READING
GUIDE TO: Bourdieu, P.and
Passeron, J – C (1990) Reproduction in Education, Society
and Culture, 2nd edition, London:
Sage Publications.
by
Dave Harris
Preface to the second
edition
Bourdieu says that the points
made here are clearly linked with his other work
such as Distinction,
Academic Discourse,the Inheritors, and Outline of a Theory of Practice.However, his notion of
reproduction has been distorted and simplified,
and the empirical work ignored.There is no mechanical reproduction, but
rather a process of transformation and resistance.It would be wrong to see
his work as Althusserian—he has done empirical
work on classroom interaction, for example
[unfortunately, a very obscure reference for
this—McCallum, D, and Ozolins, U.(eds) (1980) Melbourne Working Papers,
University of Melbourne: University of Melbourne
Press—I am on its trail. I think it might be this].This work might look like ethnomethodology,
in fact, rather similar to Cicourel [possibly the
one about how decisions are made about bad
behaviour and juvenile justice when school rules
are actually put into practice?].Classrooms involve negotiating a ‘minimal
working definition of the situation of
communication’ (ix).It
is a model showing how the transmission of
cultural capital goes on behind the backs of the
participants and sometimes against their will, and
how ‘differences in inherited cultural capital…[are stamped]…with the meritocratic
seal of academic consecration…[via a]…credential’
( ix-x).Schools
legitimate the exclusions and inclusions that make
up the social order, and can produce the State
Nobility.Credentials
take the place of feudal titles.They are not just a record of skills, but
reflect ‘social essence’ (x).Schools both reproduce and conceal this
process.Bourdieu
cites later American work on American elitism
showing how even their credentials are also linked
to cultural capital.
Foreword (Tom Bottomore]
For Bourdieu, there is a close
connection between theory and empirical research
on this topic.Reproduction
is about the symbolic power of power relations,
and their legitimacy.Pedagogy
involves imposing a ‘cultural arbitrary’, a
cultural scheme that looks natural but is really
based on power.Pedagogic
action involves more than just what schools do
[the family in particular is discussed below].How pedagogic action
works can be spelled out to give a series of
testable propositions, especially through actual
interaction in universities.This implies complexity of class relations,
especially given changes in the composition of
classes and the activities of counter cultures.
Forward to the French
edition [the authors]
Sociological language contains
ideological overtones.It
is necessary to avoid a moralistic reading
especially.These
problems arise when using terms such as violence
or arbitrariness.We
must also avoid excessive philosophical
speculation too.The
notion of a cultural arbitrary means that culture‘cannot be deduced from
any principle’ (xx), meaning we must look for its
social conditions and role.It
is also necessary that the arbitrary origin is
misrecognised, and this immediately suggests an
arbitrary use of power.‘Symbolic
violence’ is a term designed to break the
conventional, including the spontaneous depictions
of pedagogy, to show the unity of arbitrary
classifications and arbitrary power, and how these
belong to the general category of violence.In particular, we need
to show the homology between the school’s monopoly
of legitimate symbolic violence, and the state’s
monopoly of physical violence.We must not be misled by appearances,
especially an apparent shift from
authoritarianism.We
must question the social function involved,
especially of the ‘indirect paths of academic
consecration’ ( xxi), which are mechanisms
to hide pedagogical violence.Attempts to conceal these only show their
importance.
Translator’s note [Richard
Nice]
Thus book is a product of
Bourdieu’s Centre for European Sociology [a useful
summary of the collected works and specialisms
ensues].It was
founded on an homology between the school system
and the church, which led to several sociology of
religion pieces.Religion
and education were both seen as ‘fields’,
producing work on various sections of the fields,
including work on particular authors and their
relations to fields.There
was even interest in the scientific field, in
particular the way in which an arbitrary can still
produce progress.Members
of a field shared typical misrecognitions—belief
for the religious, neutrality of teacher judgments
in education.The
work included some material on language codes.There were aspects of
the notion of habitus here too.
Book one: Foundations
of a Theory of Symbolic Violence
[Laid out horribly formally as
a series of theses and glosses.I have not attempted to reproduce (!) this
structure, and have mostly summarized the
glosses.]
Power conceals itself under
symbolic forms [and therefore all symbolic forms
are really power relations?].Understanding this requires a classically
sociological approach which neither reduces
everything to individuals nor to a theory of
symbols [semiotics?] All pedagogic action is
symbolic violence which imposes a cultural
arbitrary.There are
many kinds of pedagogic action, shared across
social groups including the family and
institutionalised education.Pedagogic action always legitimates the
dominant class by reproducing its cultural
arbitrary [this seems to be an acknowledgement
here that the dominated class can occasionally
reproduce its own cultural arbitrary, in
families].School and
classroom activities are best seen as ‘fourth
degree propositions’ of this general tendency.However, schools do tend
to secure a monopoly of legitimate symbolic
violence [legitimated by the state, presumably].
Pedagogic
action
Pedagogic action depends on the
power relations of the major classes and groups.For example the
differences between patrilineal and matrilineal
societies produce different kinds of parental
authority.Power
relations must take particular forms,
however—pedagogic ones.This
depends on power relations outside of the specific
relation of pedagogic action.A dominant pedagogic action is dominant
because it expresses more fully the objective
interests of the dominant class.This dominant pedagogic action can produce
specific pedagogic actions in different sectors.[Not the first hint of
an Althusserian notion of ‘a structure in
dominance’].
Pedagogic actions also
reproduce the selection of groups according to
their cultural ability because they only develop
and transmit what is been selected as worthy.The actual meanings of a
culture must be arbitrary (non deducible, for
example from some notion of nature [—so that
screwsRousseau]).The selection of meaning
is necessary in order to lend significance to a
culture.The signs of
arbitrariness are clear when we compare one
culture to others or to other imagined
possibilities.The
necessity of the culture really derive some its
connections to social conditions, but this is
masked by a common ‘genesis amnesia’ (9).
Power relations are never
naked, and culture is never pure—so idealism and
relativism are inadequate.Pedagogic
action operates between ‘pure force and pure
reason’ (10).That
some elements are really arbitrary leads to the
need to make greater use of ‘direct means of
constraint’ (10).Pedagogic
actions reproduce power relations and the system
of cultural arbitraries.So
the whole education system reproduces culture and
social or power relations.Functionalism
sees the reproduction of the whole cultural
capital system as a common heritage, but pedagogic
actions are really the reproduction of
distributions of cultural capital and therefore of
the social structure.The
economic value of cultural capitals is clearly
involved.
Pedagogic
authority
The education system needs to
both implement the symbolic activities of
pedagogic action and to make it look as if it is
autonomous.It
therefore collaborates in misrecognitions.There are paradoxes—for
example in claiming the authority to teach
cultural relativism on the one hand, and yet to
claim that the cultivated pupil is ‘a native of
all cultures’ on the other (12).This shows how the power of the pedagogic
action requires a misrecognition of its own
position.Especially
glossed is the notion that pedagogues are
nonviolent, that they engage in ‘non directive
teaching…Rousseauistic
myths of natural education, or pseudo Freudian
myths of non repressive education’ (13).
Pedagogic authority is really
about the right to exert symbolic violence and
claim legitimacy, so it reinforces arbitrary
power.It does not
need any external validation.Pedagogic authority is especially not
psychological [ that is related to 'personality'?]
, and can be unconscious.It
is not the basis of rational choice or a social
contract.The
recognition of its authority shows its power—its
objects are unable to criticize it [Bourdieu gives
a rather Durkheimian example here of an outlaw who
rebels but only by accepting that the law has the
right to ban him].The
strength of pedagogic authority is therefore
related to the impossibility of brute domination,
and to the extent and unification of market
mechanisms which constitute the value of different
pedagogies.The
legitimacy of the power system itself is an
important variable in retaining pedagogic
authority—it depends on the dominated not
realizing their strength or potential.
Thus analyzing pedagogic action
is at the heart of analyzing the social basis and
exercise of power, domination and legitimacy.The power relations
themselves determine characteristic modes of
imposition and concealment.This
depends on: the congruence of the cultural
arbitrary of the dominant group and the particular
kind imposed by the pedagogic action; the extent
to which coercive imposition is ruled out or
apparent [an interesting example follows noting
the divergences between cultural and power
arbitraries, especially in the case of the French
working class who distance themselves from
educational culture and its authority, but are
also more likely to accept repression and
sanctions as legitimate](16):there may be different
stances to corporal punishment—for one group it
simply helps them recognize the arbitrary nature
of power, while for another it is a mere
‘attribute of teacherly legitimacy’ (16).
