Notes on the Bergsonian bits of Deleuze,
G. (1992) Cinema 1.The Movement
Image
Dave Harris
Chapter one: Theses on movement. First
commentary on Bergson
Bergson has three theses on movement, with the
first really acting only as an introduction.
The first thesis says that movement is distinct
from the space covered, 'space covered is past,
movement is present, the act of
covering'(1). However, movement is an
integral part of the whole: we cannot split it up
into static spaces or instance in time, 'immobile
sections', since by themselves, they would never
move. There has to be some movement added,
but the usual notion implies some 'abstract idea
of the succession, of a time which is mechanical,
homogeneous, universal and copied from space,
identical for all movements'. However, there
is another movement which explains this
succession, something which occurs in the interval
between points allocated by mechanical time, 'a
concrete duration', something qualitative.
At first, Bergson saw the cinema as
offering an illusory notion of time, with static
images joined by some abstract [in the mechanist
sense] time provided by the apparatus
itself. This will be false movement.
He saw cinema simply reproducing the natural
perception of movement, something abstract and
mechanical, something 'constant and
universal'(2). However, cinema offers
something else, not just immobile sections, 24
images per second, but some 'intermediate image',
something which gives us movement
immediately. Unlike natural perceptions,
there is nothing to correct the movement of images
[nothing which stabilizes or selects among them as
a result of human intentionality]. The
cinematic image appears 'without conditions', some
immediate 'movement - image', something which is
itself mobile. Bergson had already suggested
this possibility, in Matter
and Memory, in the first chapter [I
rendered it as: The notion of the image
works both ways, to deny both idealism and simple
materialism. We already have the notion of a
relation of movement replacing static binary
divisions.]. Bergson probably 'forgot' this
statement, because the new always takes time to
emerge, as in his view that 'when it began life
was forced to imitate matter' (3). And we
have to remember that in the early days, cinema
was a matter of fixed shots which were immobile,
and the technology did indeed combine cameras with
projectors 'endowed with a uniform abstract
time'. The real breakthrough was in the
development of 'montage, the mobile camera and the
emancipation of the viewpoint, which became
separate from projection'. The shot became a
temporal not a spatial one, and the section itself
mobile. This is what was to support
Bergson's original idea in Matter and Memory
[confirmed in Canales'
book].
The second thesis is found in Creative
Evolution, where the illusions of natural
perception are further analyzed. The
classical conception sees movement as a transition
from one ideal form to another, 'an order of poses
or privileged instants, as in a [classical eg
Greek] dance' (4). However, modern thinking
involves the notion of 'any - instant - whatever',
a series of normal material elements which were
immanent rather than transcendental. Deleuze
gives a number of examples from Kepler, Galileo,
Descartes on movements on a straight line, and
finally Newton and Leibniz
on calculus and 'sections which could be brought
infinitely closer together'. This also had
the effect of seeing time as an independent
variable [that is, a separate quantifiable
variable, not linked to some transcendental motion
of necessary or ideal movement?]. The film
camera has a role in this transformation,
expressing movement between ordinary instants [and
Deleuze says we see this in the films of
Wenders]. What the film camera does, in
Bergson's first thoughts, is to take snapshots
rather than posed photos, and to suggest an equal
distance between them, made possible by a
perforated film and a mechanism to move images at
standard rates. Classical drawing might
still rely on poses, but drawing for animated
cartoons shows figures already forming and being
dissolved 'through the movement of lines and
points taken at any-instant-whatevers of their
course' [the mundane and tedious 'tweens' that
luckily computers now do for you].
You can still find 'privileged instants' in
cinema, such as Eisenstein's films which work with
'certain moments of crisis', 'peaks and shouts'
which come into collision, and which he called
'the"pathetic"' (5). By analogy, we know
that the classic films of galloping horses also
show particular interesting instants, where only
one hoof is on the ground, for example, but these
are best seen as 'remarkable occasions'[as in
Leibniz where remarkable occasions are those
points on a curve where something unusual happens,
amid all the unremarkable points]. These are
also called 'singular points', but they do not
arise because some transcendental principle is
being actualized in a privileged pose, they are
still any-instant-whatevers. The interesting
question is how singular points get produced by
movements among ordinary ones, how 'the
qualitative leap is achieved by the accumulation
of banalities (quantitative process)'(6). In
Eisenstein's terms, the pathetic presupposes the
organic, which organizes the set of
any-instant-whatevers.
So cinema shows movements between
any-instant-whatevers, and this seemed to
contradict the analytic interest in science.
And art seem to be stuck with the notion of some
higher synthesis of movements between privileged
poses or forms. In this sense, cinema was
always ambiguous, neither science nor art.
However, some arts were also getting interested in
any-instant-whatevers, especially dance, and
mime. One cinematic example is Fred
Astaire's '"action dance"' associated with musical
comedy, which takes place in the street or along
the pavement, in other words in
'any-location-whatever'(7). Another example
would be Chaplin developing the 'action - mime'.
Bergson was aware of these developments, but
showed two contradictory ways to think about
them. In the first, we can still see
movement as being something which links static
images, whether these are eternal poses or merely
[temporarily] immobile sections. This
is still flawed, because the elements are thought
of as some abstract self contained whole, in which
everything is already given. However, he
wanted to argue that real movement is something
outside these given wholes, not something that
takes place within a closed system [where possible
movements are already circumscribed]. In the
second thoughts, we insist that even these
predictable movements allude to 'the production of
the new, that is, of the remarkable and the
singular at any one of these moments'. This
is what Bergson wanted to do, including his
project to give even [Einstein's] science a
metaphysics. It follows that a philosophy
might also be developed from art and cinema, that
these media have a role to play in developing this
new way of thinking. This is the second
thesis, which sees cinema as'the organ for
perfecting the new reality' (8).
The third thesis is found in Creative Evolution.
We can describe the instant as 'an immobile
section of movement', but go on to see another
kind o fmovement as 'a mobile section of
duration'. It thus becomes a section of the
whole, something capable of bringing change:
duration 'changes and does not stop changing',
while matter merely moves 'but does not
change'[qualitatively, that is]. Ordinary
movements occur as 'a translation in [ordinary]
space', but those movements also produce
qualitative changes in the whole. In Matter
and Memory, for example we can explain the
movement of an animal between two points
abstractly [as distance covered in a particular
time], but there's also a qualitative dimension,
as when that movement is produced by a search for
food: when the movement is completed, 'what has
changed is not only my state, but the state of the
whole which encompassed [the points] and all that
was between them'. Similarly, the fall of a
body presupposes another one, and results in a
change in the whole 'which encompasses them
both'. Bergson has discovered not just the
translation of a fixed state, but other kinds of
movements 'vibration, radiation'. The
qualities can be seen as 'pure vibrations which
change at the same time as the alleged [self
contained] elements move'(9). There is
another famous example in Creative Evolution
which involves putting sugar in a glass of water
and having to wait until it dissolves [and thus
experience duration]. The point is that a
qualitative change is going on from water to
sugared water, a change in the whole [which was
formally made up of separated sugar and water, and
might also include a glass and a spoon].
