Notes on: Deleuze, G. (2013) Francis
Bacon: The Logic of Sensation. Trans.
Daniel Smith. London: Bloomsbury Academic
Dave Harris
[Originally published
just after ATP.
Before reading this, I also read a more general
commentary on Bacon: Davies, H and Yard S. Francis
Bacon. London: Abbeville Press. That book mentions a series of
interviews between Bacon and Sylvester (and
others), which Deleuze also cites (rather heavily) I did not make notes, but,
obviously, Bacon's own comments on his work are
not the same as Deleuze's interpretations, which
raises problems for the boring old empirical
validity of what Deleuze says -- sometimes Bacon's
views can be taken as supportive 'evidence', but
at other times they need to be
reinterpreted.
Deleuze also draws heavily (!) on Gowing's essay on
Cézanne., and the book also contains extracts from
the important observations of, and remarks and
aphorisms by, Cézanne himself in Vollard or
Bernard. I am otherwise entirely in the
hands of Deleuze. Finally, idly browsing D Hockney's
(2006) Secret Knowledge. London: Thames
and Hudson, I was reminded of how important the
actual technology of the arts is. Hockney argues
for the relevance of new optical devices in
painting 'realistically', and I also recall
arguments about the role of the German chemical
industry in producing consistent colours in oil
paint. No technical issues are discussed in
Deleuze, neither here nor in the huge books on the cinema, which limits
his critique of 'human creativity' a bit.]
Authors Foreword
The idea is to consider aspects of Bacon's
paintings moving from the simplest to the most
complex, informed by 'the viewpoint of the general
logic of sensation' (xi). All the aspects 'coexist
in reality. The converge in colour, in the
"colouring sensation", which is the summit of this
logic'. There are also implications for the
history of painting
Author's Preface to the English edition
Bacon's paintings are violent, not only the
depictions of horror or mutilations, but rather of
violence 'that is involved only with colour and
line: the violence of a sensation' (xii),
something static or potential, a reaction or
expression, like a 'scream rent from us by a
foreboding of invisible forces' [luvvie]. Bacon
wants to paint the scream. The bodies should be
seen as ordinary ones 'in ordinary situations of
constraint and discomfort'. He wants to show 'the
invisible forces that model flesh', especially the
inertia of flesh itself, falling from bones or
flattening bodies. It is the effects of movement
on the mobile bodies and interior forces that he
is depicting, informed by 'an intense pity: pity
for the flesh'.
There are also large fields of colour detached
from Figures, with no depth, sometimes divided
into sections or frames and tubes, 'an armature, a
bone structure' (xiii). [NB Figure with a capital
F denotes a special meaning, avoiding confusion
with ordinary human figures?]. Background and
Figure are related, sometimes the fields of colour
offer a shallow depth or hollow volume in which
the Figure 'enacts its small feats', rather like
experimental theatre or Beckett novels. As the
fields of colour press in, the Figure presses
outward, trying to pass through the fields in
spasms or screams. We see this in objects like
umbrellas which mask parts of the Figure [and seem
to act like a kind of funnel to help the body
escape]. The scrubbed and blurred effects indicate
the 'dissipation' of the Figures. Sometimes the
Figure disappears altogether leaving a jet of
water or dust, characteristic of Bacon's
individual abstractions.
Colour is very important and there are two
different systems one relating to the Figure and
the other to the field. We might see this as an
extension of Cézanne [pass, for now at least]
leading to 2 further problems how to preserve the
unity of the background as a 'perpendicular
armature for chromatic progression' while
preserving the specificity of a form 'in perpetual
variation' (xiv). This was a problem common to Van
Gogh and Gauguin, making sure the ground did not
become inert nor the form 'murky'. Both made the
background into 'vast monochrome fields that are
carried towards infinity' and invented new colours
for the flesh, making it look rather ceramic,
kiln-fired.
