Notes on: Gowing, L. (2001)
Cézanne: the logic of organized sensations. in
M. Doran (ed) Conversations with Cézanne.
pp 180--214. London: University of California
Press.
Dave Harris
[Much-cited source in Deleuze's
book in Bacon. Rather clearer than Deleuze.
Another reminder of Badiou's
critique that Deleuze discovers only what he has
thought already when he adds philosophy to
detailed analysis -- in this case the diagram as
well as the BwO and becoming-animal].
The history of art is really a history of
misunderstanding, and that applies particularly to
Cézanne. His influence has been unparalleled,
however, but it is more than just 'novel kind of
fragmentation, the development of discontinuity
into pattern, or the elevation of concords of
colour and line into harmonies that were
sufficient in themselves' (180). A major influence
was a concern with 'the existent world' (181) as
well. He painted objects rather than effects, and
the influence of his native countryside is
apparent.
Colour does become more important later, but still
as an attempt to depict 'the breadth and depth of
nature'. It was not Impressionism, despite signs
of an influence. Nor is it the same as 'the object
– based structures of earlier years'. He was a
modernist, but in terms that did not and still
does not exist. The apparent discontinuity and
fragmentation actually suggested 'ways of
perception and patterns', although he did not see
himself as succeeding
There are 'different kinds of rationale' (182) in
the earlier and later work. One stressed a
'logical mimetic theory of painting', while the
other depended on 'inherent meanings', 'a way of
thought rather akin to free association'. It is
not clear whether Cézanne intended this — some of
his remarks indicate equivocation and 'aesthetic
doubletalk'. He displays 'contradictory kinds of
reference' that are still widespread, despite his
commitment to 'earnestness' and the 'moral dignity
of tradition'. Cézanne himself was preoccupied
with theory and explanation. The questions are
still relevant.
Although Cézanne was 'passionately attached to
objects', he also moved towards 'the
disintegration of the object' especially in the
last phase. The patch of colour replaces the
object. He worked on this before, for example
originally using palette knives: that had been
generally associated earlier with 'an attachment
to what was actual and physical' (183), but
Cézanne wanted to paint with the knife throughout,
thinking that 'the handling was the picture'. A
new 'intrinsic material unity' emerged which links
the picture to objects but also to the 'common
consistency of the material world'.
A new aesthetic emerges in the late 1860s,
involving 'extreme standpoints and total
solutions', and it is this that finally separated
out the avant-garde, including Cézanne. Patches of
colour with straight edges reappeared, as in L'Etang
des Soeurs (below) but colour
differentiation became 'the chief medium of
definition'. We see in this picture parallel
alignments of colour patches offering a kind of
early version of a structure, and this was to
reappear in later works, including watercolours
which had 'eliminated the material substance that
remained' (184). Objects in space became
'apparently immaterial relationships of colour',
appearing in the oil painting as well. An area was
composed of vertical brushstrokes, delicately
graded in colour and then more differentiated
'like detached facets'. These still had a
figurative function, however. Cézanne himself
agreed this, in his own way: we interpret nature
as a series of patches of colour 'following one
another according to a law of harmony'. These hues
are understood as having modulations. In this way
painting 'is classifying' sensations of colour.
Cézanne was precise in his terminology and was
generally well educated, so terms like harmony and
modulation should be seen as part of a system,
although he was occasionally 'more literary and
fanciful'. [L'Etang is a transitional
piece]
Later, there is tonal homogeneity, like
Impressionism, but the colour patches do not mould
the form. The physical shapes of the earlier
paintings do not persist: 'the structure is no
longer one that we can imagine built. It is a
property of the juxtaposition of colours on the
flat surface' (185). Cézanne began to talk about
the work of the eye, and the way in which it
operated with a 'culminating point', always
closest to the eye.
The discussion that nature models itself on
spheres and cylinders, was not to be taken
literally — even flat surfaces could be seen like
this. The line of sight meets a flat surface at
different angles, and this is not really different
from viewing a rounded surface. The 'geometry of
vision' displays a common property. The use of
modulated different colours, instead of monochrome
flat spaces to depict objects is an example of
this view that nature operates with circular forms
[the modulations apparently vary the angles of
lines of sight]. Angles of sight always vary, even
with lines that are actually straight. This might
explain why straight lines become curves as
'compensation'(186), a rejection of plane
perspective. However, he was guided as much by
theory as observation, and once explained that a
sense of colour was developed by both work and 'by
reasoning', responding to needs that were 'both
emotional and intellectual'. Modulations of colour
were intellectually necessary, and offered a
continuing form of modelling.