Bergson explains the difference between the old
conception of change as a combination of an
immobile section and a movement, while the new
conception has a mobile section related to
qualitative change. That is the proper
representation of reality. The example of
the glass of water certainly adequately represents
subjective reality, but it is also a change in a
objective reality. The mistake that
positivist science makes is to attempt to fully
define the whole [close the system]. The
recurrent failures to do that adequately led
to skepticism [or operationalism, so there is a
good enough closure of the system], but what it
really tells us is that the whole is 'the Open',
and that the Open endures—'its nature is to change
constantly, or to give rise to something new, in
short to endure'. When we experience
duration we can conclude that 'there exists
somewhere a whole which is changing and which is
open somewhere'. It is not surprising that
Bergson explored duration first of all via
consciousness, but later he concluded that
consciousness helps us experience duration only
because it opens itself to the whole, discovers
the opening up of that whole. He goes on to
say that living beings change when they do the
same thing, open themselves to the whole [expose
themselves to something outside a closed
system—this is what drives evolution].
We see the importance of relations, ones which are
external to their terms [that is which are not
predicted in terms of pre specified possibilities
within a closed system]. They are always
linked to the open. They do not belong to
objects or closed sets of objects. They
bring about transformative or qualitative
change. Duration or [philosophical] time
reveals a whole set of relations [or all the
relations in the Open. This is another way
of thinking about the multiplicity, of course,
which contains all the possible relations between
virtual and actuals themselves, and all the ones
within each category].
The whole cannot be considered in terms of sets,
which are always closed. The whole does have
parts, but only 'in a very special sense, since it
cannot be divided without changing qualitatively
at each stage of the division' (10) [just like the
definition of the rhizome
or the multiplicity again]. On the contrary,
the whole shows that sets can never be closed,
must always be kept open, even in the most tenuous
way, always connected to the rest of the
universe. The whole creates itself, 'like
the pure ceaseless becoming which passes through
[specific, actual] states'. This is how it
appears as something spiritual or mental,
something graspable by consciousness, which can
see the inadequacy of abstractions and closed
systems.
Closed sets or systems can be well founded.
The link to the open can be reduced, and this
might even be necessary given particular
organizations of matter and space [and the need to
work with them]. But it is still a mistake
to confuse a set with the whole and to ignore
qualitative change, and we still need to bear in
mind that there are two conceptions of the
relation between movements and time. In
fact, we have three 'levels': sets or closed
systems which can be defined in terms of their
objects or distinct parts; movements as
translation between these objects which modify
their position; the whole which constantly changes
'according to its own relations' (11). Thus
we have two kinds of movement—translation and
duration. Overall, movement relates fixed
elements and systems to duration and vice versa
[duration has the effect of opening up the
systems. It's starting to remind me of Kuhn
on the progress of science, with normal science
being interrupted now and then by something new
from the outside producing a scientific
revolution, although not without a lot of
resistance]. To summarize, in terms that
will guide the rest of the book, Bergson suggests
that: there may be 'instantaneous images...
immobile sections of movement', but also images
which show immobile sections of duration [the
movement-image proper], and also images of
duration and qualitative change, beyond
simple movement, and these are 'time images'.
Chapter four: The movement -
image and its three varieties. Second
commentary on Bergson
Earlier conceptions of movements thought images
were held in consciousness, and movements in
space. The images in consciousness could
only be 'qualitative and without extension' (56),
while movements were only 'extended and
quantitative'. The problem was to move from
one to the other, to explain that movements can
suddenly produce an image as in perception and
conversely that image can produce a movement as in
voluntary action. One answer was to look at
the 'miraculous power' of the brain, but there was
still problems because movement could clearly be
seen already as 'at least a virtual image', while
the image could be seen as possible
movement. The problem really lay in an old
confrontations between materialism and idealism,
with the first seeing consciousness as a matter of
material movements, and the other seeing reality
as produced by pure images in consciousness.
There were also certain new developments external
to philosophy, including the clear role of images
in the material world, and the cinema was a key
development. This duality had to be
overcome, and both Bergson and Husserl attempted
to do this. The alternatives were that
consciousness just is something, or that all
consciousness is consciousness of something,
respectively.
Neither mentioned the cinema, or at least Bergson
did only negatively at first. Sartre ignored
the cinema. Merleau-Ponty attempted a
phenomenology, but like all phenomenology, it took
natural perception as the norm, with images
as 'existential coordinates' which anchor
the knowing subject in the world [intentionality
is the concept I thought of to explain the phrase
that all consciousness is consciousness of
something]. Movement becomes a sensible
form, a gestalt, which organizes the field
in which intention and perception can
operate. This connects with a classical
motion of movement as a matter of poses, although
existential rather than essential ones. The
cinema was not seen as very helpful here, because
it can challenge both the existential anchor of
the subject and the horizon of perception,
offering 'an implicit knowledge and a second
intentionality' (57), unlike the other arts which
can produce something unreal from the real world:
with cinema 'it is the world which becomes its own
image'. This is why the cinema was initially
seen as offering false perceptions, but also as
extending them.
For Bergson, the cinema misrepresents movement,
but this is just the same as natural perception:
both take snapshots of reality. Bergson's
model is not that of natural perception, but of
things that constantly change, 'a flowing-matter
in which no points of anchorage nor center of
reference would be assignable'. Instead,
centres have to be formed and imposed to produce
fixed views, an operation in both natural and
cinematic perception that requires
investigation. However, cinema did offer one
possibility not open to natural perception in this
respect: the latter moves from the 'acentred state
of things to centred perception', but cinema can
do the reverse and show the acentred state of
things itself. Bergson saw at least saw this
possibility [apparently in the first chapter of Matter
and Memory—see my
notes].
We can develop this by thinking of a world [of
cinema] where 'IMAGE=MOVEMENT' (58). We can
initially see the image as the 'set of what
appears', with no interaction with other images,
no mobile section, nothing moving away from the
initial perceived moment. Instead, the image
is 'indistinguishable from its actions and
reactions' [ie a closed set]. However, [and
this is the crucial step] we can also see it as
'universal variation', via Bergson, acting as a
conduit for all the modifications at work in the
entire universe. Although images might seem
to be immobile, they are therefore acting and
reacting at this universal level, with all their
facets and elements reacting. Every atom is
an image like this, with actions and reactions
extended almost infinitely. If we think of our
brains or bodies as images like this that means
they are also open to external images and
movements from the universe. The brain is
not some universal arbiter above images in its
consciousness. Instead 'me, my body, are
rather a set of molecules and atoms which are
constantly renewed'. Even atoms should
really be understood as a set of 'interatomic
influences' [real posthumanism here!]. In
fact, 'matter [is] too hot for one to be able to
distinguish solid bodies in it', and we see only
universal variation, 'universal rippling' with no
centres or other fixed points or dimensions.