Experiments with monochrome fields have continued,
varying not hue but rather 'subtle shift of
intensity or saturation determined by zones of
proximity'. This is Bacon's route, inducing zones
of proximity by sections or by a band or stripe
crossing the field. Bacon also produces broken
tones for flesh, 'as though baked in a furnace and
flayed by fire'. So both problems are addressed at
the same time, unlike most other painters, and
there is correlation between them: 'a brilliant,
pure tone for the large fields, coupled with a
program of intensification: broken tones for the
flesh, coupled with the procedure of rupturing… a
critical mixture of complementaries'. In this way,
painting conquers time [luvvie again] — through
colour, referring to 'eternity and light in the
infinity of a field', and through 'metabolic
variability in the enactment of… bodies'. There
are parallels with Messiaen's music.
Most modern painting has abandoned simple
figuration, but Bacon breaks with it in a
different way, not drawing on impressionism,
expressionism, symbolism, cubism or abstraction.
Instead, the Figure is elevated to prominence and
related to the field. This rejects all narrative
and all symbolization, forms which result only in
'the bogus violence of the represented or the
signified' (xv).
[I bet actual viewers restore both. T Chevalier
has written a novel The Girl in the Pearl
Earring. In the
Times she says how she viewed the painting:
Sixteen
years after buying the poster, I was gazing
at the Girl one morning when out of nowhere
I thought, “I wonder what Vermeer did to her
to make her look like that?” In all the
years the painting accompanied me, I had
sometimes wondered what she was thinking,
but had never included the painter in the
equation. In that moment, my view of the
painting changed: it went from being a
portrait of an anonymous girl to a portrait
of a relationship. Suddenly it was not
wallpaper, it was a story...Everything about
Girl with a Pearl Earring began to interest
me because it became part of a narrative I
was piecing together. ...I become part of
the creation of the story that the painting
is telling...I’ve begun to create a story as
I study this overfamiliar image and suddenly
the painting becomes new and fresh and
powerful.
Can you do that with Bacon's paintings? Do viewers
still speculate about the relationships Bacon had
with his subjects in the portraits? Did he pose
them with screams or smiles? I f we know G Dyer
was also his lover does that make a difference?]
What is missing is 'the violence of sensation — in
other words, of the act of painting'. Bacon's
revival of the triptych offers separate and
distinct sections which also negate narratives.
Yet they are linked with a 'kind of brutal
unifying distribution' that denies any symbolic
undertones. In triptychs, 'colours become light
and that light divides itself into colours'.
We also discover rhythm 'as the essence of
painting', not the rhythm of objects or
characters, but rhythm itself which 'alone become
characters, become objects', indeed 'the
only Figures'. [The reference is to the
work of Messiaen --wiki entry here
-- especially to his Chromochronie which
you can hear performed here]
In Bacon's triptychs we find something 'analogous
to 3 basic rhythms' — a steadier attendant one,
one of crescendo or simplification, something
expanding and adding value, and one of diminuendo
or elimination, removing value. In every triptychs
we will find an 'attendant – Figure, like the one
in the 1972 Triptych [below] which shows one
Figure with an incomplete back but a complete leg,
another with a complete torso but missing one leg.
These can be understood as monsters if we are
interested in figuration, but 'from the point of
view of the Figures themselves, these are rhythms
and nothing else' [with another reference to
Messiaen and his 'rhythmic characters']. Even the
single paintings are organized as though they were
a triptych with the same three Figures,
'resonating in the field', both separated and
united. [so the attendant is the central panel,
the crescendo the right-hand one and the bloke
missing a leg is the diminuendo? I reckon they are
interchangeable/arbitrary. More below]
Chapter
1 The Round Area, the Ring.
We find lots of round areas, sometimes ovals,
sometimes in the form of round shares or even
in discs or spirals painted around the body.
These serve as a kind of circus ring, a place,
intended to isolate the Figure. Sometimes the
Figure is put inside a box or located on
rails. The idea is to convey mobility, some
sort of exploration of the Figure in a place.
The relation to the place will be understood
as a fact. 'The Figure becomes an Image, an
Icon' [but not a signifier].
Bacon wants to avoid the 'figurative,
illustrative, and narrative' aspects of
figures (2). His painting does not represent
anything or tell a story. Painters in the past
have escaped by heading for pure form or the
purely figural, either through abstraction or
extraction. The point is to oppose the figural
to the figurative [a note refers us to
Lyotard]. In ordinary figurative painting,
there is an implied relationship of an image
to an object and also to other images,
permitting both illustration and narration, a
story in between different figures [I think
the viewers will supply this anyway]. There is
a need to isolate and illustrate the Figure,
'to stick to the fact'.