The recognition of the
arbitrary power of a pedagogic action still might
not lead to a full understanding of symbolic
violence.However,
the most radical challenges are provided by
utopian beliefs in a culture without any
arbitrariness, or an individual fulfilment.However, utopian
thinking like this is understood best as a device
to enable a new group to come to power—for
example, in the 18th century, French
intellectuals embraced the idea of cultural
tolerance the better to attack the church.In this sense, utopian
thinking is still illusory and misrecognises its
own violence.
Experience alone is never
enough to counter pedagogic action nor is ‘liberal
education’.This
merely masks the arbitrary nature of pedagogic
action.Indeed,
sometimes the softer approaches might be more
effective ways of exercising symbolic violence.For example the American
education system which displays affection, love
and the use of nicknames, also becomes a ‘subtle
instrument of repression, the withdrawal of
affection, a pedagogy technique which is no less
arbitrary…than
corporal punishment or disgrace’ (17).The psychological
relationship also conceals an arbitrary character,
as in 'human relations' [presumably in the
management sense].These
are also more tightly bound to the traditional
system than appears to be the case—it is simply
that one system is waiting to replace the other
(18).
It follows that pedagogic
action is not just a technical matter of efficient
communication: it must also have its authority
recognized.Authority
is sometimes seen as the major real issue anyway,
but it is usually misrecognised.As a result it is usually non-negotiable
and rarely requires to win consent.It is often enough to claim that something
is ‘education’, as propagandists sometimes do.It is its position in a
system of pedagogic authority that makes pedagogic
communication effective rather than the personal
qualities of educators or educated involved.The same goes with
willingness to listen.
Pedagogic authority is
supported by the dominant cultural arbitrary.However, educational and
academic legitimacy can come into competition with
the pedagogic authority of others.However, academic knowledge is claimed as
being especially valuable, which enables it to
regulate and integrate its rivals (23).A failure to grasp this
is what haunts liberating education—from those who
think it is important to teach elite culture and
Latin to the masses [the Jacobin policy,
apparently], to the open recognition of diversity
and the value of popular culture [often involving
the aggressive denunciation of dominant culture]
(24). Both olicies show definite ambivalence
towards the dominant cultural heritage.
The agents of pedagogic action
are best seen as delegates of social groups or
classes whose cultural arbitraries are being
imposed.They are not
necessarily explicit or legalised agents, but
functional ones.They
must be so, in explaining the‘cultural
proxy between the [dominant] cultural arbitrary
imposed by that pedagogic action and the culture
of arbiters of the groups or classes subject to
it’ ( 25).Thus the
media for example ‘encounter and reinforce
predispositions’, and it is class/power relations
rather than the force of ideas as such that make
them effective.There
is a tacit delegation here.Delegation
is limited by the need to reproduce the cultural
arbitrary [with a reference to lots of examples of
kinship systems here], and there can be conflicts.Similarly, the
recognition of authority by the dominated class
works only if there is a pay off in terms of
market value or symbolic value—for example in
terms of middle class support of schools [there is
a link to material on the abstract value of
diplomas here -- but see Bourdieu and Boltansky].
There is a risk, however,
because the education system also determines lack
of worth.This can be
exacerbated if there is a unified cultural market
[yet another notion of a structure in dominance,
since pedagogic action unites and dominates the
cultural market].Dominated
systems can survive, but students soon realise the
worthlessness of their products. In
this way pedagogic action
establishes its authority and needs less
legitimation.If all
goes well, there is a close relation between the
dominant culture or arbitrary, the cultural
arbitrary of the dominant pedagogic action, and
the cultural arbitrary of students through their
early family influences.This
is especially effective if the economy and the
educational system are integrated so [however,
there are often contradictions, as Bourdieu and
Boltanski say].Ideally,
a relation also exists between pedagogy, the value
of diplomas, and the family, and cultural capital
itself (30).Such
close relations lead to classic
misrecognitions—ethnocentrism for the [lucky]
individual, and a general misunderstanding of the
relations between legitimate culture and the
reproduction of power relations.
Pedagogic
work
Systematic work is needed
especially if education systems are to produce a
‘lasting habitus’ (31).Hence
the very long duration of the education system
compared with families, and the inertia of the
education system.The
habitus is an ‘analogue of genetic capital’ while
pedagogic work is an analogue of generation (32).Pedagogy work is also
related to the production of the cultural
arbitrary and its reproduction in a durable
habitus.This is more
effective than conventional political power, which
reproduces itself in the short term.Effective pedagogic work generates a
transposable habitus, one which is exhaustive.
Pedagogic action implies
pedagogic work—another delegation.Together, they help to integrate the
dominant group, and it is this rather than some
consensus or common culture that operates.The actual contents of
pedagogic work can look and be very different, for
example, producing different artistic styles, or
the system of paired oppositions in politics or
aesthetics.Again,
these contents become accepted as legitimate, as
effectively ‘as physical restraint’ (36):
pedagogic work produces a tendency to always give
‘the right response’ (36).Pedagogic
work therefore confirms pedagogic authority, in a
‘circle of baptism and confirmation (37).This produces an
unquestioning acceptance of cultural arbitraries
as ‘natural’.It is
impossible to leave behind these effects, since
there is no reason outside of ‘the circle of
pedagogic authority’ (37).
Pedagogic work produces the
legitimate consumer, and the right ‘social
definition of the legitimate product and the
disposition to consume it in the legitimate
manner’ (38).[This
whole section looks a bit like Althusser’s
generalities model, with pedagogic work
transforming pedagogical authority into
educational contents]. Genesis amnesia is the
usual result, which can lead to the concepts such
as 'natural reason' or ‘innate taste’ (38).Agents who consume
cultural objects do so because pedagogic work has
shaped their values and the legitimacy of the
objects too (39).Pedagogic
worktherefore
produces misrecognitions of both pedagogical
authority and its relation to social reproduction.It makes it impossible
to see the limits of an habitus, which therefore
leads to an ‘illusion of freedom and universality’
(40).
So pedagogic work is not just
about enforcing particular ideas, or the contents
of dominant culture, but its overall legitimacy.For example it persuades
people who are excluded to accept their exclusion
as legitimate, to accept hierarchies of prestige,
or to generate ‘transposable, generalised
dispositions’ toward ‘social disciplines and
hierarchies’ (41).It
helps to devalue non dominant knowledge, and
increases susceptibility to cultural goods
produced by dominant groups [and the examples here
include medicine, legal advice, and the culture
industry].
The habitus so generated seems
to be primary and irreversible.We can gain knowledge of others, but never
fully appropriate them.Secondary
pedagogic work, like that based in schools, builds
on the habitus developed in the family, despite
school denials—that is where ‘logical
dispositions’ are acquired in practice, and they
form the basis of subsequent ‘symbolic mastery’
(43).[So this is the
origin of ‘deep approaches’].[The argument here seems to be that the
family and its pedagogic work therefore structures
all the others in dominance].
Any reforming secondary
pedagogic work faces a considerable task.One tactic is to
demonstrate the arbitrary nature of cultural
roles.This is the
tactic involved in military or religious
conversion. Or to select as students only those
who are already prepared, as in finishing schools
[the example here is the Ecole Nationale
d’Administration].Some
upper class families employ members of the working
class to care for their children, and those
children have to be reconverted in boarding
schools.So, for
example, the teaching of grammar builds on those
earlier principles for logical classification
which are codified, as much as traditional laws
are.The process is
best done using‘implicit
pedagogy’ (47).Here,
the disciples abandon themselves and model
themselves on their masters.This works very well if they are already
predisposed to do so: others must be persuaded of
their failure.This
goes on at an unconscious level, via ‘anonymous,
diffuse pedagogic action’ (48).Such action includes arranging space in
particular ways.People
are able to cope with explicit verbalized
pedagogical work if they are already able to
‘neutralize in imagination or reflectionthe vital urgencies
which thrust a pragmatic disposition on the
dominated classes’ (49).
Primary socialization therefore
is really about categories and dispositions rather
than formalcognitive
mastery, about symbolic mastery.The mastery of words rather than things
helps.Those who have
already undergone this socialization can cope with
the implicit pedagogy of schooling.They already have a suitable habitus.There is, for example, a
‘structural affinity between teaching in the
humanities and bourgeois primary pedagogic action’
(50).Even in
technical education, theorization excludes
working-class children, despite their possession
of skills, and the ‘general education’ they
receive reduces their own language ‘to jargon,
slang or gibberish’ (50).
