Notes on: Leonardo, Z. And
Broderick, A. (2011) Smartness as
Property: A Critical Exploration of
Intersections Between Whiteness and
Disability Studies. Teachers College
Record. 113 (10) to 206 – 2232.
Dave Harris
NB the American usage of 'smartness' is
indexed here throughout,of course
The point is to unravel the myth of the
normal child and identify ideological
systems which constitute it. They draw on
critical race or Whiteness studies and
disability studies and their theoretical
intersections. They don't want to operate
with particular issues all groups but
rather focus on ideologies, the construct
of smartness as intersecting both race and
ability, and the need to consider both
ideological traditions.
It is obvious that POC are overrepresented
in special education and therefore seems
to be exposed to a double jeopardy.
However there are theoretical pitfalls in
the work which tends to foreground either
race or ability in discussing notions of
'overrepresentation' for example. Problems
are obscured here. It is not just a matter
of statistical overrepresentation, but the
legitimacy of the system and how it
operates. Even if the numbers of POC in
special education were somehow
representative in terms of numbers in the
education system as a whole, the problem
would not have been satisfactorily
addressed — the 'naturalness and
neutrality of the bureaucratic system of
special education… And, by extension a
deficit driven and psychological
understandings of "ability"' which grounds
it would not have been challenged (2208).
Equal representation does not mean
equitable distribution of power.
Instead, the central concept of
smartness needs to be challenged. Like
race, 'ability is a relational system'
with a necessary 'denigrated other' the
uneducable, and this generates privilege
and a normative centre
If we examine Whiteness rather than
traditional race studies, we can better
unmask racial privilege. This is a White
led innovation, a '"pedagogy of the
oppressor" (Allen 2005)' (2209), showing
how educational practice becomes natural
and valorised. It is an intervention race
theory and studies how White myths and
even the concept of race is perpetuated.
Of course minorities also invest in race
as 'a certain possessive investment in
colour… A defensive posture, a reaction to
the power of Whiteness… Histories of
resistance, pride in their culture', but
this is a reaction, within a logic
premised on Whiteness.
Whiteness needs to be pinned down, since
it tends to be a floating signifier.
[shades of S Hall here] It is an
articulation of disparate elements only
some of which are racial. There are class
gender and sexual interests as well. For
example subordinate White groups are also
offered a psychological reward, 'public
wages' [privileges for being White or at
least not being Black]. There is no
essence to Whiteness offering benefits to
any essential group or membership. It can
even include groups with 'long-standing
ethnic animosities towards one another,
such as the English and Irish' in the USA.
It aims to preserve race relations
themselves, with Whiteness at the top.
There are periodic ambiguities, for
example allocating Arabs [sometimes
considered to be honorary Whites, at least
until 9/11]. There may be buffer groups.
As C.
Harris argued, Whiteness is
analogous to property, and this relation
developed through the objectification of
African slaves and then through
reification and hegemony which transformed
Whiteness into law and conferred
privileges which can be demarcated and
fenced off.
This notion of ideology might look
orthodox compared to recent formulations,
especially those that oppose it to
science. These took ideology to be a
descriptive term relating to integrative
functions, culturally-based necessities,
even inspiration for mass mobilisations
[associated with Ricoeur, Geertz and
Gouldner] [odd rendition of the humanist
case]. They want to go back to theoretical
orthodoxy with Whiteness.
Whiteness is not an essentialism, there is
no privilege colour skin. It varies
according to the commonsense of the time,
as certain US legal cases indicate
[particular people were able to argue they
were White because they originated from
the Caucasus, for example, so the courts
retorted that there were nonWhite
Caucasians 'by the standards of common
sense' (2211). A man of Japanese descent
claimed to be more culturally White than
many recent White immigrants, but lost
because Japan was deemed to be 'not a land
of White people', despite commonsense in
this case.] Asian Americans are still
sometimes called probationary Whites or
honorary Whites. In some cases
Mexican-Americans have been ruled to be
White when treaties were drawn up, and a
Mexican appealing against a murder
conviction on the grounds that there were
no Mexicans on the jury was rebuffed
because he was deemed to be White. These
are examples of 'egregious arbitrariness'
(2212), showing the tactical nature of
Whiteness and its violent history.