It might be possible to produce 'diverse
figures that would spring from the same fact'
to achieve the same ends. Bacon might be doing
this with his coupled figures, or the
relationship between the panels of the
triptych. Classical painting has allowed
narrative to creep in, and this will '"cancel
out the possibilities of what can be done with
the paint on its own"' (3).
What might factual relations look like,
without any attempt to offer more conventional
intelligible ones? Bacon's Figures have broken
with the convention of putting something like
a landscape behind a figure, or a ground from
which the figure might emerge. He did try
these at first, but progressed to 'a set of
short "in voluntary free marks"', sometimes
looking something like grass. Thick and
blurred textures in the background are related
to the local scrubbing and blurring of the
Figures, which extends them into a
'non-figurative zone' (4). Bacon therefore has
a system which is following.
The fields of colour structure and spatialize
and are adjacent to the figure. We can see
this in close-up view, a tactile or haptic one
[another note refers us to an earlier art
historian who says that a distant view gives
one perception, but a close view enables us to
see something of texture, something tangible].
There is no relation of depth. Instead, 'two
sectors on a single plane, equally close'are
correlated, inside the ring or round area
which is their common limit. [Deleuze says we
can think in sculptural terms which will
enable us to see mobility, and says this is
hinted at in a painting like Man with Dog — we
see sidewalks, pools, and people emerging from
pools].
There are connections with earlier art forms,
including Egyptian, but Bacon has a system
involving two adjacent sectors enclosing
space, depicting space better than simply
something in the background which is
indistinct. Both space and Figure are blurred
in a spirit of '"destroying clarity by
clarity"' [a note refers to a commentary on
Tati films, where two dialogues are heard
simultaneously and equally clearly, with the
intention of rendering both insignificant]. We
see this say in the depiction of newspapers
which are illegible despite having certain
clear characters.
Chapter 2 Note on Figuration in Past
Painting
Painting 'extracts the Figure from the
figurative''(6). Bacon says he wants to do
this because photography already illustrates
and documents, and secondly he wants to break
with religious possibilities in earlier
attempts to do painting, and instead pursue
'an atheistic game'. Deleuze has his doubts.
Photographs do more than just represent or
illustrate, as Bacon knows when he uses his
own photographs. Similarly, religious
sentiment did not prevent nonrepresentational
experimentation [some brilliant examples here
including Giotto's Stigmatisation]: in
heavenly matters, for example, there is no
need to preserve simple realism, but rather to
portray sensations. The word of God is not
limited by conventional aesthetics. Classical
paintings sometimes liberated Figures.
Nor does modern painting easily liberate
itself from existing photographic and artistic
clichés [the famous bit]: 'the entire surface
is already invested virtually with all kinds
of clichés' (8). Abstract painting already
realized that it was a struggle to break with
these. Bacon knows this when he says that
photographs are not simple, but represent
'what modern man sees'. The real danger is
that this will replace actual vision,
including that formerly depicted in painting.
Chapter 3 Athleticism
There is a double
relationship between the Figure and the
place, the ring. We see this by looking at
actual contours [boundaries or those strange
structures made up of lines?]. These relate
both 'the material structure and the
Figure], and the Figure and the field,
working as a kind of membrane.
Often, the Figure
appears to be waiting for something,
although this is neither a spectacle nor a
representation. The Figures are
'"attendants"' (9). Both spectators and
spectacle are to be avoided [and the second
painting of the bullfight makes this point
best because there are no forms of access
for spectators, merely a connection between
toreador and bull]. Sometimes spectators are
deliberately excluded by closing a door.
However, there must be
an attendant, not a spectator but included
in the Figure — sometimes as photographs or
paintings hanging on walls. They are to be
seen as 'a constant or point of reference in
relation to which a variation is assessed'
(10). [Apparently, there is a resemblance to
Kafka]. We can see all these features in the
Painting of 1978 — the contour or
round area migrates from the ground to the
door, giving the illusion that the Figure is
standing on the door [note the arrows too
--variously explained as non-realist,
borrowed images etc]
The Figure often shows
athleticism, but not for its own sake,
rather something derived from the material
structure or field — a cylindrical field
carols and imprisons the figure, boxes
confine bodies. This conveys movement on the
Figure which it continues. What we get is 'a
derisory athletics, a violent comedy in
which the bodily organs are prostheses'
(11).