Pedagogic action which excludes
in this implicit way is better at concealing the
arbitrariness of education, and in underpinning
the legitimacy of its ‘products and hierarchies’’
(51).Museums assume
a knowledge of the cultural code [so do art
galleries, to cite an earlier example].Educational institutions
encourage self elimination, although this can be
disguised by an explicit legal form of
discrimination and elimination in the exam system,
their 'ideological function' (52).
Another ideology is found in
the notion of giftedness [see Inheritors].Rosenthal’s experiment
[the classic example of self fulfilling prophecy]
shows the flaws.Would
a perfectly rational system of pedagogic work
overcome exclusions?It
would be aimed at 'incorporating in all its pupils
the practical principles of the symbolic mastery
of practices which are inculcated by primary
pedagogic action only with [dominant] groups and
classes' (53).However
this would be utopian.Such
a
system
would
inevitably
be
vetoed
as
not
in the interests of the dominant class [smuggle it
past the bastards?].It
also assumes that the interests of individuals and
those of the dominated class are the same.In practice, there are
few socially mobile proletarians, and their cases
only 'perpetuate the structure of class relations'
(54): there is no possibility of the social
mobility of the whole dominated class.
The
education system
This takes a specific form
according to the requirements necessary to
implement pedagogic action, produce an enduring
habitus and a set of general misrecognitions.Durkheim noticed that,
for example, an education system is specifically
needed to produce a Christian habitus [in modern
societies].Weber
extracted the more general conditions for a
religious habitus [theodicy, a rational priesthood
and so on?].Bourdieu
and Passeron think the best way to proceed is to
suggest generic conditions first then examine the
social conditions which lead to the realisation of
specific forms.The
social conditions include ‘urban concentration…division of labour
entailing the autonomization of intellectual
tribunals or practices… a
market in symbolic goods’ (55).This approach can be compared with Marx on
the decline of feudal and the emergence of
capitalist modes of production.In particular, the relative autonomy of the
education system should be seen as a part of
general social change.
Pedagogic work is gradually
institutionalised, leading to paid teaching,
teacher training, standardisation, examinations
and so on.This
process probably began with medieval universities.Durkheim was right to
specify the emergence of the need for moral
education, Weber was right to spot the emergence
of a group of specialists trying to monopolise
legitimate culture: the interests of specialists
have been important in the development of the
education system, just as the activities of
priests developed a religion, once it was
established, as Weber tells us, or artists with
art, once it had emerged as an autonomous field.The specialists produce
specialist pedagogic work, in this case, the work
of schooling.
Specialist teachers disseminate
messages which they have not necessarily produced
themselves—this is the notion of professorial
mastery.It is an
ideology, requiring ‘the laboured negation of the
truth of the professorial function’, which is
cultural and social reproduction (57-8).Training, textbooks and
so on emerge really to maintain control, to
maintain an orthodoxy against various ‘prophets
and creators’.At the
same time, the possibility of prophecy is a useful
part of a myth that the institution is not totally
binding on its personnel.In
practice, there is massive standardisation,
including standard rituals, replaceable personnel,
the production of manuals, commentaries, model
answers and so on.New
members have to undergo a classic apprenticeship.Additionally, ideas are
syncretised and brought together in eclectic
lists, principally to routinise and neutralise
messages and conflicts over cultural legitimacy
(59): these are the classic ways in which
professors arrive at a consensus on a programme.
Routinization varies according
to the nature of pedagogic action and is role in
cultural reproduction.In
France, for example literary education is more
routinized than is science education, since it is
mostly literary education that reproduces dominant
culture and legitimises it.The
autonomy of a particular subject is also
important, especially whether it is confined to
the education system, or linked to other practices
in the overall field.
The education system must
produce its own agents to reproduce it.These agents reproduce
the market that gives them a value.On the surface, it looks as if they are
simply defending the value of their own scarce
educational credentials, but this action is
supported by dominant groups because they are also
reproducing the whole market [and members of
dominant groups themselves require diplomas to
legitimates their own access, as the Inheritors points
out].This process is
masked by the relative autonomy of the education
system.
Reproduction works best when
the principles of the education system are
implicit, or rendered as unconscious influences,
passed down from master to apprentice.This is part of avoiding
a general danger of education becoming too
explicit: for example, it must resist any pressure
to include more than the dominant cultural
arbitrary as its focus.This
danger is resolved by institutionalisation—‘it
resolves by its very existence the questions
raised by its existence’ (62) [clever French
stuff].The
institution protects itself from difficult
questions, such as whether teaching itself, as a
kind of mastery, is appropriate.There also certain crises which affect the
education system now and then [and the example
here is a protest by parents over controversial
content].These
crises have the potential of bringing into light
the reproduction role and the links between the
education system and wider social and
institutional conditions.
Specific school authority
develops as a subset of pedagogic authority [and
this authority is invoked against protesting
parents and others who would question the
institution].The
school as a system protects and shelters the
authority of individual teachers.The parallel here is how Papal and [RC]
Church infallibility protects the authority of
individual priests.In
fact, this parallel has played a useful
ideological role despite the emergence of the
education system from the church.Education has borrowed from the church the
assumption that teaching will be impossible
without infallibility in the system.This Christian origin has helped develop a
very uncritical acceptance of this view of school
authority.
School authority is therefore
particularly good at enabling a misrecognition
that its own symbolic violence is autonomous and
unrelated to power relations more generally.Thus school seems to be
able to be neutral in any struggle between classes
and groups, able to protect science and critique
as above petty conflicts, as the embodiment of
‘the Utopian vision of the “critical university”
capable of bringing before the tribunal of
pedagogic legitimacy the principles of cultural
arbitrariness from which it precedes’ (65).[However, some critical
intellectuals have obviously escaped, including
Bourdieu himself.In
fact, I remember Bourdieu arguing this very point
somewhere, pointing out that he only escaped
because he was a marginal member of Parisian
university life, and crossed two academic
specialisms – anthropology and sociology].Another myth is that the
education system can bring about social change on
its own, modernise societies for example.Liberal universities
only mask and help misrecognise their relation to
social and cultural power—they are also derive
their authority from social relations, in this
case liberal ones.
Misrecognition also arises
particularly when university academics become full
state employees.This
leads to a specific ‘ideology of
“disinterestedness”’ (66).Further,
individual
professors receive institutionalised authority in
a particular way, represented as professorial
charisma.This is an
effect of educational specificity which permits a
certain amount of tinkering, such as ‘juggling
with the syllabus that is implicitly on the
syllabus’ (66).There
is a general ‘enchanted adherence’ to the view
that authority rests in the person of teachers.Their real power arises
from their ability to inculcate the cultural
arbitrary, sometimes with ‘scheduled
improvisation’ which helps them mask their
relation to conventional pedagogy and thus to the
wider system of authority.
So in general, the whole
education system works by establishing the
necessary conditions for its internal
function—inculcation—which then become sufficient
conditions for the external function—cultural
reproduction.And
institutional power helps education pose as an
autonomous institution, therefore a neutral one,
the better to reproduce the cultural arbitrary of
dominant groups—‘dependence through independence’
(67).
The
Literate Tradition and Social Conservation
The analysis works from the
assumption that pedagogy is a ‘simple
communicative relation’: as it is obvious that it
is inefficient, the question arises about how a
system like this persists (107), especially
through the ‘unhappy consciousness’ of its
perpetrators (108).It
attracts a mixture of teacher confidence and
student ‘semantic fog’ (108).The words involved convey a familiarity
since they arise from ‘stereotyped
configurations’, and the style is supported by a
whole culture, sustained institutionally.Academic pedagogy is
about status rather than efficiency.It expresses values, codes, and notions of
who is worthy to receive it.It expresses social distance, supported by
physical distance—professors are ‘remote or
intangible, surrounded by vague terrifying rumour…committed to theatrical
monologue and virtuoso exhibition’ (109).Academic style is a
matter of ‘intonation, diction…delivery…oratorical
gestures’ (109).Dialogues
are only a ‘fiction or farce’, and student
responses or interventions are best seen as
religious responses.The
discourse itself is the best way to maintain
distance.It appears
as intrinsic or personal.Professorial
discourse neutralises.The
language is incantatory and largely about
preserving authority (110).It
positively discourages communicative efficiency.Student assignments are
only allowed to echo professorial discourse—the
dissertation is a copy of official discourse.There is positive
professorial contempt for the lack of clear
communication in student scripts [some scathing
remarks about students are quoted 111], but this
is rather ironic in the circumstances!In fact, garbled and
simple student work is a sign of successful
enculturation, even if students are speaking and
writing in Creole versions.Professors
are always able to blame students rather than
examining their own discourse.