Whiteness exists 'for the sole purpose of
stratification'. This has led Roediger 'to
announce that "Whiteness is nothing but
false and oppressive"', and they take this
as a good beginning. He did not say this
applied to people, but to an ideology.
Some people have been traitors to
Whiteness, although it's also possible to
benefit from Whiteness even while acting
against it. The point is to disrupt 'the
commonsense notion of Whiteness as
equatable with White identity'. It is
instead 'an interpellating system' whose
subjects act on behalf of Whiteness.
'There were no White people to speak off
before the arrival of an interpellation
called Whiteness' (2213). White people are
not 'an ontologically real category', but
can become so as an effective ideology, as
in Althusser's
argument that the modes of existence of
ideology are real. Social institutions
like education, and processes like common
sense 'recognise certain bodies as White'
The argument insists that Whiteness exists
'only as a tool for oppression' acting
against racism need not reconstruct
Whiteness. White people acting differently
need not make Whiteness appear to be
virtuous but can cause it to cease to
exist, to expose it as 'violent and bogus'
[I think the pessimistic outcome is more
likely though, that acting will make
Whiteness seen virtuous]. Whiteness was
constructed 'for the sole purpose of
denigrating and dispossessing people of
colour', starting about 500 years ago.
This was implicit in people such as
Descartes who really meant '"I think I am
White therefore I am"'. POC also shared
this ideology and the way it was embedded
into educational arrangements, in the form
of White smartness, the educational system
and official knowledge, in the way books
signify POC, for example. If ever it were
possible to think of ourselves as White
without racial privilege, 'the circle
between ideology and material practice has
been broken' (2214). However racial
supremacy is taught to all students in a
pedagogical form, but still with a
possibility of critically reflecting on
its manifestations, as in the notion of a
hidden curriculum. There is a lot of
analysis as well including Gillborn
and earlier Leonardo.
We can now turn to disability, and the
ideology of smartness which works in the
same way to create a centre of normative
privilege, a system of domination and a
periphery of marginalisation and
subjugation. This ideology 'operates in
the service of the ideology of Whiteness
and vice versa' seen particularly clearly
in special education and the issue
minority over representation, once we add
necessary ideological layers referring to
the bureaucratic system, especially 'the
ideological systems of ability and
disability, competence and incompetence,
smartness and not – so – smartness'
The ideology of smartness
A great deal of ideological work goes on
hear in schooling, and smartness leads to
entitlement to cultural capital [not seen
as something the family provides in this
case] as well as prestige. Literature both
in race studies and disability studies
have taken on the idea of smartness but
both have their own theoretical
inadequacies.
We know that schools construct and
constitute some people are smart. Teachers
do this and reward the smart. We can make
the immediate point that the term means
nothing without privilege, that the whole
term exists for the sole purpose of
stratification. As we saw with Whiteness,
this can lead to the conclusion that
smartness is nothing that holds and
oppressive as well, that it exists only to
promote hierarchy. Questioning the concept
might lead it to wither away as a
category.
Certainly intelligence and IQ have been
critiqued before and there is a similarity
between cultural constructs of
intelligence and cultural constructs of
race. In America the two have been
'"inextricably intertwined"' (2216),
especially if intelligence is seen to be
sophisticated thinking [not quite Bourdieu, but
close]. The disabled need to be considered
here as well, although they are often
included implicitly in the definition of
competent White people. Specifically
people with disabilities are less likely
to be characterised as smart [citing
Hayman 1999], part of the general tendency
to take physiological factors as
indicators of intelligence. However, even
Hayman seems to suggest that there may be
some realist basis to smartness, and this
is common in commentaries, to 'leave open
the possibility that there are exceptions
to their treatment of smartness as
ideological' (2217), even if these are
rare.