'The infinite set of all images constitutes a kind
of plane of immanence' (58-9). When images
exist in themselves on this plane, they constitute
matter, an 'absolute identity of the image and
movement'(59). This identity of image and
movement means that 'the movement image and matter
are identical... The movement-image and
flowing-matter are strictly the same thing'.
The operations are not mechanical, since mechanism
implies closed systems and snapshots ['immobile
instantaneous sections']. These do exist,
but they are 'cut from this universe or on this
plane', something made exterior. By
contrast, 'the plane of immanence is the movement
(the facet of movement) which is established
between the parts of each system and between one
system and another, which crosses them all, stirs
them all up together, and subjects them all to the
condition which prevents them from being
absolutely closed'. It is itself a section
[of pure chaos], but 'a mobile section, a temporal
section or perspective... A bloc of space
time'. The time of movement within it is
also a section of 'all time' [presumably
Aion]. There is an infinite series of these
mobile sections, 'so many presentations of the
plane, corresponding to the succession of
movements in the universe'. This is
machinism as opposed to mere mechanism, and the
material universe, [and note that the material
includes the plane of immanence] is 'the machine
assemblage of movement images'. This is
citing Bergson, and one implication is the famous
one that 'the universe [acts] as cinema in itself,
a metacinema'. Thus have we developed a
theory of cinema from Bergson, although it is
completely different to his own account.
What we're left with is 'images in themselves
which are not for anyone and are not addressed to
anyone'. These are not the same as bodies,
however [too actualised]. Bodies are a
result of our perception and our language which
can assign qualities and actions to them. We
customarily work with a system of nouns,
adjectives and verbs. But action in this
case is not [pure] movement, but rather a more
limited notion involving something which is
directed at some intended result. The same
goes for quality which appears to offer a limited
movement between a state which persists 'whilst
waiting for another to replace it'. Body
confines movements to 'the idea of the
subject... Or of an object which would
submit to it' (60). Again we do find such
images, appearing as action images, affection
images and perception images, but they are
different from movements 'which are called images
in order to distinguish them [for the sake of
convenience] from everything that they have not
yet become'
More positively, we can see that the plane of
immanence 'is entirely made up of Light', and this
light diffuses without resistance or loss [citing
Bergson again -- light for him meant
electromagnetic radiation of all kinds, or the
basis forces of the universe?] ]. Light is
identical to matter as well, and this provides the
identity between image and [real] movement.
Apparently, Bergson was to apply this notion of
movement as light to relativity theory. This
shows his intention to produce a philosophy of
modern science, not an epistemology, but involving
the 'invention of autonomous concepts' which would
fit with the new terms of science. Bergson
wanted to start with a diffusion of light on the
plane of immanence, initially producing movement
images which were only lines or figures of
light. These become apparent only when light
is interrupted, reflected or stopped, say by a
human eye. However, this implies that the
eye 'is [itself] in things, in luminous images in
themselves' [not something separated from the
universe, but a potential so to speak?], and thus
human perception is both interior to the universe
and capable of acting anywhere in it [maybe --
this is difficult]. There is no opposition
of consciousness and things, as in phenomenology
with its notion of consciousness as some kind of
light ray aimed at aspects of the exterior [this
is why we had to talk about light from the
beginning, I assume --everyone used optical
metaphors]. For Bergson, things are already
luminous, consciousness is a part of things which
share the image of light. Consciousness is
not grounded in a particular source of light
giving insight, but is potentially at least
everywhere, itself located on the plane of
immanence and with a particular capacity to stop
or reflect light [I heard echoes of Hegel here and
the role of Spirit, because somehow this is
important for the plane of immanence as
well—incidentally, I think there's a typo on 61
which talks about the capacity to stop light as
something 'which the plate {sic} lacked], anywhere
on the plane. [Deleuze wants to also describe this
capacity as providing a black screen, to link with
that strange stuff about screens, actually white
ones, in ATP].
When humans actually perceive something, they are
picking up one of these opacities, intercepting
light that is being propagated universally.
After this difficult section, Deleuze summarizes:
'the plane of immanence or the plane of matter is:
a set of movement images; a collection of lines or
figures of light; a series of blocs of space
time'(61).
We can only explain actual happenings using the
characteristics or factors already
identified. The first possibility is that an
interval can appear on the plane, 'a gap between
the action and reaction'. An interval
implies a dimension of time. This interval
gives living things or matters their distinctive
characteristics as images. All other images
act and react using all their facets and parts,
but living images receive actions on one facet or
in one part, and, produce reactions on other
parts—they are '"quartered"'. This is a way
of explaining their receptive or sensorial
capacities. What they do is isolate certain
images from all those that might be available in
the universe, and organize these in a more closed
system as perceptions. This is the same
operation as cinematic framing. Similarly,
reactions select elements after an interval and
organize these as new movements. Again the
delay introduces an element of selection and
unpredictability and this is '"action" strictly
speaking'(62). These processes of selection
mean that living images are '"centers of
indetermination"'
When light encounters living images, it becomes
opaque. The reflected image is a
perception. This introduces another system,
a center. Images can be referred in two
ways: to their connections with all the other
images reacting across all facets and parts,
and secondly to their relation to a single image
[the living image] which receives other images and
then reacts to them. It is not the human
brain that is the center of images, because it is
itself a special image. We have to start
with the whole plane of images interacting among
themselves. For Bergson, the brain image
implies 'a highly complex and organized state of
life' (63) [in Matter and Memory,
apparently, before we went on to consider the elan
vital]. All living beings are capable
of inserting intervals of the kind discussed
above, and we can suggest that these intervals
even occurred in the primeval soup at the start of
life, when forms of matter emerged. This
only occurs once the earth, the earthly plane of
immanence has cooled down sufficiently [this is
the basis for DeLanda's
account]. The evolution of solid matter
is accompanied by the 'organization of images in
more and more elaborate perception', corresponding
to the development of more elaborate solids.
The thing and the perception of the thing are
united in the image. These images are
related to two systems of reference: as a thing,
there is a relation to all the other images as
above; as a perception, there is a relation to the
special living image and its selective
activity. Human perceptions select from
things, subtract the aspects which are not
relevant to needs, those needs themselves provided
for by the receptive facets and actions retained
from our own relation to other things. Human
subjectivity is at first subtractive. This
is only possible once the thing itself is
presented as an initially diffuse perception, as
image. Non living things do not subtract
like this, hence the famous statement that 'the
atom perceives infinitely more than we do' (64),
[which might excite fans of Barad].
We can use the term prehension [to refer to this
diffuse perception before human intentionality
provides apprehension, if I remember my
phenomenology]. It follows that there are
objective prehensions that things have of other
things, and subjective prehensions that living
beings have of things.