This looks like abstraction, but Cézanne insisted
there was still a 'systematic figurative
function', not descriptive but 'expository'. This
appeared first in the watercolours and began in
the 1880s. Gowing understand it as 'progressive
process of sublimation'. The material characters
were less important, so the new images looked
ascetic, subordinated to designs, structural
rather than matters of 'sensuous enrichment', akin
to buildings. We see this in an 'exceptional'
watercolour The Green Pitcher:
Here is what Gowing says of
this: the culminating point is not a highlight on
the front of the pots but a blank piece of canvas.
Then the colours are arranged in order blue, green
'the material colour of the pot' then ochre. Here,
'a deliberate system is being employed… No pot
ever produced this logical sequence' it is the
colour sequence that produced 'the lightness of
the spot'. There is also a spot of red at the base
and an asymmetrical line, providing 'stance' and
'pictorial poise' respectively. The whole painting
shows the method and way of thought that was to be
developed and elaborated later. For example we see
colour sequences which are 'increasingly
independent of direct transcription of sense data'
[the example is a portrait of Cézanne's wife]
(188). The colours are presented 'abruptly' and
are not 'continuous modelling in light and dark.
They convey the rounded surface metaphorically'.
We see the same sort of development in the first
series on Mont Sainte-Victoire. It is an emergent
logic in the order of colour rather than 'anything
one can imagine observing on the spot'. In the
later paintings, 'related colour mutations were
noted in groups of brushstrokes in contrasting
directions, beginning to form into discrete
patches, with no reference to separable objects'.
Later paintings was even more 'systematic and more
detached'. Watercolour avoided 'implications of
material substance'. Colours were always presented
in the order of the spectrum, with regular
intervals ending in a culmination point and then
reversed. This produces both 'melodic response'
and 'the continuous curvature of the surface'.
Cézanne was to make explicit his notion that it is
the contrast in connection of colours that is
central to modelling, and he assume that nature
was also 'modelled on forms with a rounded
section'. There were occasional complications from
superimposition, and some experiment with the
watercolours, but the underlying principle
remained, to replace light and shadow by 'changes
of surface and the ideal roundness of mass as if
in a code' (189). But this was not an artificial
symbolism, rather a matter of 'natural, almost
physical reactions to the relationships and the
contrasts inherent in intervals of colour'.
An observer [and later recipient of thoughts, one
Emile Bernard] saw the method in action. Cézanne
began with a single patch which was then
overlapped to produce a hinging effect which not
only colours the object but moulds its form. There
was '"a law of harmony that directed his work"'
with modulations '"fixed beforehand in his mind"'.
Apparently, '"he deduced general laws, then drew
from them principles"' to guide his
interpretation. '"His vision was much more in his
brain than in his eye"'.
Later work shows the effect of definite motifs,
but even here patches of colour were organized in
the same way [the example is a watercolour of
rocks, or other topics — in these, we are offered
'deepening echoes of a single progression; in both
it is the colour not the description makes the
form'. Cézanne himself was to confide in Bernard
that the point was to stress modulation not
modelling, although the French word might imply
both. There might also have been a musical
analogy.
Modulation means a 'transition through clearly
perceptible stages', but Cézanne rejected 'smooth
monochromatic modelling, although later work might
include using colour to indicate changes in the
direction of shapes, or scale. Whatever, 'the
possibilities enough to show that this is a
procedure in which reason and calculation are
inseparable from the poetics' (190), and there is
no 'direct reliance on empirical data'. Gowing
sees it as the result of Neoplatonism — '"theory
developed and applied in contact with nature"'.
An example here is Bridge under Trees [it
might be this one?]. Gowing says that there is no
specific local colour, but rather a series based
on green and blue, as 'an equivalent to the great
blossoming of form'. It was painted at a time when
Cézanne saw art as '"a harmony parallel with
nature"'. Again this draws on ideas going back to
antiquity [Deleuze specifically broke with all
those, of course].
So, by the
end of the 1890s, Cézanne was using oil
painting for observations of nature, and
watercolours for 'metaphoric sequences of
colour, which operated through the gradations
of colour interval rather than identifying any
local hue or effect' (191).[I could not find
the examples on the web, so I reproduce them
from Gowing page 191]. Gowing says that the
watercolour shows 'a key of blue modulating
into yellow and pink'which became 'a
conventional system for the notation of the
actual bulk'. He also used pyramid
formulations or diamond-shaped's, reinforced
in the oil painting by the wallpaper. The oil
painting looks more real but is 'in fact more
schematic', with straighter lines and flat
planes. The colours in the watercolour
attempted 'to grasp of the actual volumes; it
was a digestive system' and after the solidity
had been grasped, the schematic structure was
possible. We see therefore 'two processes,
analytic and synthetic' (192), explaining the
'immense labour, indeed the eventual
impossibility of completing a picture'. The
method became increasingly deliberate.
