 'effectuate the abstract
machine', but how does this actually happen in
the Mechanosphere? We know it's got nothing to
do with all the usual binaries like
signifier/signified, or base/superstructure,
mind/matter. Apart from being reductive,
this would close off the possibilities of
destratification.
[At this stage, Challenger
was clearly cracking up, we are told, but he
felt the need to summarize]. We have to
work with notions like the BWO 'or the
destratified Plane of Consistency; the Matter of
the Plane, that which occurs on the body or
plane (singular, nonsegmented multiplicities
composed of intensive continuums, emissions of
particles-signs, or conjunctions of flows); and
the abstract Machine, or abstract Machines
insofar as they construct the body or draw that
plane or "diagram" what occurs (lines of flight
or absolute deterritorializations)' (80).
Then we have to consider strata in a system, how
they form matter, distinguish between expression
and content and their units, 'for example, signs
and particles', and operate with territories and
their changes. We have to see that they
set up double articulations, including the
construction of segmentary multiplicities.
Although things like content and expression are
distinct, they intermingle in machinic
assemblages. This actually varies however
from stratum to stratum, and it is this that
produces the 'real [actualized?] distinction
between content and expression'. Further,
there are distinctions according to orders of
magnitude, the type of resonances at work [such
as induction], the differences between formal
and real distinctions, the nature of linearities
of expression [induction and transduction], and
the development of superlinear expressions like
human language which permit translations.
The stratum can become a substratum for another
stratum. The degree of unity of
composition is defined by milieu, elements and
traits. They can be subdivided into
parastrata and epistrata as above there, and
these are also strata in their own right.
A machinic assemblage relates the strata, and
also contents and expressions on each stratum [must
do or else we could not explain real objects and
clusters] A single assemblage can 'borrow
from different strata' (81), and display
different amounts of disorder. However,
because machinic assemblages also have to relate
to planes of consistency [they have to
for reasons of philosophic consistency
here] and behind them, abstract machines,
they are also metastrata. Abstract
machines can be enveloped in strata, or work on
the plane of consistency, performing
destratification, and combining these two
produces a specific effectuation of the abstract
machine. Since machinic assemblages do all
these wonderful things, 'they rotate in all
directions, like beacons'.
Apparently, 'only later would all of this take
on concrete meaning'. Challenger seems to
have cracked up entirely, but then 'panic is
creation'. He retreated towards the plane
of consistency, trying to slip into an
assemblage, to reach the 'Mechanosphere or
rhizosphere'(82) [with an ending quote from HP
Lovecraft!].
back to menu page
|