The Figure also moves
toward the material structure and the field.
Something comes from inside the body which
requires an effort. These efforts are not
the result of some superhuman ego, but come
from the body itself, in the form of a
spasm. The body seems to attempt to escape
through various exits like drains or the
points of umbrellas [with a quote from
Conrad about a prisoner trying to escape
through a viewing hole]. Sometimes a
particular organ takes the lead in vomiting
or excreting. The shadow becomes important
to point to a body that has escaped from
itself. The scream shows the body escaping
through the mouth. [I like this umbrella
painting below, Painting 1946. One
of the crucifixion series. Also shows
the armature, of white lines in this case]
So it is no longer that
the material constrains the Figure, more
that the Figure itself wants to disappear
into its surroundings. Here, the contour
indicates a volume for escape. Umbrellas
appear more than once as contours like this.
There is a connection with Burroughs on how
characters want to try to escape through
their cocks. The painting with the
hypodermic syringe should similarly be seen
as a body attempting to escape through the
syringe. There are also mirrors which bodies
can enter. Bodies elongate or flatten in
mirrors.
The Figure is not only
isolated but deformed, and this is movement
of the figure itself. The deformed body
escapes from itself, and must return to the
material structure. We see here depicted
'passages and states that are real,
physical, and effective, and which are
sensations and not imaginings' (13). We see
in mirrors what happens. Sometimes the whole
structure acts as a mirror. Overall, there
is a constant and intense movement 'that at
every moment transfers the real image onto
the body in order to constitute the Figure'
(14).
Chapter 4 Body, Meat
and Spirit, Becoming–Animal
The body is the Figure not the material
structure. It is a body without a face,
although it does have a head, sometimes as
in the portraits, it is reduced to a head.
There is [of course] 'a great difference
between [head and face]' (15), since the
face is a structured organization concealing
the head. The head also possesses 'spirit in
bodily form, a corporeal and vital breath,
an animal spirit' shown in specific animals
-- pigs buffaloes or bats. Bacon's
project therefore as a portrait painter is
'to dismantle the face, to rediscover the
head'. This is what the scrubbing or
blurring does, destroying the form of the
face to make the head emerge
Animal traits of the head are shown in the
deformations of the body. Animality is not
so much the form of an animal, but rather
the 'spirits that haunt the wiped off parts'
[a note, page 127, refers to Guattari (Machinic
Unconscious) on faciality traits which
are liberated, and how these are also animal
traits of the head]. Even where animal heads
replace human ones, it is still 'the animal
as a trait' [and may not be literally
depicting an animal but perhaps the track of
a bird spiralling] [the example is the 1976
Tryptich below: bird trait faced by portrait
faces as attendants]. Sometimes animals
appear as shadows detached from bodies. We
have here a painting of 'zone of
indiscernibility or undecidability between
man and animal' (16): man becomes animal and
animal becomes the spirit of man. Forms are
not just combined, but display 'rather the
common fact of man and animal'. The
bullfight also shows the coupling of man and
animal.
Indiscernibility of the
entire body arises because the body is flesh
or meat, only structured by bone, and
revealed only where bones are removed. Flesh
becomes bodily material. Bacon paints meat
as 'the body in which flesh and bone
confront each other locally'. The mouth and
its teeth can be seen like this too. The
flesh descends from the bones, or bones are
raised in the form of a raised limb. In
these, the bones take the form of 'a trapeze
apparatus (the carcass) upon which the flesh
is the acrobat' (17). We see the same things
in the crucifixions. Meat is the object of
pity, since it retains suffering and
manifests pain and vulnerability as well as
'delightful invention, colour, and
acrobatics'. Thus meat 'is the common zone
of man and the beast, their zone of
indiscernibility' [surprisingly literal
example of this concept]. Bacon himself
confesses to being emotionally moved by
slaughterhouses and meat, a kind of empathy
[maybe] in that meat becomes ourselves, the
spectator is in the spectacle, animals are
part of humanity but also 'we are all
cattle' (18) [actually referring to another
writer, a certain KP Moritz]. This is not
just resemblance or sentimental
identification but 'a deep identity… The
reality of becoming' [felt by all
revolutionaries, apparently].