[Then a bit which Deleuze cites, where a patch
on the portrait of Vollard was left
deliberately blank and when asked, Cézanne
says that he would struggle to find the right
colour to fill the spaces, and that once he
did he would have to go over the whole picture
again]. The point is that relationships of
colour are crucial, 'akin to the physical
articulation of forms' in some of the
drawings.
After 1900, Cézanne became increasingly
figurative, but never entirely, nor never just
parallel with nature. Indeed, the figurative
style is 'so magical that he has come to glory
in it is an order of reality in itself' (193).
We see this with the increasing tendency to
focus on segmented surfaces, say with foliage,
'an absolute intoxication with colour contrast
is an order of reality in itself, a complete
world'. Cézanne said there was no other task
for painting, not line or modelling, a
'self-sufficient fabric of colour contrast'.
Cézanne persisted with metaphorical sequences
of colour however to depict volume, even in
some of the oil painting.Gowing describes the
House on the Hill as having a number of
successive culmination points with sequences
arranged around them in spectrum order e.g.
'emerald, cobalt, the bluegrey culmination and
violet', or crimson succeeded by red pink and
golden oak. The system is used elsewhere too.
Cézanne was determined to 'read nature', to
realise it in his terms. This meant realising
the sensations both personal and traditional,
to interpret nature in terms of patches of
colour. He explicitly defined these terms in
his theory, although Cézanne was not primarily
interested in the correctness of theory.
Nevertheless to paint required 'both a way of
seeing and a system of thought' (194), and
both were inseparable: logic related to the
organisation of sensations '"which provides
the means of expression"'.
Sensations were 'the root of everything'
(195), and seem to include both sight data and
feelings. He was proud of them, and served as
a basis to defend his stance. There is some
ambiguity, however. They might be organised by
logic and in that sense go beyond mere sense
data, the stuff of mere perception. Cézanne
wanted to reawaken '"confused sensations"'
which we have originally, to revive our
instincts and artistic sensations. At the end
of his life, they became identified as
sensations of colour, again seen 'as much
innate as experienced'. The struggle was to
realise them
Cézanne originally took realisation to mean
'simply the satisfaction of natural wishes'
(196). Difficulties arose, however, for
example in the tendency for the erotic drive
to become 'sublimated in the pursuit of a
consummation in art', a special notion of
realisation, evoking emotions and unsatisfied
longings. He was a lonely person. What must be
realised is not just the 'actuality of
nature', which the artist merely depicts.
There may well be a basis in observation,
combined with a love of nature, but Cézanne
opposed photographs and accurate drawing, 'the
whole conception of representation is a reflex
action' without intellectual activity,
allowing the eye to direct the hand '"without
reason intervening"'. Representation was not
the same as reproducing. He preferred the
notion of interpreting instead of
representing, although he was also well aware
of traditional conceptions involving imitation
and even artistic deception.
The point was to make things real. First of
all the model had to be read, form traced or
construed and then realised, a much slower
process. Imitation did not deliver reality in
painting, and the focus had to be what was
'intrinsically real'. (197). This involved
logically organising and classifying
sensations. The debate between copying objects
and realising sensations was in fact an
earlier one [discussed 197]. Intrinsic reality
turned on the sense of colour that was both
'inborn and confirmed from nature' (198), and
subject to logic, organisation and
classification. It could be thought of as
using sequences of colours to interpret
volume, with colour patches ordered by the
spectrum and spaced evenly along it: this
could be the 'law of harmony', rather like
using a particular key and scale. Cézanne saw
it as 'an inborn visual syntax'
Cézanne face difficulties including those
provided by age and ill-health, and a tendency
to see himself as a Moses. Cézanne saw the
pain of realisation and intensity as 'part of
the triumph': painting had to make real in a
way that 'would parallel nature and its
harmony and follow it in structure'. This
required magnificent colour, something the
animated nature and life itself. He saw the
life of nature as inside himself, as the
result of some 'imperative emotional need'
(199).
These uses of colour characterise the last
works, including the still lives, depicting
'sombre resonances' of colour — 'the polarity
of ginger and violet or orange and blue green'
(200). There is material richness in the
objects depicted. The colours are not intended
to generate an atmosphere but reflect 'a
specifically pictorial pressure between
complementary colours' [the characteristic
example is Still Life with Apples and
Peaches. More examples on 201]:
The portraits at this point turn away from
concern with the human subject, who become
devoid of expressive character.
Another example of colour
modulation is Nature morte: Pommes, poires
et casserole:
Here,
says Gowing, is 'astonishing brightness'
and a progression of primary colours from
red to yellow to green to blue. The
culminating point is the violet blue
handle. The formal content is also 'so
physical and sensual', an example of
'biomorphic modelling' found elsewhere.