There is a ‘professorial
ideology’ of student inability.Failure is a matter of not ‘being – for –
the – teacher’ (111).Students
have to respond in these terms, producing
‘semantic atoms…a
rhetoric of despair, and the regression towards
the prophylactic or propitiatory magic of a
language in which the grandiloquence of
magisterial discourse is reduced to the passwords
or sacramental phrases of a ritual murmur’ (114),‘a smokescreen of
vagueness over the possibility of truth or error…A caricature of mastery’
(114).
Class functions support the
system ‘even where its pedagogic efficiency tends
toward zero’ (114).Style
is the issue, ‘a type of relation to language and
culture’ (114).It
may be based on a Jesuitical influence, involving
a systematic reinterpretation of the social
demands of the aristocracy, involving a necessary
detachment from the pedagogic task.There is also a heavy influence of literary
aptitude—academic life is to be literary and
Parisian.However,
there is class reproduction too.The distance from native languages is
uneven, and produces two extremes: in bourgeois
parlance, there is considerable borrowing from
Latin, clear signs of the effects of scholarly or
fashionable legitimating agencies (115).Thus school [university]
transforms this legacy to a ‘quasi scholarly
handling of language’ (115), which increases the
receptive capacity for scholarly discourse among
the bourgeois.This
provides them with ‘educationally profitable
linguistic capital’ (116), whose value varies
according to changes in schools and families.The legacy comes with a
definite mode of acquisition—‘abstraction,
formalism, intellectualism, euphemistic
moderation’ (116), itself a ‘socially constituted
disposition’.It
produces a ‘distinguished distance, prudent ease,
and a contrived naturalness’.By contrast, working class language is
expressive and particularistic, moving from case
to case, from ‘illustration to parable’, avoiding
fine words and the ‘grand emotions’ (116).It features ‘banter,
rudeness and ribaldry’, and is unable to separate
‘objective denotation and subjective connotation’.Working class speech
features ellipses from frequent ‘implicit (or
gestural) reference to the situation’. This is
because there are no suitable social conditions
for distance and separation in working class life.
So language denotes social
position.There is an
underlying need to ‘stand aloof from one’s
practice and from the rule governing the practice’
(117) [if we are to do well academically].Native languages contain
revealing ‘rhetorical devices, expressive effects,
nuances of provincialism, melody of intonation,
registers of diction or forms of phraseology’
(117).These are
found in whole categories of speakers, and are
produced by the ‘social conditions of the
acquisition and use of language (117).Bourgeois speakers
systematically exclude the vulgar and thereby
affirm their distinction.[Note
16, PP. 133 – 3 acknowledges Bernstein, but
criticises him for treating the characteristics of
working class speech as abstract and intrinsic,
rather than as produced by an habitus.It also notes the
anxious perfectionism in middle class speech, with
its fears of breaking etiquette]
These important modalities of
language are not picked up in the usual empirical
research. [Note 16
says that modality is all important even though it
looks trifling and is hard to research.The example given is the
difference between real left wing commitment and
that which is produced by disenchantment with
right wing positions]. They
are hinted at in things such as vocabulary tests.[One intriguing example
relates the different performance in tests where
students had to define imaginary words.Middle class students
were much better at it, but also revealed the
suspicious ‘off handedness’ of the approach—the
dark side of the deep approach for me.They had to define
‘gerography’, an imaginary term.Middle class students examined the possible
linguistic roots of this term to come up with the
definition, showing their classic ‘desire to “do
one’s best”, to make use of one’s knowledge within
the bounds of scholastic prudence', note 18, 135.
In other words they can bullshit about anything
while guarding their backs].
Similar social signs are used
to judge oral exams, including the modality of
language use, ‘bearing, gesture, dress, make up
and mimicry’, all of which allude to the all-
important social ‘relation to the teacher and to
the situation’ (118).Manners
contaminate all practice.It
is important to demonstrate natural ease, casual
delivery, and ‘stylistic understatement…suggesting, by the
tempering applied to the temptation to speak too
well, the potential excellence of one’s speech’
(119).It is
important never to be too presentational, which
will only lead to a suspicion of ‘self interested
vulgarity’ (119).Far
better to adhere to the fiction of an exchange
with one’s assessors.
People acquire scholarly
language by encountering scholastic work, but for
the bourgeois, there is already a degree of
‘insensible familiarisation’ (119).Only those enjoying this situation can
fully produce ‘the practical mastery of language
and culture that authorises cultivated allusion
and cultured complicity’ (119).For working class kids, school and its
language appears unreal.In
academic life, oral transmission and the
manipulation of words is central.This explains the predominance of lectures
rather than workshops, and the ‘extreme difficulty
of obtaining access to the tools of self teaching’
(120).Academic
speech is dominated by stylistic conventions.It is good to ‘talk like
a book’ (120).Academic
speech
presupposes access to legitimate culture ‘at every
point’ (120).
Professors speak rather than
assess or mark.Underlings
mark, and then have to submit to the ‘sovereign
power of the examining board’ (120).Pedagogical speech is the best way to adapt
to the institutional conditions.It enables a demonstration of virtuosity,
especially in the open lecture [apparently given
on a series of topics, which may fall under
subject expertise or not, and with a very diverse
audience—a particular requirement for effortless
and confident talk, of the kind demonstrated
beautifully by the YouTube videos of Derrida
or Lacan].Professors use academic
speech to situate themselves and their
intellectual field.It
is admitted that such speech can also be
economical [for those in the know who can
recognise the allusions].Academic
speech can also be recorded, but performance is
primary.There is
also considerable scope for self justification:
the ‘demands of didactic clarity dispense it from
the meticulousness of erudite references, the
appearance of erudition dispenses it from the
original research, and the appearance of creative
improvisation can in any case dispense it from
both clarity and erudition’ (122).In this way, displays of professorial
charisma even convey a claim to supersede everyone
else’s works!
The style is often imitated by
non professorial intellectuals, as in ‘Parisian
style culture…An
insubstantial structure [based on] brief
encounters with authors, their works, and those
who talk about both, or through weekly
consultation of the gazettes of the intellectual
Demi Monde’ (123).Such
culture features ‘all embracing taxonomies’ [not
the first echo of current educational theory!].The style applies also
to ‘econometrics, computer science, operational
research, or the latest thing in structuralism’
(123) [some really waspish examples on page 123!].
Academic discourse is all about
prestige and self esteem, but it is supported by
strong social functions, which lend it authority.There is a social and
economic need for some recognition that people
have actually learned something [ a credential],
even if it is only a sense of recognition of
obscure words, or passing familiarity with the
classic authors.This
social authority is deflected on to pedagogues
themselves, thus ensuing maximum ‘resources and
zeal’ devoted to this task (124).This explains the necessary identification
of professors with performance, in the dramatic
aspects of their role.It
is necessary to exalt their profession.Good performers can
dispense with official props and protections, and
emphasise their unique qualities [as in Goffman on
role distance?] Charismatic feats include ‘verbal
acrobatics, hermetic allusion, disconcerting
references, or peremptory obscurity…technical tricks...such
as the concealment of sources, the insertion of
studied jokes…the
avoidance of compromising formulations [which
might prove to be wrong]’ (125).There is often a surface disrespect for
conventions, but an affirmation of the value of
academic discourse by transferring personal
prestige and virtuosity on to it.This includes ‘taking liberties with the
syllabus that implicitly are on the syllabus’
(125).Cultivating
relations to the teacher leads to support for the
academic institution, and thence to a ‘relation to
language and culture which is none other than that
of the dominant classes’ (125).This is the ‘ruse of academic reason’,
where the institution persuades teachers to serve
their interests by making it individually
rewarding.Social
conservation is served here, even if ‘academic
reason cannot recognise [it]’ (125).Individual freedom guarantees that the
teacher serves the system, the freedom of the
educational system guarantees service to class
relations.The system
‘never better fulfils the social function than
when it seems to be exclusively pursuing its own
ends’ (126) [exactly the focus of the famous
critique of the autonomous news industry in Policing
the Crisis…, but this predates it by a
decade, and typically is fearlessly focused on our
own institution, rather than taking the easy route
of conveniently exposing ideology in other
institutions].