Is the head just meat? Even though close to
bone, the bone belongs to the face and the
head is 'deboned', although made of firm
flesh. The head and meat are arranged on
'scale of intensity' that becomes
increasingly intimate. The meat is on the
edge of the ring initially, but is also in
things like 'fleshly rain' (19). Screens and
pitying gazes also 'have meat as their
object'. Later heads particularly are
painted 'in the colours of meat, red and
blue'. Eventually, 'the head becomes the
non-localised power of the meat' [pass].
There is an infinity with mouths, so the
open mouth is like a severed artery,
something nonlocalised, something that turns
meat into 'a head without a face', a route
of escape. The scream indicates 'the immense
pity that the meat evokes'
Chapter 5
Recapitulative Note: Bacon's Periods and
Aspects
We have discussed becoming animal, but there
is another kind of becoming with figures
dissolved back into structures and fields,
'melt into a molecular texture' (20). Here
we will find the domain ['a justice of'] of
colour and light [with a hint of smooth
space]. Bodies escape through mouths, or
even enigmatic smiles which help to bring
about 'the disappearance of the body', just
as with Lewis Carroll and the smile of the
cat. [Several examples are offered where
faces disappear leaving only smiles. The
1953 triptych offers screaming mouth in the
centre, hysterical smile on the left, [other
way round?] and the dissipated head on the
right].
Here, bodies are no
longer confined but are perhaps shielded by
curtains and partially hidden. Bacon is
deliberately exploring again the blurry and
indeterminate, depth and sickness. There is
a German term malerisch [a note on
page 128 says this used in earlier art
history, referring to '"that depreciation
and gradual obliterated of line (outline and
tangible surface) and for the merging of
these in a 'shifting semblance' of things —
it is an attempt to represent that they and
in palpable essence of things"'].
Sylvester wants to suggest three periods for
Bacon: an early one with precision and
bright and hard fields, a second one which
is malerisch, and a third one which
brings both conventions together returning
to something dated and thin in the ground,
with local blurriness using striping and
brushing. Deleuze wants to insist that these
are not sharply distinguished periods,
'coexistent aspects' (22) [and he provides
some examples]. He also suggests a possible
recent fourth period, where the dissipation
of the figure continues leaving only a vague
trace behind. Here the field structures
elements, offering divisions sections and
regions, and the scrambled zone now stands
on its own, appearing not as a Figure but as
'a pure Force without an object'. One
example is the waterjet. The technique can
also be used to describe Turner. This should
not be understood of abstraction without a
Figure, but rather dissipation of the Figure
into the background [another example is the
sand dune series] We see this with
only disfigured elements in the background,
for example, or the use of pastels between
Figures and empty spaces.
'Painting is this
coexistence' (23). There is a first movement
of tension, from structure to Figure, where
the structure can Carroll around or isolate.
The second movement of tension goes from the
Figure to the structure, contraction or
dilation as escape, 'an extraordinary
becoming – animal', eventually dissipating
into the structure leaving only a smile,
where the contour becomes a curtain,
concealing not enclosing the Figure. So the
contour already had a number of functions —
isolation, but also a '"depopulator" or…
"deterritorializer"', cutting off any other
background. Then the contour deforms the
Figure as it passes through a hole. Then it
becomes a curtain where the Figure is
dissolved 'by joining with the structure'
(24). In each case it acts as a membrane
offering two-way communication. We can
understand this communication as systolic,
contracting the body and diastolic which
extends and dissipates it, sometimes finding
both in the same body. 'The coexistence of
all these movements in the painting… Is
rhythm' [original ellipsis]
Chapter 6 Painting
and Sensation
We can move beyond illustrations of figures
either towards abstraction or toward the
Figure. Cézanne said this was heading
towards sensation: 'the Figure is the
sensible form related to a sensation; it
acts immediately upon the nervous system,
which is of the flesh, whereas abstract form
is addressed to the head' (25). Cézanne gave
this notion 'an unprecedented status'.