In his old age, Cézanne was increasingly
subject to mortification but obstinacy. We
can see a sublimation in the biomorphic
shapes [the example is Rocks near the
Caves above Château Noir]. The setting
provoked thoughts about 'the diversity and
complication of nature'(203) which
resisted reason, although his own personal
confusions of sensation were a problem as
well. It was necessary to somehow
represent 'the manifold image of nature'.
A new 'dichotomy of style'also emerged,
based on some emotional issue, and seen
between 'bulging biomorphic rhythms' and
'light yet calculated precision with which
colour patches are built'. Together, we
see how 'rectilinear structures
[organising the colour patches]…
Sublimated the physical and sensual
content of form into the successions of
chromatic intervals'.
There may have been a therapeutic benefit:
being able to realise sensations like this
became 'the prerequisite of his own sense
of identity', and when it worked, he felt
himself stronger than others: at other
times a helpless victim of himself,
needing friends, suffering from black
moods. Mastering oneself involved command
of the subject and means of expression.
That in turn depended on '"a good method
of construction"' (204). Eventually,
logical readings of nature became a matter
of survival itself.
Cézanne's sequences of colour patches
should not be mistaken for those in other
styles. They 'do not represent materials
or facets or variations of tint. In
themselves they do not represent
anything'. It is the relationships between
them that counts, progressions and
modulations and these 'parallel the
apprehension of the world'. The colours
imply not only volumes but 'axes,
armatures', often at right angles to
chromatic progressions a kind of
'invisible upright scaffolding' [the
portrait of the gardener is the
example.Some of the paintings of trees
forming a vault also use wedges of colour
to indicate both foliage and 'the imagined
structures implied' (205). Much depends on
'implications of gradient that are is
naturally inherent in colour intervals as
in music intervals'. We are not talking
about reference but a 'psychology of
vision'. The patches must be large enough
to stay perceptible in their own rights.
There is also an earlier 'linear flourish
that marked the passion of the figurative
act'. 'Descriptive rightness in an image'
could affect the artists detachment and
his autonomous reaction to nature.
Instead, the right sort of brushstrokes
and colours would produce the drawing
themselves, 'an image is the product not
of an act of will, but of a process that
was analogy used to the automatism of
nature'.
The series of paintings of Mont
Sainte-Victoire [discussed in more detail
206 – 9 begins with a depiction of local
colours and conventional light and shadow,
tangible modelling. Then there are gentler
versions, still with light and dark and
'highly specific drawing of contours'..
Other images show the full chromatic code
'a continuous band of colour modulation'.
There are 'parallel vertical brushstrokes
that unite the canvas', with patches
arranged along the horizontal lines,
deliberately chosen to offer human depth
and breadth respectively, drawing upon
earlier traditions, perhaps. Later
painters like the Cubists would build 'the
human role vertically into the conception
of an image' (207). There is 'surface
homogeneity', and landscapes 'reimagined
in bands of colour modulation with sharp
contrasts'., Although still with some
'material realism': the sky, for example
is rendered nonnaturalistic the, and the
same colours as the landscape, although
material differentiations of substance are
still apparent. Eventually, the consistent
range of colour dominates, and linear
marks do not define anything. 'Affinity
and correspondence in themselves' (208)
become important. Finally, the system of
colour embodies all form, with horizontal
parabolas representing the real, despite
flat surfaces, an abstraction for Gowing.
Cézanne acknowledged that abstractions
were necessary because he could not cover
canvases entirely or look at objects with
delicate points of contact, although he
still criticised the practice of
describing contours with a line, and
thought that nature would provide the
solution.
Cézanne
turned back to consult nature in the
last years, especially at
Fontainebleau, where 'combinations of
light atmosphere and natural shape'
helped him with an analytical reading.
The example here is Le Chateau a
Fontainebleau
u
GowingSays
we see a restless linear definition, tree
trunks moved through successive positions
to adjust the view, a 'deceptively
traditional look' (209), but also 'an
advanced and complex abstraction' (210)
which include not only a colour sequence
but 'a graphics system too — a linear
code' [I think the argument is that
Cézanne was trying to dominate nature more
at this stage. There are other examples of
'sharp and wiry' brushstrokes on 210, some
returning to the Mont St Victoire series].
We see some other structures like echoing
shapes or progressions of colour between
foregrounds and backgrounds. Sometimes
colours are splintered 'with no
three-dimensional connotation', but also
'the wiry line out of which the contour is
woven' (211).
In the last watercolours, 'correspondences
of colour melt together'. Things are no
longer separated, differences are
reconciled, a gentler kind of 'mild
luminosity' reflects the painter's own
pleasure. There is also 'prophetic
grandeur'.
Overall, Cézanne insisted that 'the
process [of developing from past
histories] is rational and sensible'
(212). Painting was 'of an art of rational
intelligibility'… '"Simply the means of
making the public feel what we feel
ourselves" close '
|
|