The interesting thing about cinema is that it does
not just rely on the subjective perceptions.
It can deal with mobile centres and variable
framings, and thus exceed natural perception,
displaying the first system of relations as above,
'universal variation, total, objective and diffuse
perception' (64). It can actually change
between the two, showing both the 'total objective
perception which is indistinguishable from the
thing' and subjective perception which features
elimination or subtraction. When we do this
subjective perception, we have the perception
image as the 'first avatar of the
movement-image'[curious terminology], which begins
to organize by awakening the centre of
indetermination. Once we have a center, we
can organize the universe around it, 'incurve' it,
treat it as a horizon. This also awakens the
possibility for action, which arises after a
delay, as we saw, while things are
organized. The whole thing combines to
provide the sensory motor schema, the connections
between perception and action: perception reveals
certain unstable facets of things and this makes
action possible to use them.
It is possible to experience and understand this
combination that links periphery and center as
both '"virtual"' and '"possible"' action
(65). What actually happens is that the distance
between core and periphery is altered, a spatial
dimension that corresponds to the delay. The
more distant, the more that virtual action is
extracted [virtual here meaning potential,but also
emanating from the unperceived real?]. This
produces the second avatar, the action image which
follows imperceptibly from perception, once the
universe has been incurved. This incurving
allows for possible actions on our behalf and also
'the virtual action of things on us'. This
provides another classic material
[objective] aspect of subjectivity.
Linguistic activity thinks of actions as something
to do with acts or verbs aimed at some assumed
end.
The interval is provided because there are two
'limit-facets', perceptive and active, but there's
also an 'in between', occupied by affection that
connects perceptions and hesitant actions.
It offers a 'coincidence of subject and object',
involving what experience feels like [when
impacted by objects?], as an aspect of
subjectivity. It lends a quality to
movement, as expressed in adjectives. It is
the returning of aspects of the external that had
been selected out by perception, still not
actually perceived subjectively but representing
some pure relation between object and
subject. It is necessary to the whole system
of perception and action, overcoming the apparent
immobility [passivity?] of perception compared to
the necessary activation of action. Affect
'replaces the action which is become momentarily
or locally impossible'(66) [which is what gets the
politics of affect advocates so interested -
affect produces something immediate, before
cognition catches up and has the chance to censor
reaction]. This is why Bergson defines
affection as a motor tendency acting on some
receptive plate which has been [temporarily]
immobilized [Matter and Memory]. Thus
affection reestablishes the relation between
perception and action, making action a form of
expression, not just a mere translation, adding a
quality. Micromovements in the face show
this well. Thus movement-image is divided
into perception images, action images and
affection images, and human subjects are 'nothing
but an assemblage [agencement] of three
images', a consolidation of them.
We can consider this in reverse, seeing how we can
work back from human consolidation of these images
to get to the pure movement-image, before it had a
center. This is what Beckett attempts with Film,
[see the discussion here]
trying to show how humans are perceived and how
they think this demonstrates their essence, their
persisting notion of self. [The film is then
described... We see the character first
acting, moving along walls and up staircases, but
this action image is constrained by certain
conventions of the camera, only showing the
character within particular angles {classic
subjective pov shots?}. The camera takes
different positions to offer both subjective and
objective perceptions, perception images that
combine the double system described above.
The character eliminates all subjective
perceptions by taking away the animals and
mirrors. Here, the restriction of camera
angles supports objective perceptions. In
the last sections, when the character himself sits
before the camera, the total elimination of
subjective perception threatens, amplified by the
removal of restriction on how the camera can move
and show the character. However, each time
it shoots the character from a new angle, he can
wake up and force the camera back to the pov,
until his exhaustion permits the camera to show
him in close up, and the camera itself becomes
identified with the subject, even though the
subject displays anguish. This is 'the
domain of the perception of affection'(67),
showing that when all else is destroyed, only
affection remains, the only thing preventing
subjective death. Yet even subjective death
is not the end point, because Beckett wants to
show 'the world before man... where
movement was... under the regime of
universal variation'(68). He tries to end
with the 'luminous plane of immanence', showing
only matter and movement images, tracing the human
avatars back to the movement-image. Deleuze
says this is a common ambition in experimental
cinema, often using complex technology, but
Beckett simply uses conventions to eliminate human
centered images.]
However, mostly analysis goes for movement-image
to the varieties or avatars. Although identifying
three varieties, other kinds of images are
possible, because the plane of movement images is
only one section of 'a Whole which changes, that
is of a duration or of a "universal
becoming"'. Movement-images offer a temporal
perspective which also opens to some deeper 'real
Time' beyond the specific plane of movement-images
and beyond specific movements. This means
there must be time images to depict real time
specifically. There can be indirect images
of time produced by relating movement-images
together or combining their three avatars, and we
see this in montage, but this is still not a
'time-image for itself' (68-9). There can be
a relationship with this whole or duration, but
Bergson himself suggests direct time images, in
his case 'the "memory image"' (69).
Peirce can be used to attempt to classify these
different images, although we will have to work on
the relation between this concept of the image and
his notion of signs. Deleuze suggests that
we can see signs as particular images,
representing a type of image, sometimes related to
the composition of the image, sometimes to its
formation or extinction. Until this is
clarified, Deleuze proposes to still use Peirce.
Back to illustrations, The Man I Killed
offers 'an exemplary perception image' when a
cripple perceives a parade through the gap in the
crowd. Lang offers an example of the action
image in Dr. Mabuse the Gambler, where an
organized action corresponds with synchronized
watches, and this produced lots of classic action
images in film noir, with the depiction of
'detailed segmentarised action'. Westerns
present action images and also perception images,
where 'the hero only acts because he is the first
to see, and only triumphs because he imposes on
action the interval or the second's delay which
enables him to see everything' (70), with the
example of Winchester '73. Dreyer on
Joan of Arc offers the classic affection
image.
The three images are combined in montage, which
assembles movement-images with their corresponding
avatars. However, usually films have one
dominant type of image which affects montage
[action films or affection films -- Dreyer offers
almost exclusively affect, Vertov perception,
Griffith action]. Each has a characteristic
shot as well, long shots with perception, medium
shots for action, closeups for affection.
However, for directors like Eisenstein, each of
these movements is supposed to offer a pov on the
whole of the film, a way of grasping it, so that
it is really the whole that becomes affective in
closeups etc.
Notes on the
Bergsonian bits of Deleuze, G (1989) Cinema 2
-- the time-image, London The Athlone
Press.
(I know the date of the second
volume is before the date of the first one
-- shows the effects of different
publications in English)
Chapter three. From
Recollection to Dreams: third commentary on
Bergson
Bergson says that recognition can be
automatic/habitual, a form of sensori-motor
recognition that takes place through movements
reacting to and extending perceptions so
that we pass from one object to another, but
always on the same plane. Attentive
recognition is not just the extension of
perception through movement, however, but a
'return to the object' (44) through attempts to
analyze and add characteristics to it: the object
goes through 'different planes'. If the
first is a sensori-motor image, the second image
is 'a pure optical (and sound) image of the
thing'. It looks like the first one is
richer, while the second one involves description
which replaces the concrete object [and apparently
Robbe Grillet uses these Bergsonian terms to
describe the cinematographic image].