Sensations are the opposite of the
ready-made or the cliché 'but also of the
"sensational," the spontaneous. It
represents both the nervous system or
instinct, temperament [both terms relating
to earlier work --Maldiney?], and the
object, the fact the event. 'It is both
things indissolubly… I become in the
sensation and something happens through the
sensation' [a note on page 129 refers to
earlier art historians and also to
Merleau-Ponty. Neither saw sensible
qualities in the object {nor in the
individual consciousness, I recall} but as a
field something that 'stands on its own
without ceasing to interfere with the others
(the "pathic" moment)' — something like a
phenomenon for phenomenologists? A compound
perception or gestalt?. This 'forms the
basis for every possible aesthetic']. The
same body can be both subject and object,
both giving and receiving sensations. 'As a
spectator, I experience the sensation only
by entering the painting, by reaching the
unity of the sensing and the sense'. Cézanne
was to critique impressionism with its
emphasis on 'disembodied play of light and
colour' (26) and to argue that sensation is
'in the body'. What is painted is something
that can sustain sensation.
Painting the sensation is the same as Bacon
wanting to record the fact, and Bacon talks
about some connection between the paint and
the brain directly. The two painters differ
in terms of their perceptions of nature, but
both are dealing with sensation and
temperament. Bacon says that the form
related to the sensation is the opposite of
a form related to an object that it
represents. Sensation also avoids the detour
of narrative, and it is somehow capable of
passing from one level to another or from
one area to another. 'This is why sensation
is the master of deformations'.
Representational and abstract painting alike
'pass through the brain, they do not act
directly upon the nervous system, they do
not attain the sensation, they do not
liberate the Figure' because they remain at
one level.
It is not that each order or level or area
relates to a specific sensation, placed in a
series, as in a series of self portraits
which produce different sorts of feeling.
Bacon does have series, and he also offers
'series of simultaneity, as in the
triptychs' (27). But there is something else
as well — each painting or Figure is itself
a sequence or series, offering sensations at
diverse levels, not different sensations but
'different orders of one and the same
sensation', 'a plurality of constituting
domains'. Each figure is an accumulated
sensation, something synthetic, like
sensations themselves.
This unity does not arise from the object or
thing. Even when things appear, 'all primary
figuration' has been removed first. Bacon is
not trying to depict the sensational,
something that provokes a violent sensation
– he wants to paint screams rather than
horrors. Screaming Popes do not scream at
anything specific, but rather they scream
'before the invisible' (28). We have to
infer a deeper horror. Bacon has experienced
horror himself, including the violence of
war, but he does not like his own paintings
that are too sensational — 'even the
bullfights are too dramatic'. If we have
horror, we have a story. For this reason,
most violence can be found in seated or
crouching Figures which reveal the power of
the paint — '"the violence of paint, it's
nothing to do with the violence of war"'. It
is the same with Artaud on cruelty, which
'depends less and less on what is
represented'.
It is not just that viewers experience
different separate levels of feeling [with
some psychoanalytic underpinning] — '"too
logical"' for Bacon who is interested in
some deeper reality. This is also mistaken
in attributing ambivalence to the Figure
itself and its feelings. 'There are no
feelings in Bacon: there are nothing but
affects; that is, "sensations" and
"instincts"' (29) [referring to some
'formula of naturalism'. Sensation
apparently determines instinct at a
particular moment, and instinct is the
passage from one sensation to another or the
search for the best sensation, one that
'feels the flesh at a particular moment of
its descent, contraction, or dilation' [I
gather that all these are terms in art
historical accounts of naturalism].
The 'motor hypothesis' is better, where
levels of sensations are snapshots of
motion, and the movement is the synthetic
[Duchamps Nude... is the example
here].
Bacon also likes [and
borrows from -- see Davies and Yard] those
early photographs of movement as a series of
stills in Muybridge [lovely one below]
He paints intense
movements, [blurred] turns of the head, for
[one] example. Sometimes, the Figures appear
to be frozen in the middle of movements.