Critical disability studies to offer more
of a dispute and challenge, usually
through taking on notions like cognitive
impairments or intellectual disability.
Some people, like Blatt (1999) see these
terms as mythical or metaphorical,
inherently abusive, certainly inadequate
and undefinable. Most of this stems from
social constructionist approaches denying
the ontological reality and objective
epistemology of the concept, and favouring
qualitative research based on the
testimony and experiences of the
individuals who have been labelled.
Nevertheless the work has evolved into 'a
more general and much more radical
critique of the corollary constructed
intellectual ability', although this is
still 'somewhat marginalised' within
disability studies, perhaps because it
might strike at critical academics
themselves.
,
For L and B, there are theoretical
inadequacies. Social constructionist
critiques denying that disability
categories are given or real on import a
kind of relativism. This does not help
explain unequal relations of power,
oppression and mystification. It ignores
the modes of practice, or, for Althusser,
how these concepts are embodied in
ideological state apparatuses, real and
institutional forms. Reality appears on
the existential plane. Ideological
critique is necessary to grasp this.
There is still some reification of
traditional conceptualisations as well,
for example in the personal accounts of
some of the research respondents who still
use terms like 'retarded' and 'normal' in
their stories of improvement and how their
neurodivergence manifested itself [exactly
as Lewis and Arday do]. These might be
stories of resistance, but they still
contain ideological constructions.
Asserting intellectual competence in these
ideological terms is quite understandable,
especially given the reaction of many
professionals, some of whom failed to even
grant that these individuals might be
exceptions to the rule. However, these
strong reactions are a tacit admission
that critique threatens an ideological
state apparatus, and one study noted
'vehement professional position to
recognising the competence of individuals
who have been described and regarded as
"mentally retarded"' (2221).
There are signs of [convergence],
validating as smart after all people who
have been originally stigmatised. This is
no different from recognising that some
POC are nice people: 'the standards are
set by the Masters terms'. Smartness is
still a property granted according to the
owner's discretion, with value only
because others continue to be denied
access.
It is understandable that parents want to
tell their kids they are smart and to
avoid negative labelling, to be pleased if
their kids are gifted and talented, to see
such labels as some sort of protection
against the full discrimination of racism.
But there are still costs. Smartness
requires an opposite, 'the cursed
population of so called low intellect'
(2222). To claim you are smart means to
condemn others. It also means to deride
the intellectually disabled on a daily
basis, it is similar to 'the preference
for lightness within communities of
colour', or the hierarchies found among
disabled people, including 'the cultural
preference for Asperger's syndrome over
autism, or "high functioning" over "low
functioning" autism', the same as smart
and not so smart autists. These are
possibly local defensive responses but
they still 'unwittingly reproduce the
system of stratification responsible for
their degradation'.
There is still a central notion of 'the
presumption of competence', an underlying
view that despite individual judgements
there must be a rational explanation for
ranking decisions. There is a similarity
with the idea of 'culturally relevant
pedagogy, in which students interests,
experiences, desires and cultures are
understood to be relevant, rich, and
valuable resources, and the onus is placed
on the educator to enact curriculum and
pedagogy in culturally relevant ways'
(2223). This assumes competence and
capacity, but there are theoretical
difficulties. If it is understood as a
form of property or cultural capital it is
'theoretically untenable that everyone
could attain access to these material
spoils… Just as in the capitalist system,
everyone cannot, by definition, be
wealthy'. Competence implies its
conceptual binary privilege.
The presumption of competence stance needs
explicitly critical engagement of how
smartness is bound up with [vague] other
oppressive ideologies including Whiteness.
Otherwise it is 'a mystifying mythology'.
Seeing people as incompetent involves
racist, classist, sexist and other
ideologies, more so than in ablist
ideologies, they must be interrogated if
there is to be an emancipatory narrative.