However, the first description is also organic
[which includes being connected to our own life
and its adaptation] while the other is 'physical -
geometrical, inorganic'. We start to see
these in shots like Rossellini's depictions of
landscape as almost abstract, while Godard [Les
Carabiniers] offers just a series of
descriptions in each shot, 'pure descriptions
which are unmade at the same time as they are
outlined'. So the main characteristic of the
new cinema at first is that it operates with a
different theory of description.
It is possible to see the sensori-motor image as
the impoverished one, retaining only what
interests us, including provoking reactions from a
character. The sensori-motor plane provides
interests in general. The pure optical image
on the other hand points to 'an essential
singularity' which also endlessly refers to other
descriptions at the same time. The first set
of images look more useful, while the use of the
optical image remains unclear. Bergson
suggest its importance lies in its ability to call
up a '"recollection image"' (46), but is also
possible to see suggestions of the relations
between 'the real and the imaginary, the physical
and the mental, the objective and the subjective,
description and narration, the actual and
virtual', the relations between terms that are
different in nature, although they refer to each
other. It no longer matters which one comes
first. These images invoke 'a plane or
circuit' suggesting infinite characteristics of
the thing which has its own layers or
aspects. In this way, it is possible for
characters in films to read images quite
differently [as reported in dialogue], almost as
hallucinations.
In practice we are talking about a circuit of
'obliteration and creation'[descriptions supplant
then add meanings],with different planes
intersecting and contradicting each other to show
different layers but via 'forking' [not smooth
succession?]. But this depicts reality as layered
as well as memory [referring to the quote in Matter and Memory
about layers in the cone also representing strata
of reality] [the example is Rossellini and Stromboli
with the different perspectives offered by the
character climbing higher and higher on the
island]. Sensori-motor images and their
extensions are replaced by 'much more complex
circular links between pure optical and sound
images on the one hand, and on the other hand
images from time and thought' (47). All
coexist 'by right', representing, in this case,
'the soul and body of the island'.
So pure optical and sound signs link with a
virtual image not with movement. So what is
a virtual image? Bergson talks of
recollection images, although these are already
implicated in automatic recognition.
However, their proper role is to link with
attentive recognition, which positively requires
them. A new model of subjectivity is
involved, not just a gap between received and
executed movement. The recollection image
fully fills the gap [affection only describes the
process that goes on internally in the gap].
The recollection image 'leads us back individually
to perception', involving a subjectivity that is
'temporal and spiritual' actually adding something
to matter.
One obvious way to see this is in the flashback,
which goes from present to past and then loops
back to the present. Some filmmakers [Carné
in Daybreak] actually offer us 'a
multiplicity of circuits', operating in a whole
'zone of recollections and returns' (48).
However, a flashback is still a 'conventional
extrinsic device', offering a psychological
causality, which is 'still analogous to a
sensori-motor determinism' and does not threaten
linear narration. Flashbacks arise because
it is necessary to go back to the past, to either
'mark or authenticate the recollection image', to
explain destiny, for example. However, we
might still be hinting at 'a pure power of time
which overflows all memory'[more description of
Carné and how he uses expressionist figures].
Mankiewicz [Joseph that is] offers the best
examples of flashbacks, but does this not to
explain or suggest linearity, but to offer 'an
inexplicable secret, a fragmentation of all
linearity, perpetual forks like so many breaks in
causality' (49). It is time that forks, and
this can be unacknowledged by the
characters. The flashback involves several
people indicating the multiplicity of circuits,
and even the circuits fork within themselves
[sometimes the characters can pursue these forks
to find out what is happening]. Nor is there
some easy alignment, some common destiny, but only
new meanders or breaks in causality, 'a collection
of nonlinear relations'[examples from the films
follow—as I say in the other
notes the only one I recall is All About
Eve, which shows nonlinear progress as the
heroine schemes to take the place of the actress,
but as a deviation which makes a circuit and
offers a secret]. Sometimes we see that
flashbacks do not even explain the present, and
sometimes the secrets remain forever.
Sometimes the forks seem to constantly complicate
so that everything has to start again and become
even more enigmatic. Overall, it is the
forks that have to be explained by the flashbacks,
and the recollection images are used to point to
the forks. Originally, they are often pretty
well imperceptible and need to be recalled by an
attentive memory [there are links here with the
structure of the novella in ATP.
Mankiewicz is seen as combining the novella with
the more theatrical element]. The memory is
still 'story behaviour', represented by voice and
the voice-off. Sometimes this is further in
bodied as a phantom or ghost, or some absent
character barely glimpsed, but theatricality is
added because we see the characters and listen to
their dialogue [implying that they act out the
story, sometimes in a way which is emphasized by
camera movements or sound qualities which vary in
volume]. The fork, also understood as 'a skidding,
a detour', is usually revealed after the event
through flashback, but one character always
foresees it [examples follow, including the way in
which an assistant overhears Eve, off-frame,
producing a false story]. Here, we are
seeing 'the birth of memory' which will reappear
in the future. [This links with Bergson on
time, showing that the past had already been
constituted in the present, as an aim to come].
Mankiewicz uses the cinema particularly to show us
this happening, the present recurring in the
future as past. In particular, he uses the
notion of out-of-field [the eavesdropping or
overlooking].
Sometimes this is depicted directly, without
flashback [still with Mankiewicz] as in films like
Julius Caesar or Cleopatra.
The characters are remembering history, sometimes
with visual clues, like the frescoes in Cleopatra,
but there are still forks. The characters
are depicted differently in psychological terms,
the linear Brutus, for example, although even here
he lets Mark Anthony speak in his absence and is
easily outmaneuvered. Mark Anthony is 'a
supremely forked being', with his many faces,
complete with plebeian origins, acting as a simple
soldier and so on. Cleopatra is also
'the eternal forking woman, devious,
capricious'(53), and Anthony hides behind a
pillar to witness one of these duplicitous scenes
with Octavian.
The flashback is still limited by requiring a
justification, although in Manciewicz there is
forking time at least. There is also a
similar problem with the lack of autonomy of the
recollection image: it exists because it needs to
find a pure recollection, discover pure
virtuality.. Recollection images only really
emerge as actualizations of pure recollection
[when I read Matter and Memory, I wasn't
sure if this was just a way for the philosopher to
understand them—Deleuze seems to think pure
memories really do actualize on their own, which
is also what Bergson actually says, to be
fair]. So there is another element to
subjectivity. The recollection memory can
only represent 'the former present that the past
"was"'(54) in the process of it being
actualized. Again this is being hinted at
with the 'deeper time images' seen in later
discussion. Attentive recognition has to go
through recollection images, but it assists
sensation and movement. It informs us, but
often more when it fails them when it succeeds,
when we cannot remember, and have to suspend
action, or where there's a disconnect between
recollection image and the actual optical
image. Recollection images point to the
virtual directly in those cases, appearing as
'feelings of déjà vu or past "in general"'(55) [as
these examples suggest, Bergson really sees such
disconnection or suspension as psychological
pathology, and discusses it as such, while Deleuze
wants to turn it into philosophical
insight].