There is also an interest in 'mobile
sculpture', painted as movements along the
armature. The mundane daily round of
movement is also found in Beckett's
characters. Figures often show 'amoeba –
like exploration'. These movements are
explained by sensation and its elasticity
[with some strange connection to Beckett or
Kafka about the necessary connection with
immobility 'beyond movement']. Bacon is most
interested in 'a movement "in–place," a
spasm' (30), something showing the action of
invisible forces on the body.
There is another '"phenomenological"'
hypothesis. Levels of sensation arise from
different domains related to the different
sense organs, although they also refer to
each other independently of any represented
object. This is the pathic
'(nonrepresentative)' moment. 'Between a
colour, taste, touch, smell, and noise, a
weight{?}, there would be an existential
communication'. We can hear the hooves of
the bull and we can touch the quivering of
the bird, interact with the meat, 'a common
exercise of all the organs at once'.
Painters thus depict 'a kind of original
unity of the senses' appearing in 'a
multi-sensible Figure'.
This also implies 'a vital power that
exceeds every domain and traverses them all.
This power is rhythm'. It can appear in
music but also in painting. There is a
'"logic of the senses"' for Cézanne, 'which
is neither rational nor cerebral' [getting
close to the Ken Gale viewpoint! Quite
different from his own work on the logic of
sense of course]. The sensation relates to
rhythm [expressing different levels and
domains if I have understood this properly].
The rhythm is diastolic and systolic,
closing of the world and opening of the self
[as above — this apparently is referring to
Maldiney on Cézanne, says a note on page
130]. In Cézanne, it was Nature, for Bacon,
it is something more closed and artificial.
Bacon might even share the same temperament
as Cézanne: 'cerebrally pessimistic but
nervously optimistic' (31) in his own words,
'an optimism that believes only in life,
figurally optimistic while being
figuratively pessimistic.
Chapter 7 Hysteria
We find the 'rhythmic unity of the senses'
(32) beyond the organism and the lived body.
There is by contrast 'more profound and
almost unlivable Power', and it is there we
find rhythm, in close connection with chaos,
and where the levels are perpetually mixed.
This is what Artaud called the BwO [see the
discussion in ATP] . It is
organization rather than the organs that we
need to focus on, the organism. The BwO is
by contrast 'an intense and intensive body…
traversed by a wave that traces levels or
thresholds… according to the variations of
its amplitude'. Sensation itself has 'only
an intensive reality… allotropic
variations', as with the egg before organic
representation takes place. At this level
forms are contingent. It is 'a whole
non-organic life' (33) [which might just be
a play on 'organ']. Sensation at this level
is 'excessive and spasmodic… immediately
conveyed in the flesh through the nervous
wave or vital emotion'.
Bacon's Figure is a BwO, flesh and nerve
traversed by waves and levels. The results
of encountering the forces acting on the
body produce the '"affective athleticism"'.
Sensation is not just representative but
real. Cruelty relates more and more to
forces upon the body or sensation rather
than horrific representations. The BwO is
for Bacon the 'intensive fact of the body',
and the scrubbed and brushed bits indicate a
'neutralized organism', '"a visage that has
not yet found its face"'.
The same powerful non-organic life is found
in '"the Northern Gothic line"' [I have
discussed this elsewhere, in the books on
cinema I think: one example is the weaving
intertwined lines found in Celtic
jewellery]. It opposes organic
representation, it extracts a geometric
form. Unlike classical painting, however,
'this line is decorative; it lies at the
surface… does not outline a form'. It is not
a geometry claiming to represent something
essential and eternal, but rather something
'in the service of "problems" or
"accidents"' and features things like
adjunction intersection and projection [and
ablation, although I could not see how that
fitted — something removed, something
associated with?]. The line continually
changes direction, diverts, coils or even
ends in a series of free marks. This is what
makes it 'vital and profound'. It is not
organic but rather 'elevates mechanical
forces to sensible intuition' often through
violent movement. It can also offer zones of
indiscernibility when it 'encounters the
animal', working through 'clarity and
non-organic precision', making forms
indiscernible (34). It is driven by
'spiritual will' but the body is the spirit.