If individuals with significant
disabilities successfully contest their
relegation and do secure a themselves more
equitable access to opportunities, this
often leaves undiscussed the role of
ideological privilege, and success is
often achieved without theorising
oppressive ideologies of smartness. The
successful can therefore become 'sub-
oppressors in an oppressive system, and
rather than challenge it they are content
with sharing in its spoils' (2224).
Advance in one area will not necessarily
contradict the enforcement in another.
Educational success stories and even
'actually rely on ideological acts of
Whiteness and of class privilege in the
process'. An example follows with the
provision of facilitated communication
with autists, which reinforces class
privilege, and probably White privilege ,
while POC who are disabled are more likely
to be placed in segregated classrooms and
schools.
Toward the abolition of
Whiteness and smartness
The normative centre of schools has been
exposed by both disability and race
studies, but both are incomplete. It is
important to turn to ideology rather than
social construction, and race studies do
this, but they still leave out severely
disabled individuals, which implies there
are limits or exceptions and that severely
disabled people 'really are not smart'
(2225) and so are exempt from
emancipation. Disability studies to deal
with the significantly disabled, but have
not made the shift from social
construction to ideology, and not properly
analysed Whiteness as an ideology and so
in some ways they reproduce ideological
acts of Whiteness and class privilege in
the policies to relieve the oppression of
some significantly disabled people.
Isolation therefore can perpetuate and
reify other ideological systems of
oppression and reinforce oppressive
relations and 'a conciliatory posture
towards a bogus ideology'.
They insist that Whiteness is 'nothing
but' false and oppressive and that its
role is only 'as a tool for oppression'
and extend this to smartness. Whiteness
and smartness are real only insofar as
social institutions recognise these
qualities [and implement them in
practice]. Ideologies operate as
intertwined systems so addressing one
system and not the others will be
incomplete and can even encourage
oppression. What is required is more
integrated efforts to dismantle
interlocking ideologies of oppression in
schools, although this is challenging.
Theoretical integration is required as
well as ethical imperatives.
It is not enough just to 're-articulate'
Whiteness or smartness, nor just to
abolish either, since this 'will not win
over many Whites to join the cause' (2226)
and is 'a nonstarter'. Rearticulation
might be a coping strategy, but even there
'it is doomed from the start. Softer
versions might mean more White recruits,
but this still might indicate ineffective
combating of racism. The same goes for
re-articulation of disability, say through
'Gardner-esque, relativistic calls for a
celebration of "multiple" intelligences…
Some forms of "intelligence" are still
more highly culturally valued than others'
and so will still be used in hierarchies
[Kincheloe 2004 is cited for a critique of
multiple intelligences]. Instead we need
to abolish both Whiteness and
intelligence, although this is 'not very
intuitive' and may attract opposition from
both POC and from Whites.
It involves the abolition of identities
and existing social relations, 'what it
means to be a racial being', and those who
enjoy the status of being smart and those
who aspire to that status, even those who
have had their status modified, [say from
mentally retarded to neurodivergent]. Few
academics even in the field seem eager to
engage in a conversation about abolition
because their identities are bound up in
being smart [and their professional
ideologies are engaged] — they are also
predominantly White.
However smartness is not an inherent
physical feature and nor is Whiteness
[although they are immediately detectable
and therefore very convenient in
commonsense hierarchies? Not everything
can be used in ideological systems?]. Both
are 'performative cultural ideological
systems' (2227 constructing the centre of
schools and societies with materialist
effects and material consequences. Both
are taught, 'are pedagogical'. Both
control access to property, including
cultural capital.
This is also 'the great promise of this
work' — 'pedagogical possibility for
disruption' [very idealist and
non-Althusserian here]. We must engage in
'complex interrogation of multiple
interlocking ideological systems of
oppression' and take on other ideologies
such as 'goodness, beauty, sanity and so
on' (2228), which are connected with
disability hetero sexism and patriarchy.
These ideologies must be unpacked as a way
to form alliances with other radical
educators seeking more inclusive and more
socially just cultural practices of
schooling. [Note 1 says further
exploration of these connections with
beauty and goodness need particular
development].
|
|
|