There are dream images, or fantasies.
Avoiding links with action [the most common way to
do so says Bergson],
these provide 'the recollection image or attentive
recognition [with] the proper equivalent of the
optical-sound image'. We soon find mental
phenomena like amnesia, hallucination, dream
depicted in film, especially in Europe. This
was partly due to a reaction against American
films with action images, and partly with
stressing subjectivity against American
objectivity [note that it is Freud and surrealism
that is an influence as much as Bergson, only
briefly acknowledged by Deleuze]. The motor
extension is lost, sensations and perceptions no
longer link with recognition in a predictable
way. A whole set of memories, images of the
past in general appear as something free
floating. Cinema uses dissolves and super
impositions. Expressionism tries to restore
a panoramic vision, even where people are being
assaulted or are near drowning. We also see
it in Fellini and 8 1/2. Bergson
still sees a connection with sensation, but no
longer a tight one, with dreams as the most
extended of the circuits' connecting with
action. Any sensory image whatever can be
connected with the dream image. In normal
life, pure recollections become recollection
images, 'summoned by the perception image'(56) but
in dreams, a virtual image actualizes in the third
[dream] image, which can itself be actualized in a
whole range of the other images, this is why
dreams are not metaphors but 'anamorphoses' in a
circuit [so a dig at Lacan here—but there is no
real discussion of how these transformations or
condensations occur, and metaphor must be invovled
too, surely -- the thin cloud and the
razor?]. Thus may a green surface broken by
white patches become a meadow or a billiard table
[Bergson's actual example], linked by 'a becoming
which can by right continue to infinity' (57) ]Entr'acte
{watch it here}
and Un Chien Andalou {here}
are both given as examples].
American cinema grasp the implications in 'Buster
Keaton's burlesque', through surrealism and
dadaism [examples from Keaton's dream sequence in
Sherlock Junior, {here}
where the hero ,who is a cinema projectionist,
dreams and this shown as a film in the cinema
where he is working: balancing chairs become
somersaults and then edges of precipices and then
steps among lions, all just leaping from one scene
to the other matched on action]. Dream
sequences are not the only way to represent dreams
[in Spellbound, it is not just the Dali
sequence but things like the impressions of the
fork on a sheet turning into stripes on
pajamas]. Each image in the circuit acts as
the virtual which becomes actual in the next, and
sometimes they all return together [in the final
shot of rosebud the sledge]. Dreams in films
are depicted in various ways. One overloads
the visuals with dissolves de-framings, special
effects and so on, while the other heads for
abstractions offering 'a perpetual unhinging'
between concrete objects. These are actually
both like linguistic operations. [Examples
of the first are Murnau {Nosferatu} and The
Last Man {aka The Last Laugh}, and
Keaton as above for the second, or between Entr'acte
and Un Chien... The latter
apparently retains the circular shape in common
between the different objects.
This circuit of dream images often ends with a
depiction of real objects, or shows us an actual
dreamer, or depicts the dream in a separate
distinctive visual way [so it is not a very acute
critique of the real]. A certain Devillers
introduced ambiguity in terms of the '"implied
dream"' (57), with no link between optical or
sound image and motor extension, and no attempt to
compensate by becoming a dream image.
Instead, there is another connection with
movement, but this time the world itself moves, in
a depersonalized form. [Some gripping
examples, with the slippery road itself sliding,
all the world running away from a frightened child
as if on a conveyor belt, the camera causing the
path on which characters and to move. We see
these features also in dreams, but their effect is
then mitigated by acknowledging that they are
dreams]. The example is Epstein and The
Fall of the House of Usher, where landscapes
or houses extend, Hathaway [Peter Ibbetson]
or Laughton's Night of the Hunter, where
nature apparently intervenes to save the children
[the boat is motionless, but the landscape slips
by]. Malle also uses the technique [how
about David Lynch when the fairy descends to save
Sailor in Wild at Heart, or the
miniature characters come to life in Mulholland
Drive?]. Different dream worlds can be
entered, sometimes indicated by peculiar animals,
or other inversions. This is the whole
'cinema of enchantment' (60). We can also
see this at work in the depiction of fairgrounds
in Fellini which apparently transport viewers to
alternative space times.
Even musical comedy 'outlines a dreamlike world'
as bodies and movements are depersonalized
[Berkeley and the girls' legs as a kaleidoscope].
There are still identifiable individuals, but they
can still display 'a supra-personal element... a
movement of world that the dance will outline'
(61) [examples where walks turn into dances in
Astaire or Kelly— critics do a lot of work here,
and there's also an attempt to link both dancers
into what Kleist says about grace [see Bogue's commentary and
my additions]—Astaire dances quite unconsciously,
while Kelly is simply able to impose his
consciousness through athleticism]. The idea
is to get us to dream, and we enter the dream
state as soon as the dancing starts, a
dream-like metamorphosis, an implied dream again.
A definite ambiguity remains, as normal sensory
motor movements turn into dance, and then
return. We can speculate about whether the
normal action was itself just a pure optical-sound
situation, pure description, not real
action. In Donen's films [which include Singing
in the Rain], the ambiguity is deliberate,
with real action already represented by postcards
or snapshots, using the same colors as on the film
set, so that dance adds proper depth to the world
[also think implied here is that a movement of
dance is clearly not normally connected to the
sensori-motor adaptations of normal life, but is
itself an excess]. Minnelli was able to
depict plural worlds through dance, finally
questioning dominant reality: each set becomes a
world, offering pure description, although we have
'to let ourselves become absorbed'(63) [the
examples here are Yolande {aka Yolanda
and the Thief} and The Pirate].
Other devices are also used, sometimes which
depict reality as 'the heart of a nightmare', or
trapped in the dream of the other. Minnelli
show best how musical comedy can offer a point of
indiscernibility between the real and the
imaginary. Sometimes in these pieces,
another dreamer is featured!