You can see the constraints on
what can be done if you imagine the alternatives.Imagine teaching
‘stripped of all indulgences…and traditional complexities…[without falling into the idea of]... a
perfectly explicit pedagogy’ (126).Perhaps we can at least minimise the
effects of the academic code ‘by continuously and
methodically stating [it]’ (126), a more promising
alternative than trying to sidestep the code
altogether with a simulated clarity.We can reduce the differences between
teacher and taught at both the production and the
reception ends.We
can give the message and the code which helps
people decipher it, or insist on familiar modes of
expression, or even stratify academic production,
introducing students first then preparing them for
the next stage, in order that they can gradually
possess the academic code.We
need to recognise the effects of the code and its
social roots and function.We
should be studying the acquisition of codes rather
than looking for individual conversions.We need to put pedagogy
first.Teachers
should be differentiated according to their
specialisms rather than in some kind of academic
hierarchy.We need to
make the school survey other social functions.The current system
imposes one code and therefore rewards those
closest to it.We
need to recognise that the relation to culture is
the issue.Academic
denial of this relation, together with its
disavowal of anything scholastic or pedagogic only
shows its ‘dependence on class relations’ (128).
Traditional pedagogy is seen as
a practice in itself, and is probably unable to
recalculate the best mean to achieve its official
ends.Depreciation of
pedagogy, the cult of the amateur, both show that
its contradictions cannot be recognized.Academic institutions
cannot repudiate pedagogy altogether, since they
are expected to do it, but nor can they confirm
it, because this would seem to threaten their
traditions and autonomy.They
therefore develop ‘academic anti-academicism’
(129).This is as
paradoxical and as unnoticed as giving a lecture
on creativity, or combining school routine with
the notion of giftedness.However,
schools must be conservative, they must serve the
pedagogic interests of the dominant class who need
the university to legitimate their relation to
culture.
The arbitrary nature of
university pedagogy can be seen from historical
and other comparisons—with the Jesuits or the Ming
Chinese.However, our
system has important current functions as well,
involving the necessary relation to the dominant
classes.For example
the culture of the ‘literary gentleman’ still
persists in the value given to manners and style,
in the way that ‘naturalness and lightness [are
contrasted to] pedantry, didacticism or effort’.There is a contempt for
study, where progress is explained as a matter of
gift or birth, a disdain for specialisation as
mere ‘trade’.‘Manner,
nuance, refinement, literary culture and then
artistic culture’ are still more conducive to ‘the
indefinite niceties of the games of distinction’
(130).Academics
spend a lot of effort opposing the vulgarity of
achievement, and therefore support the idea that
there is only one legitimate mode of acquisition.
The
examination within the structure and history of
the education system
Examinations are dominant and
stressful, yet they are also ‘the clearest
expression of academic values and of the education
system’s implicit demands’ (142).They inculcate the dominant culture.For example, the French
dissertation ‘defines and diffuses the rules of
writing and composition’ (142) which are
widespread, for example in the ‘administrative
report, a doctoral thesis or a literary essay’
(143).It is just
like the Medieval disputatio, or the ‘British
university essay whose rules are not so different
from those of the literary genre of the same name
and in which the subject must be approached with
wit and a light touch’ (143) [long ago!] .‘Brio and brilliance’
are more important for the French style, ‘a style
free from all familiarity or personal comment’
(143).Such
assignments are prototypes for pedagogy and
intellectual ambition rather than signs of a
national character.The
French System emphasises form and produces the concours as
the major form of examination, where ‘young men
who know how to amuse the audience and their
judges and who, although their glib tongues will
get them out of trouble, have neither patience nor
firmness enough to teach well’ [a quote from
Renan] (143).These
ties explain the social significance and heated
debate about changing forms of assessment [compare
with the debates about assessment in the UK,
especially the ‘gold standard’ of the A level.Curiously, much more
innovation is now permitted at university level,
although the standard essay, exam and dissertation
still seem common].
We need a comparative study to
sort out the ‘generic tendencies’ arising from the
need to inculcate, and particular traditions and
social functions ‘never completely reducible to
the technical function of communication –
producing skills’ (144).Durkheim
argued that examinations arose from the need to
reproduce the university, while Weber argued that
they were needed to rationalise access to careers.They also clearly
satisfy the ‘the petty bourgeois ideal of formal
equality’ (145) [which would be a Marxist
insight?].All these
are right, but the education system has its own
logic too.This
‘retranslates’ external demands systematically
according to its own principles.The university is especially ‘directly
dependent on…[Its]…own past because of the
particular form of its relative autonomy’ (145)
[that is it needs to reproduce itself as well as
the wider society].The
French system seems the most independent from the
economy, but has the greater emphasis on
examinations [Lyotard
says that Napoleon's reform of the French
University system made it much more tightly tied
to political, administrative and military
systems].As Weber
argued, the Confucian education system used
literary prowess to produce a selection system,
with frequent exams and the system of three levels
of degree.The
similarities with the French system show the
continuing effects of this emphasis on selection,
and the role of the university in selecting
particular qualities and qualifications to meet
system needs.
The ability of the French
system to maximize this role arises from its
relative autonomy and its ability to retranslate
and reinterpret external demands.It has managed a near monopoly of academic
values as the ‘official principle of every social
hierarchy and every hierarchy of values’ (147).Class values vary
according to the degree of linkage with class
interests and academic values, and market value
and the social position obtainable from
credentials.There is
certainly no valid rival principle of academic
selection [this notion of a tight credentialist
bond is still in dispute in British work on social mobility,
however].There is a
convergence of interests.Senior
university personnel define meritocracy as a
matter of reward according to school rank, while
the aristocracy still maintain a belief in
university values and the moral right of the
university.Universities
enshrined competition in the form of exams which
then produce rationalised hierarchies ‘based on
the imponderables of derisory quarter points’
(148) [idiotic percentages for the British
system].These
results are taken very seriously.There is actually no rational connection
between the contents of the syllabus and any
notion of [transferable] merit, any more than
there was in the Mandarin system, which tested
knowledge of poetry in order to allow access to
senior positions in the civil service.However, the Jesuits
were among the first to classify and translate
aristocratic ‘glory’ into scholastic success
(149).
Historical precedence is
important but so is the current functioning of the
selection system.First
and foremost, it is about ‘self perpetuation and
self protection of the teaching corps’ (149).It is this self
perpetuation that produces a drive towards
relative autonomy.This
interest is allied with those of the petty
bourgeois and bourgeois intellectuals to produce a
preferred pattern of formal equality as the main
principle of selection rather than nepotism or
favouritism.Universities
took advantage of a new centralised state
bureaucracy to introduce a national system of
examinations.The
competition to recruit teachers [the concours?Or is it the aggrégation?]
is the archetype of all examinations.Qualifications achieved
value in vocational terms [what a nice way to put
it, instead of the usual view that it was the
other way around!], often where credentials began
as unofficial criteria (150).These were sometimes idealised as
indicating some universal standard, and maintained
even if insufficient numbers of candidates to fill
positions were available!Examinations
like this were always the most socially
significant form of activity [because they
reproduced universities themselves], more so than
the doctorate.The
same exam can take on quite different meanings.There is a constant
maintenance of interest in reproduction as the
main thread, though, an example of the
university’s opportunistic ‘power to select and
reinterpret accidents and influences in accordance
with…general
principles’ (152) [a great description of the
current adaptation of government interests in
vocational qualifications, work based learning and
the like].Here, the
role of specialists is crucial, who are able to
systematize accidental elements.
However, the university is not
that autonomous and has to discharge social
functions too.Academic
hierarchies look rational, but they help to
support social hierarchies.University
autonomy is the ‘quid
pro quo of the hidden services it renders
to certain social classes by concealing social
relations under the guise of technical selection’
(153).
In practice, universities
exclude most candidates before exams are even
taken [before massification, obviously].This is selection by
social class.Your
chances of entering university is more affected by
your class than your chances of passing exams when
you get there.Working
class candidates eliminate themselves, or get
sidetracked [this is the British system, like the
community college American system].All this is hidden by a focus on
examinations as selection, including studies of
the characteristics of those who passed or failed
[docimology!],
nor is it picked up by conventional sociological
work on the differences between those who enter
and those who complete universities, which ignores
dropout between the stages.So
the scandals about pass rates are misleading, an
obsession only for those ‘for whom the risk of
elimination can only come from the examination’
(154).