Burlesque offers similar possibilities [examples
here include Jerry Lewis]. Modern burlesque
celebrates sensori-motor situations and links them
in various kinds of series [including the Laurel
and Hardy 'dismantled series' (64). But
there's also a strong 'emotive affective' element
[specially in silent film] which can appear in
both large and small forms of action. The
characters are strange, lunatic, or dumb [and
lunatic] as in Harpo. There are still links
with the sensory motor schema at first, sometimes
connected by absurd yet logical relations, Groucho
or Fields. This will lead to another stage,
Deleuze predicts, which breaks with th the
sensori-motor altogether and becomes pure
description. Apparently we can see this in
Jerry Lewis, which are sometimes openly theatrical
or which resemble musical comedy [with the dance
in The Patsy]. The sets are
unrealistically intense. The character sets
off movements of world which often become
catastrophic. Lewis is a loser, but he makes
the world move, often oft are extraordinary bodily
movements of his own, and can triumph. We
can also see a new notion of the machine, the
remote controlled electronic machine, which goes
out of control and 'ravages the set' (66).
This evokes an 'energy band', not centered on the
character alone, but appearing as a movement of
the world.
We have to go beyond Bergson on the comic here,
because this is not just something added to
something living, but something which carries away
the living. Pure optical and sound
situations are connected to this waiver of energy
or movement of world, in a special kind of fantasy
or implied dream [lots of Jerry Lewis
examples]. Tati offered something similar
(66). Sound also ceases to be integrated
into sensory motor schemes visual. Again
Tati rides a wave, although these are not traced
to personal fantasizing, instead, he offers 'sound
and visual configurations capable of making up a
new op'art, a new son'art'(67), and others and
named in developing situations as 'pure set valid
for itself', or optical and sound situations
turning into song rather than conventional action
[like the extraordinary Japanese film Zaitoichi
(2003) about the one armed samurai which ends in
song and dance]. [Demy {The Umbrellas of
Cherbourg} is given as the best example,
where 'set...replaces situation, and the
to-and-fro...replaces action'.
Chapter five. Peaks of present and sheets
of past: fourth commentary on Bergson
The crystal [discussed in chapter four, see notes]
reveals time without having any movement, showing
how time itself splits into present and
past. This raises the possibility of two
time images in fact. We can see the first in
the inverse cone model, where the pure past is not
managed by recollections tied to
the present but exist as a virtual element.
These can exist autonomously, and we have to
access them with a seed. This shows that
'memory is not in us; it is we who move in a
Being-memory, a world memory' (98), it seems
something already there or preexisting, towering
over the point of the cone which is the
present. Fellini says something similar.
Within the cone are many 'regions, strata, and
sheets' (99), some extended, some contracted, each
with different tones, themes and shining
points. This is quite different from linear
clock time. They're only layered in terms of
the perspective offered by the actual
present. When we search for recollections,
we place ourselves in these regions through a
'jump', and if we do not find a recollection image
there, we have to return to the present and jump
again. It is the same with sense and
language, ideas and thought, which are similarly
organized in circles or sheets and into which we
jump.
We can get a sense of the present by thinking
about something which is replaced by something
else, something in the past or future, implying a
form of succession. However, we can also
grasp a single event as something 'purely optical,
vertical, or, rather, one in depth' (100) [this is
the crystal, surely?]. If we pursue this,
though we can detach events from the space in
which they are located, and from the
present. This leaves the time of the event
as including past, present and future, 'a time is
revealed inside the event', and the elements of
the past, present, and future of the event can be
seen as 'deactualized peaks of present
[sic]'. This appears paradoxical, but we can
see the events, or life itself as containing a
different number of presents—of the past and of
the future as well. The paradox can lead to
disruptions in interpretation or in social
relationships. The appropriate chronosign is
the accent or peak of view ['pointes de vue'], as
opposed to the signs of aspects, regions or layers
as in the first example.
Robbe-Grillet shows the peaks best, including in Last
Year...—'the three implicated presents are
constantly revived, contradicted, obliterated,
substituted, recreated, fork and return'
(101). This as an effect on narration which
now becomes abstracted from action, distributing
'different presents to different characters' which
are plausible enough until they are
combined. In the end, we realize that the
man 'lives in a present of past', while the woman
'lives in a present of future', and neither of
them live in the present of present where the
husband is. [Other examples are given 102 F,
and there's even a short meditation on relativity
and chance {via a critic}]. We see
depictions of unconventional time not regulated by
movement in Bunuel, through things like repetition
[The Exterminating Angel] or cyclical time,
or alternative endings, including the substitution
of different actors for the same character in That
Obscure Object of Desire.
Back to Last Year... The two main
contributors Resnais and Robbe-Grillet, had quite
different understandings of the film and how it
should be constructed. Both were aware of
the crisis of the action image, in the wandering
of characters. R maintained that something
real always did exist, even in Marienbad, while R-
G saw everything taking place in the head of the
characters or even the viewer. However, for
Deleuze, the image remains whatever the viewer
thinks, and that something can be distinct and yet
indiscernible [I think because the whole
distinction between real and imaginary is
reversible]. The two might also disagree
about whether the film is set in a perpetual
present stripped of time, or whether it shows an
architecture of time, points of present or sheets
of time. Again the issue is that the
time-image can do both. The film also raises
issues of what is true and what is false,
especially if the film is to be read as offering
not only an' indiscernible becoming of distinct
image' or 'undecidable alternatives' (105).
We can see time as depicted as simultaneously both
sheets of the virtual past, and deactualized peaks
of present. In either case, the film shows
that cinema is not always 'by nature' rooted in
the present.
The direct time image, this time of sheets of the
past, is found in Citizen Kane.
Witnesses are found to offer recollection images
of the man in a series of subjective flashbacks,
which also offer 'a slice of Kane's life, a circle
or sheet of virtual past'. The whole point is to
try to discover what 'Rosebud' means. No
sheet is prioritized, each has shining points, so
the overall picture of Kane is nebulous. The
recollection image can never offer unity,
however. The first kind of recollection
image shows a 'motor series of former
presents' or events (106), such as those
developing the desire to make Susan a
singer. The culmination of this sequence is
the shot showing depth of field, with Kane in the
background and Susan about to commit suicide in
the foreground: here images are arranged in depth
rather than shown as a series of presents, to
represent regions of the past.
This restored depth to one of its earlier
functions in cinema, before montage or camera
mobility. However, it was not depth of field
as such, but rather parallel planes which
harmonize. The breakthrough comes, in
painting first, when the planes refer to each
other, say when characters from different planes
address each other. We can see the same
history in the cinema, with Welles inventing a
depth of field, and having the characters in the
background make direct contact with those in the
foreground. In other examples, characters
communicate by watching each other along a
diagonal. In Welles, there is visual
distortion too, and the combination of light and
shadow can rightly be termed baroque or neo
expressionist. The deep shot shows
temporality, or 'continuity of duration' (108), a
depth of time not space, indicating regions of
time, linked to other regions by optical aspects
or borrowed elements.
Many functions are offered by this depth of field,
all of them producing 'a direct time image'
(109). Is not just depth, however which
offers direct time images, but this one
corresponds to definitions of memory and shows us
processes of remembering. This is the usual
location for depths shots which appear
necessary. Flashbacks can show
'psychological memory' (109) as a series of
recollection images, and there are a number of
occasions when the present passes according to
chronological time [clocks or calendars].
But the depths shot can show how someone evokes
the past in an actual present as a preliminary to
gathering recollection images, or where a sheet of
the past is explored before being consolidated
into recollection images, both the contraction and
the expansion in Bergson's terms. So pure
and psychological memory are connected again as in
Bergson.
We see contraction in Kane, for example
the high angle shot picking out the alcoholic
Susan which then can 'force her to
evoke'(110). Other examples are given in
other Welles films, 110f. We see expansion
as the witnesses go back to their own sheet of the
past, searching for the meaning of
'rosebud'. In all these examples, high and
low angle shots offer visual contractions, while
oblique and lateral tracking shots show
sheets. Depths of field in each type of shot
shows evocation and exploration taking
place. Depth serves as 'a function of
remembering...a figure of temporalization'.
It can show adventures of the memory, including
pathologies of disconnection where evocations for
example can no longer be applied to perceptions.
There are also montage techniques in their own
rights, relating the sheets of past with the
shorter shots of passing presents [that initiate
them]; relating sheets together; relating the
sheets to the contracted present.
Each witness evokes but Kane is actually dead, his
death is the fixed point [not movement is the
point, I think, so movements cannot be used to
allude to time]. The same goes with the end
of the film when rosebud is revealed, but there is
no one there to record it as it burns, 'it is
totally pointless and of interest to no
one'(111). This raises questions about the
relevance of the sheets of past, but again maybe
this is the point, since once a person is dead,
there is no point. A similar structure is
apparent in Ambersons, where sheets of the
past are evoked, but no longer fit the transformed
present where the key figures are dead. In The
Lady, sheets of the past can no longer be
evoked or even distinguished, so recollections
seem like hallucinations [more discussion 113
F]. In Arkadin, the character erases
his own past, having feigned amnesia, in order to
construct a 'grandiose, paranoid unity'. All
the films can be seen as offering a progression
towards the impossibility of evocation and
recollection. In The Trial, the hero
cannot recall anything about the offense and
experiences and number of puzzling regions of the
past which offer more hallucinations rather than
precise recollections so that 'nothing is
decidable anymore'. Behind all the episodes,
is not some notion of superior Justice, but rather
a machine [to quote D's
and G's book on Kafka].
So for Welles, the sheets of past exist but may
not be usable. Death is also 'a permanent present,
the most contracted region', or the sheets
themselves have become twisted or scattered.
We see time as a perpetual crisis or even 'at a
deeper level, time as primary matter, immense and
terrifying, like universal becoming' (115): either
the strata are unending, or there is some
substance without stratification at the
bottom. This is not transcendental but
immanent, some immanent justice or earth. We
contact it directly, it is 'autochthonous' [no
origin or history, found in its original
place]. This is best seen in Welles's Macbeth
with its stone age setting.
At least Welles offers some fixed point, some
present offered to our view, which is the starting
out for the exploration of the past. But
Resnais films have no center, and 'the present
begins to float' (116) [apparently, in Je
T'Aime Je T'Aime, the time machine returns
to a different present and past each time].
As a results, there is no way to decide between
sheets of the past, seem to each has their own
present [the example is Hiroshima...,
where even apparently agreed characters in their
pasts turn out to be quite different, in a
movement of 'generalized relativity']. There
are 'undecidable alternatives' between sheets of
the past. [Then Deleuze attempts to show
continuities between the films as opposed to the
normal way of dealing with them critically which
is to see a number of 'oppositions': JeT'Aime
over the memory of one character, Last Year
as complications because there are two, Hiroshima
shows completely different memories between the
two characters with nothing in common ...].
The sheets of the past can belong to a single
memory, a whole memory world, or some
reconstructed notion of the ages of the world
itself. Tracking shots are used to construct
circuits and continuums are particularly pliable
[apparently offering an example of the 'Boulanger
transformation'. Known in English as the baker's
transformation, this involves mixing
elements in such a way, liking cutting and
kneading dough, that apparently unconnected
points become adjacent to each other. The
point seems to me that characters in each of the
sheets are separated but can also be related in
some topology, demonstrating 'each of the
characters', or the 'various periods of Van
Gough'. In Last Year... there is
one sheet where the characters are actually quite
close to each other, although they also have a
separate existence on other sheets. The
issue is whether each of these sheets can be seen
as a regular transformation of the other or of
some underlying single one, and this is how you
would unify Resnais films for Deleuze. More
discussion 120 F, including Resnais' rejection of
the flashback in favor of transformations,
sometimes shown with fragmented objects which are
redistributed or when ages are superimposed.]
What these films show is Bergsonian pure
recollection as virtual, and the recollection
image as a way of making it the actual in relation
to a present. Bergson insists that the two
are separate, and that pure recollection is found
in a sheet preserved in time, or an age.
When we occupy it in memory, we can either
discover specific points which will be actualized
as a recollection image, but we're also aware that
the past itself is not always accessible, that it
belongs to a different age. However, as
Resnais shows, there is another possibility of a
sheet of transformation, where fragments from
different ages are brought together. This
can happen in dreams where one recollection image
turns into a series of others referring to
different points. Spectating ,reading or
writing can involve something analogous, where we
construct a sheet of communication to weave a
network of detached relations between them
[transversality?]. 'In this way we extract
nonchronological time'[a mixture of timescales, as
in the event?]. Sometimes this will fail and
end in incoherence or bland generalities.
Sometimes this can be shown in discussions of
false recollections.
However, art can construct such streets which are
both a past and something to come. This is one way
to read Last Year, where both a man and
the woman are seen as characters occupying two
sheets from which the third character has
constructed a transverse link. We see hints
of this in other Resnais pieces too, especially Providence.
Here 'the work of art crosses coexistent ages'
(124) producing something like a new montage
[perhaps in a Van Gogh painting]. Resnais attempts
to stop pure memory collapsing into mere
recollection, by preserving all the other mental
operations as well, including a 'forgetting, false
recollection, imagination, planning,
judgement'. It is a structure of feeling
that underpins all these functions, not the
characters themselves. Feelings unite past
and present. Music is important in conveying
them. Feeling circulates from one sheet to
another and they can be set free on a sheet of
their own. In that event, they can make us
aware of consciousness or thought as well, 'a
becoming conscious' (125), as a kind of hypnosis,
bringing new awareness of things that appear to be
mere shadows. Thought is the transversal
operating in non chronological time across the
ages picked out by the feedings. Apparently,
this happens in the brain, in cerebral mechanisms,
which offer a continuity between feelings.
The operation can be compared precisely to the
unrolling of the film. Resnais intended that such
thoughts all to operate around and behind the
image.
This happens in the time image, where the world
has become memory, but the brain itself recreates
matter through transversals. The brain
itself can be seen as a screen where
confrontations take place between past and future,
inside and outside, in dependent of any fixed
point. 'The image no longer has space and
movement as its primary characteristics but
topology and time' (125).
|
|