These effects are missed by
work on ‘wastage of talent’ with their emphasis on
apparent lack of motivation, and by much work on
formal educational opportunity.Social origin classically appears as a
technical disadvantage, and this is missed by
those who see social inequalities themselves as
responsible for disadvantage without seeing how
the education system itself transforms social into
educational disadvantages.The
same goes for the more technical focus on exam
performance, such as work on normalising marks, or
on changes in teacher-pupil relations, especially
advocates of ‘democratisation’ (155).All these factors focus
on individuals not classes.Individuals
are persuaded to drop out, for example, by seeing
themselves as having inability, but this must be
understood within the whole ‘ensemble of objective
relations…between
his social class and the education system…the objective and
collective future of his class’ (155).These produce
‘dispositions towards education, and towards
upgrading through education’ (156).Objective probabilities of success
therefore really express something which is
understood better as a theoretical
construction—how subjective expectations are
formed (156).Agents
‘always, albeit unwittingly, make reference to the
objective relations which make up their situation’
(156).This explains
drop out and explains regional variations.It also explains a
common reaction on the part of working class
students toward University – ‘”That is not for the
likes of us”’ (157).
Courses in science are not more
democratic, despite depending less on cultural
capital.Language and
cultural differences are at work throughout the
education system.The
mastery of language already influences ‘logical
and symbolic mastery of abstract operations and…mastery of the laws of
transformation of complex structures’ (157), and
children who lack that mastery are already cooled
out.Even science has
its own hierarchies, ranging from pure maths at
the top to the more applied natural sciences, from
abstract to concrete work. Academic hierarchies
are translated into types of secondary school,
then into hierarchies of universities, with a
hierarchy of teacher origins to match.Recruitment to those at
the top depend on academic success, but working
class access has already been diverted into
‘school careers which entice them with the false
pretences of apparent homogeneity only to ensnare
them in a truncated educational destiny’ (158) [
such as the vocational route in the UK? That old
notion of formal parity of esteem is still as
bankrupt as ever?].
Social class origin plus uneven
career possibilities ‘transmute a social
inequality into a specifically educational
inequality’ (158).Would
a more democratic intake prevent this?There would still be an
elite strand in France.Elimination
would be deferred only: people would now be
exposed to elimination ‘by exam alone’ (159).There would be concealed
selection, with greater chances seen as the profit
to match educational wastage—‘the advantage the
social order derives from spacing out and so
concealing the elimination of the working class’
(159).[This seems
like a good critical account of the policy to replace
sponsored mobility with contest mobility, to use
the terms favoured by British theorists and
politicians.That in
turn was based on work on social mobility in the
USA, with its more contest system and community
college network.Both
were seen perceptively by Hopper
as ways of solving the functional dilemmas of
modern social systems, needing to both warm up the
talented and cool out those with high expectations
but lesser talents].
These insights explain the
emphasis on the examination as a whole ‘moment of
truth’ [other work also emphasisies its ritual
value] .Exams help
to both eliminate people and also conceal a much
wider process of exclusion.There
is a methodological implication.The ‘mechanical use of multivariate
analysis [misleads]’ (160), because it is the
primary relation between social class and success
that varies according to the type of secondary
training in education.Social
advantages and disadvantages have already been
translated and relayed.We
need to examine whole careers, to explain the
occasional absurd and unusual relation between
social origins and educational success, a result
of the ‘compounding of improbabilities’ explaining
success only for groups that already have been
heavily selected.It
is a combination of unequal selectedness and the
different expectations they produce that is
responsible for the different categories of
students found at university in class terms.This is missed by a
‘purely synchronic approach’ (161), which
calculates probabilities there and then, deals
with abstract probabilities rather than
conditional probabilities.Such
an approach cannot explain dispositions either:
these are not just abstract attitudes or
characteristics such as the lack of self
assurance, but social identities (161).The underlying habitus
is the ‘generative, unifying principle of conduct
and opinions…[which]…reproduces the system of
objective conditions of which it is the product’
(161).
So we need to break with
‘spontaneous sociology’ and with the narrow focus
on examinations and their characteristics.We need to look at all
the mechanisms of elimination.The examination merely legitimates
‘academic verdicts and social hierarchies’ (162).Those who pass are seen
as gifted, and examinations are seen as the only
selection mechanism.
Examiners’ judgments also
‘retranslate and specify the values of the
dominant classes in terms of the logic proper to
the education system...Class
bias [is] strongest [where it is] implicit [with]
diffuse criteria…such
as the dissertation or the oral, an occasion for
passing total judgments armed with the unconscious
criteria of social perception on total persons,
whose moral and intellectual qualities are grasped
through the infinitesimals of style or manners,
accent or elocution, posture or mimicry, even
clothing and cosmetics...or
bourgeois ease and distinction, or universal tone
or breeding’ (162).Only
a sustained ‘experimental decomposition of the
examiners’ syncretic judgement’ can reveal the
influence of social judgments.
Insisting on formal criteria
alone will not prevent the influence of these
judgments.Specialists
note that markers are often unable to agree on
using the criteria, but they never examine
agreement based on implicit criteria!The irrationality and
inconsistencies of selection arise from social
functions rather than from the characteristics of
grading systems themselves.Compare
with the scepticism that academics directed
towards other scientific measures, such as
aptitude tests, where it is acknowledged that
aptitude is often a product of past teaching and
learning!It is
absurd for systems like the USA to place even more
faith in assessment.Critics
of meritocracy, on the other hand, are simply
insisting on preserving the rights of traditional
examinations to select [I think].
The skills agenda seems to
restrict university autonomy, but universities
still preserve their social function—the ‘certification effect’
(165).Even if tests
were entirely technocratic, the education system
would still produce a scarcity of diplomates.Diplomas clearly affect
employment rather than skills and affect the
position obtainable inside the company.Different schools still
have different prestige despite their apparently
equal expertise.The
academic value of qualifications persists—the
general value of a diploma prevents questions
about specific contents which would therefore
threaten the whole system.The
selection function is still more important than
the skills content.This
is covered by the ideology of a ‘general culture’
and a denial that cultivated people also need
proof of their technical abilities.Ideology values an indefinable relation to
culture, which produces a maximum returns to
diplomas themselves.This
explains the persistence of ‘classical languages…humanism, or the
complacent drilling in every sort of formalism,
literary, aesthetic, logical or mathematical’
(166).
So examinations have a dual
technical and social function.Only universities can manage dualisms and
translate results into diplomas, then make
diplomas essential for entry into the professions.
Weber was wrong to see the possession of purely
technical expertise as the secret of bureaucracy.In practice, French
civil servants at the top of the hierarchy tend to
be the most generally educated.
Surrendering this
credentialising power to universities makes the
action of universities seem neutral, and seemingly
to be renouncing hereditary privilege, but
universities reproduce privileged nonetheless.Universities just seem
democratic.Some
limited social mobility is permitted, and this
further stabilizes the system.
Chapter
four
Dependence Through Independence
The education system displays a
dual truth [an analogy has just struck me – this
is exactly like recent criticisms of Sport England
which claim that the public emphasis on
participation and sports for all has quietly
shifted towards the implicit policy of selecting
elite athletes for future competitions].There is an internal
logic and an external function.We need to look closely at how this system
emerged: it is neither fully independent nor
economically determined.Instead,
relative
autonomy for the sector means that the external
functions are discharged ‘under the guise of
independence and neutrality’ (178).The nature of the external function varies
according to the relations between the social
classes at a given moment.Again,
this is unlikely to appear from simple empirical
synchronic analysis, nor from the conventional
forms of economic determinism, nor from some
functionalist notion of a common culture
transmitted by education.The
simplistic economic analysis produces abstract
statistics on performance and wastage, for
example, but we need to see how the value of
occupational hierarchies actually relate to the
organisation of the education system.We need a model
describing transformations in the relations
between functions and the structure of
organisations.In
practice, this always depends on the balance of
power between the social classes.
The aims of education are now
fully equated with economic growth, even when
discussing the expansion of educational
opportunity.It is
really a question about what is objectively
possible.Technocrats
see the history of education as a unilinear model
of change, and develop a universal yardstick to
assess different societies.The
abstraction of variables such as literacy rates,
the amount of discrimination by sex and so on need
to be read contextualised in the whole system of
relations.A fully
rational system therefore for technocrats is one
which has the lowest costs for the maximum output
of needed skills, the most effective pedagogy and
recruitment policies respond to merit, and there
is a focus on ‘made to measure specialists’ (181)
[as in recent UK government pressures on
universities to turn out workers for a knowledge
economy, or more scientists and technologists
generally].However,
date or like the actual number of certificate
holders produced by a given system only make sense
when we consider additional factors such as market
scarcity, and the workings of ‘symbolic
market’ as well.Thus
in some countries, possessing a certificate of
literacy is enough to guarantee a good job.Similarly, rates of
femninisation may well be signs of growing
economic rationality, or any indication of the
development in the reproduction of division of
labour between the sexes, where education is just
seen as good upbringing for a female.Western countries still
show definite patterns of ‘choice of discipline
and the rate of vocational use of diplomas’ for
their women (182), and this feeds back to
subsequent attitudes.Lower
rates of female entry into university might be a
better sign of modernization, as in Muslim
countries where there had been no enrolment at all
previously.Access
alone does not mean equality of the sexes anyway.Finally, occupations
also vary according to their value, and this value
could ‘steadily diminish as it is feminized’
(183).
Wastage rates also need
interpretation.They
reflect both their social and technical or
educational selection.Wastage
rates do have a transformative effect, for example
when failure leads to changed dispositions towards
education and occupations (183).[precisely as I’ve tried to argue with the
effects of failure for open university students,
who feel that they really must be thick if even an
open university can’t teach them properly].Wastage rates also vary
according to the degree of selection in the first
place and this process itself varies, with simple
exclusion in France compared to the gentler
‘cooling out’ in the USA [ they use this actual
phrase, 183].High
wastage rates might indicate low technical
efficiency, but a close connection in legitimating
the social order, and a form of profit on cultural
capital for the successful ones.
So the education system
represents ‘the general interest’ as well as
‘specialist ones’ (184).This
shows the connection between the education system
and the social system through the ‘mediation of
class ethos, the principal determining the level
of occupational aspiration’ (184).[this is really getting quite socially
determinist!].It is
this rather than some rational mechanical link
between the supply of labour and demand that
connects universities to the economic system.The system itself
affects the ‘needs’ of individuals and the labour
market.The education
system is never simply a means to supply skilled
labour but has ideological functions as well.‘Unproductive’ elements
of the education system [non vocational subjects]
are explicable in terms of their wider social
function in helping to articulate school and class
values.The class
relations are missed by a technocratic analysis [a
kind of critique of positivism in the Marxist
sense, where analysts first of all abstract the
economic system from class relations, then see
demand for skills to some independent factor split
from class relations, and then go on to discover
the technical function of the school, failing to
examine its reproductive function].The whole system is glossed by ‘an idealism
of the “general interest”’… a ‘pan econometric
monism’ (186).Critics
are condemned for offering only ‘negative
sociology which…Can
see only failures and shortcomings’…And ‘pedagogic specificity and historical
particularity’ are ignored (186).
We need to capture some notion
of the originality of educational culture ‘like
the configurationist school’ (186).However for them, culture is too
independent, merely expressing some ‘generative
formula, a “spirit of the age” or “national
character”’ (187).For
that school, each subsystem is also an expression
of this principle, leading to a ‘philosophy of
totality which sees the whole in every part’ (187)
[compare this with the Althusserian criticisms of
expressive totality in Lukacs].This ignores how the system comes to
discharge particular functions within its overall
structure: education does not just expressed
national values [the authors criticised here
include those who see educational groups as
prototype communities or as expressions of ‘la
France éternelle’ (187).They
actually read a bit like Parsons on the functions
of the school system in introducing children to
the wider values of democratic (but American)
society].There is no
notion of pedagogy as ‘reproducing the structure
of relations between classes by reproducing the
unequal class distribution of cultural capital’
(188) which leads them into ‘unexplained
homologies, inexplicable correspondences’ which
they grasp through a ‘leap of pure intuition’
(188).
In fact schools have ‘the
essential function of inculcating a cultural
arbitrary’ in specific historical circumstances
(188).So the
emphasis on giftedness and charisma is not just a
vestige of aristocratic values, but secures
legitimacy for pedagogy at current universities.The specifics of these
beliefs very according to the position of the
agents who hold them, whether they are for example
‘teachers and students, higher education or
secondary education staff, Arts students or
Science students’ (188), and how the classes
relate.This is
usually denied in favour of developing historical
abstractions and some supposed continuity of
cultural themes, the ‘vicious circle of thematic
analysis’ (189).One
example here is Crozier’s work on bureaucracy: he
adds some cultural specifics in order to avoid
technological determinism, but it is still an
expressive totality.It
is also reductionist since abstract principles of
bureaucracy are deployed.However,
routinization and the use of production manuals,
for example, is common in non bureaucratic schools
like Koran schools; we find charisma in the
classical Greek schools and in Zen ‘disconcertion
techniques’ (119).It
is simply a matter of maintaining pedagogical
authority. University
autonomy similarly is based on both legal
exemptions and claims to be able to interpret the
demands of society, together with an ‘ideology of
“mastery”’ (191).
The education system has
differential functions according to differential
relations between parts of the system, not
universal principles.For
example the values of meritocrats come from their
class position as well as their educational
background.Class
dispositions include a characteristic feature of
the elite of the grandes ecoles—a ‘distance from
role, a flight into abstraction’ [another
description of deep learning?], typical of the
dominant classes.An
emphasis on ‘probity and meticulousness together
with a propensity towards moral indignation’ is
clearly associated with the sort of bureaucratic
career typical of petty bourgeois.Meanwhile, the middle rank of students and
teachers exhibit ‘cultural willingness or esteem
for hard work’, a typical combination of middle
class ethos and scholastic values.It is these dispositions that are the
source of homologies between class and educational
characteristics [possibly with class relations as
the ultimate determinant].
Holistic philosophies are also
clearly ideological [the target here are people
developing philosophies involving
‘”homogenisation”, “massification”, or
“globalization”’ (192)].They
display ‘silences and reticences, denials and
slips, or, conversely, displacements and
transfers’.Their
obedience to intellectual conventions [abstraction
and idealisation?] means obedience to dominant
ideology (193).Class
relations are decried as a solecism,
provincialism: they are seekers of trends in
modernity, hoping to find new classes. They deal in platitudes.This stances even found
in advocates of class struggle, where, even here,
allegiance to intellectual values outweigh their
[adopted] class values [exactly what happened in
designer Marxism, with its curious susceptibility
to philosophical fashion and argument].
Radical critics of the
education system may well be in to ‘contestation’,
but this is often based on a notion of a general
frustration inherent in all socialization [which
is what lies behind ‘struggling man’ in appalling
anthropologies like Fay’s].These
people seem unaware that frustrations like this
bear differentially on the different social
classes.Instead,
they denounce all pedagogic action as repression
(193).They deal with
abstract ‘generic alienations, spuriously
specified by tragic reference to “modernity”’
(194).They see
nothing specific to the education system, no
notion of relative autonomy [note that N15, page
213, singles out those specializing in youth, all
those blaming the mass media and general
consumerism].
So what sort of theoretical
model would be adequate?How
do schools achieve relative autonomy, balancing
pedagogical and social functions?How concealed is their ideology?Simple class analysis is
clearly seen as flawed because it is too
‘instrumentalist’ [presumably in the sense that
Poulantzas wants to take on Miliband on how to
analyse the class nature of the state] (195).Analysing the education
system should not be limited by the assumption
that education is itself neutral, but simple class
reductionism for all the elements in it is too
convenient.Relative
autonomy is important, but we need an analysis to
show the social functions nonetheless, just as we
do with the state.Durkheim
saw the relative autonomy of the education system
in terms of its power to translate external
demands and to take opportunities to deepen its
role [in his analysis of the evolution of French
pedagogy—still in French?].Pedagogic
work does produce ‘durable, transposable training
(habitus)’ (196) [so it is not just early
socialisation in social classes then?], and these
are then reproduced, especially since the
education system is permitted to select new
recruits as teachers of university values.It is this that produces
relative autonomy.But
Durkheim was unable to see factors other than
educational history itself as responsible.
Objective conditions are also
important, especially class relations.Universities are both
autonomous and dependent ‘in the last instance, on
the structure of class relations’ (197).Schools are conservative
because this helps social conservation
[reproduction].Cultural
conservation is analysed by Durkheim as central,
but this is only one specific combination of two
functions.Socially
conservative periods leads to pedagogical
conservatism as their best ally.A perfect connection would offer an
‘illusion of complete autonomy’ (198), and
universities would be able to concentrate simply
on their own reproduction, because the
reproduction of the social order would be
automatic.This would
explain considerable support for educational
traditions [in this period] such as the teaching
of Latin, literary culture and the humanities,
from the ‘most conservative factions of the
dominant classes’ (199).University
interests
are the interests of the social order, and they
reproduce hereditary transmission of cultural
capital and conceal their social functions
underneath absolute autonomy.In this sense they are ‘masterpieces of
ideology’ (201).
In other periods the two
functions can be actually contradictory, and the
‘lordly contempt for the laboured virtues of the
intellectual worker [itself aristocratic]…Can be allied with…punctilious defence of
status rights, even against the right of
competence’ (202), producing a characteristic anti
academicsm, a celebration of ‘brilliance without
originality, and heaviness without scientific
weight’ (202).Universities
are able to promote ‘ethical justification by
merit’ (202).This
sort of tension really arises from relations
‘between the petty and the grand bourgeoisie’
locked in an ‘antagonistic alliance’ (202).The role of the petty
bourgeois especially is to serve in the middle
against both classes [N27, page 216, refers to
classic middlemen like NCOs or foremen and notes
that people gain charisma by disparaging them].
So, we need to trace both
internal and external functions.There is no need to assume any sort of
harmony or homology.It
is a matter of interests and alliances, various
‘affinities of habitus’, demonstrated throughout
this book.Those
relations which produce actual structures, and the
practices which exemplify them, need to be
studied.We need
empirical work here rather than either
‘pan-structuralism or humanism’.For example the best way at the moment to
‘serve the pedagogic interests of the dominant
class’ is ‘pedagogic laissez faire’ (206) [which
means the current disdain for any attempts to
modernise pedagogy or to criticise it].
Education is not reducible to
indoctrination.The
varied disdain towards indoctrination helps the
ideological function, covered by claiming
neutrality or even hostility to the state.The claim here is that
the education system alone is able to create order
[not far from the squeals about funding cuts from
university vice chancellors in the UK]. The state
must recognise the legitimacy of the education
system, but this power relation misrecognises the
social role of the education system [I think—there
is some dreadful writing on page 206, and see
below].Sociologists
themselves are not immune from this
misrecognition—the objective conditions of
universities also affect their aspirations and
lead two rather uncritical analysis and defence of
the education system, seen for example in support
for recruitment policies excluding even talented
members of the working class.The ideology here is that the social order
‘refuses to hurt them [working class students] by
calling them to overambitious destinies as little
suited to their abilities as to their aspirations’
(207) [the same used to be said of married women
with children at my college].
The new optimistic philosophers
simply see social order is natural.They just assume social reproduction.Selection appears as
necessary, even expressing some personal choice.This is better than
standard theodicy, since the whole system is
legitimated.Very
rational selection systems are seen to be best
[compare with the highly paternalistic and highly
developed selection system at the UK open
university].The
denial of class bias, and the devising of new
systems of selection would only be a waste of time
and money.In
practice, schools certify people through an
‘ostentatious and sometimes hyperbolic length of
apprenticeship’ (209).Delayed
selection [contest mobility] is similarly used to
convince the excluded that they are right to be
excluded, it is merely a more soft approach (209),
as in cooling out [my term this time].However, the system is
quite prepared to develop new techniques to
exclude people if self elimination tapers off.
Schools are in the business of
naturalising social inequality.Straightforward hereditary principles are
unpopular with the bourgeoisie, and so is simple
enterprise.Certification
and credentialism, giving more power to the
school, is a more ‘discrete succession…a bourgeois sociodicy’
(210). Those eliminated are persuaded that it is
their fault because they lacked gifts.If it works well,
‘absolute disposition excludes the awareness of
being dispossessed’ (210).
[This is a really difficult
read.I have done you
a great favour, O reader of this file!The writing just gets
more and more obscure throughout this chapter.Let me give you just one
example, on page 206:
Legitimation of the established
order by the School presupposes social recognition
of the legitimacy of the School, a recognition
resting in turn on misrecognition of the
delegation of authority which establishes that
legitimacy, or, more precisely, in misrecognition
of the social conditions of a harmony between
structures and habitus sufficiently perfect to
engender misrecognition of the habitus as a
product reproducing what produces it, and
correlative recognition of the structure of the
order thus reproduced
Appendix:
The
Changing Structure of Higher Education
Opportunities: Redistribution or Translation
Democratisation of the system
is being discussed in a very ideological way.There is still a great
deal of hesitation in measuring the social class
of students, and lots of variation in the way this
is done an official statistics.These display the usual problems, in
ignoring the effects of selection in a career as
well as origin as such.We
need to see what percentage of university entrance
are really survivors of selection, and how this
varies according to social origins.We need to look at relations rather than
single attributes.Thus
it avoids the naivety of, say, celebrating the
numbers of working class students in science, as
above.It is
especially important to measure this at different
periods, since disciplines and social categories
change despite their ‘identity of names’ (232).By contrast, relations between the
classes persist.
So will expansion lead to real
democratisation?They
can still be a perpetuation of the status quo, or
even a decline in class chances.For example by increased representation of
older students rewards more schooling [in France].We should be examining
the proportion of different birth cohort to get to
university rather than absolutes.There is been an overall rise in particular
birth cohorts as well as changes in proportions,
so that certain social categories of age are
simply more common in the population.
The table cited on page 225
shows disparities in terms of the likelihood of
access to higher education [for 1961 and 62].For example, the sons of
farm workers have a 1.2% chance of getting to
university, while the son of an industrialist has
a better than even chance.There
has been an increase in the chances of all
categories, but no relative change.The sons of working class groups have
doubled their chances, while those of
industrialists ones’ have risen by only 160%, but
these rates are still very advantageous in
relative terms.An
‘upward translation’ of educational chances has
occurred.What is
needed is to change aspirations, but here,
particular thresholds seem to be at work [you need
to have a particular proportion of the social
group attending university before attitudes
change].Educational
chances affect the social image of university
education.It may be
‘an impossible, possible, probable, normal, or
banal future’ (226), according to the proportions
of each group who go.In
this way, quantitative differences produce
qualitative differences.
Thus the very high rates of
entry to university by industrialists
sons—74%—lead to an experience ‘of the quasi
certainty of higher education’ (226).Those sons are already
over enrolled in suitable forms of preparation,
such as private schools or preparatory classes.The expansion between
1962 and 66 simply ‘consecrated the cultural
privileges of the upper classes’ (227).Education at university
became a typical future.For
working class groups, the increase was still not
enough to normalise university entrance, even
though chances doubled from 2% to 4%.Middle class aspirations
are rising, since
getting the baccalaureate is no longer enough to
secure a good job.We
are witnessing a translation of aspirations again
rather than a radical change.
Gender is an important factor
as well, as is the differential access to the
disciplines.Chances
are not random or proportionate to the university
population, but rather express ‘a systematic
distortion…students
from less well to do origins gravitate towards the
art and science faculties rather than law and
medicine’ (228).So
increases in access overall seem to be combined
with a severe ‘restriction of choice’ (229).This remains despite the
increased likelihood of going to university
overall.Indeed, the
gender gap in terms of choice and discipline has
widened.There has
indeed been a general drift from hearts, but more
so for upper class males.
[So there seems to be a kind of
buffer zone thesis here].Access
has increased, but into a‘ “modern stream”…Objectively situated at
the bottom of the academic hierarchy’ (229).The French working class
has been channelled into science.They have the same chances of studying law,
while the chances of the upper class students in
studying this high status discipline have
increased, and it is the same with medicine.These disciplines lead
to subsequent success ‘both academic and social’
(231).
Thus our overall statistics
need more detailed examination to take into
account hierarchies.There
should not be focused on the individual student.They should examine both
social origin and changes of selection to elite
disciplines.We have
translation rather than a redefinition of
criteria, and thus no challenge the those factors
producing rarity.Expansion
has been neutralised ‘by means of a ramifying
differentiation which conceals its own
hierarchical structure…Artfully
contrived and shrewdly dissimulated gradations
which run from the full recognition of academic
citizenship to the different shades of relegation’
(231).
[Note there is a useful
glossary to explain the terms in the French
education system, including:
Aggrégation—a concours in each
subject to select secondary education teachers
and, in effect, higher education lecturers
Classes
preparatoires—preparatory classes for the concours
of grandes écoles [aka khagne and taupe]
Concours—a national annual
competitive exam for Aggrégation or for a
certificate of suitability for entry to the
teaching profession.Each
grande école has its own.
Concours general—a national
competition for secondary school pupils
Ecole National d’Administration
– a grande école for the civil servants
Ecole Normale Superiore Ulm—the
top Grande Ecole, specializing in arts and
science, taking 50 students per year and leading
to careers and secondary higher education or
research in science
Grandes écoles—seen as the top
of the hierarchy rather than faculties in
universities.They
include the two examples above, the Ecole
Polytechnique, leading to careers in state
administration, and several others including the
Ecole Des Mines, the Ecole Centrale, and ‘Sciences
Po’ (for political science.There
is also the HEC, the Ecole Des Hautes Etudes
Commerciales, specializing in management in
industry and commerce.