We can also experience ambiguous approaches
to BwO through drugs, schizophrenia or
sadomasochism. The reality might also be
called hysterical, in a specific sense. The
transversal wave produces sensations at
particular levels and this can 'determine'
an organ, but this is only provisional,
produced by the wave and the force. [As in ATP,
William Burroughs's ravings about
interchangeable organs are cited here]. So
the BwO has organs, but they are not
organized in the conventional way. Instead
they have 'an indeterminate organ'. However,
even in Bacon paintings there are sometimes
recognizable mouths or teeth, but this 'must
be understood' as the effect of a wave
encountering a force, and there can be
changes at other levels. The BwO is 'finally
defined by the temporary and provisional
presence of determinate organs'. Bacon
depicts this as variations of texture and
colour: we should understand this really as
'temporal variation' ['in Bacon, time itself
is being painted', to put it in luvvie].
This is 'chronochromatism', to be contrasted
with the flat use of colour in the fields.
Every sensation implies a difference of
level, order, or domain, and they can move.
The phenomenological notion of unity is
inadequate here. We see it best in the
series offered by the BwO — without organs,
indeterminate polyvalent organs, temporary
and transitory organs. This series offers
'the hysterical reality of the body' (35).
Hysteria here is not the psychoanalytic
version. We can find this version in some of
the early studies in the 'specifics and
paralytics, the hyper- aesthetics or
anaesthetics'. These effects are also
sometimes migrant. They are associated with
anticipation or delay, depending on the
acceleration and delay of the wave. The
precise effect of the forces produce a
transitory character of bodily effects or
organs. The hysteric can be seen as affected
directly as in sleepwalking. Hysterics feel
a peculiar sensation where 'the transitory
organs are felt under the organization of
the fixed organs', and one consequence can
be '"autoscopia"' [you feel you inhabit a
body, that you speak from inside the head]
[notes, page 30, refer to Artaud, and there
are references to Beckett and to an earlier
commentary on Bacon by Leiris].
Beckett's characters are similar [building
on the point made above]. The spastics and
hyperaesthetics 'are often indicated by
wiped or scrubbed zones', and the
'anaesthetics and paralytics by missing
zones'. The example is the 1972 triptych
below. Bacon offers a style which points to
both a before and an after, and offers a
'hysteresis' that interrupts the figurative
and then gives it back. The often noted
presence in the paintings could be
hysterical if we see the hysteric as someone
who imposes their presence, but also reacts
to other things and beings that are 'too
present' and where this excessive presence
has signifying power [my term]. Bacon refers
to his own hysterical smiles literally, in
representing a neurotic or hysterical model,
and in a more general sense where 'the whole
painting… is hystericized'. Bacon abandons
himself completely to the image, sees
himself in a head or camera. His hysterical
smiles in[per]sist even behind faces, just
as screams survive the mouth, and there is a
body that survives the organism. This offers
'excessive presence', something already
there combined with something always
delayed. [Apparently Sartre used the term to
describe himself in this way] Conventional
representation is impossible.
There are always dangers
in constructing such clinical analyses
[which Deleuze has tried out before, of
course,with literature] and there is the old
problem of where hysteria lies — in Bacon,
in the painting, in painting in general [or
in the critic or viewer?]. Painting has a
special relation to hysteria, trying to
'release the presences beneath
representation'. The colour system is
important here in that it acts as 'the
system of direct action on the nervous
system' (37) [ I still prefer the
phenomenological insistence on perceptual
unity here including subjective elements] .
Thus all painting turns hysteria into art,
even though hysterics themselves cannot do
this. This is not to say that the painter is
hysterical, certainly not in a negative way.
Instead, the horrors of life turn into some
pure and intense life itself, and painting
releases 'all the joys of line and colour'.
This is how cerebral pessimism becomes
nervous optimism. Painting converts hysteria
by making it visible. At the same time, it
liberates the eye from its conventional
character 'as a fixed and qualified organ',
allowing it to become polyvalent and
indeterminate, so that we can detect other
presences, like the BwO or the Figure. This
is because 'Painting gives us eyes all over:
in the ear, in the stomach, in the lungs'
[which might be a philosophical way of
saying it engages the other senses]. These
subjective changes in our vision are
accompanied by objective presentations of
the reality of bodies, lines or colours. The
two changes are required simultaneously —
'the pure presence of the body becomes
visible at the same time that the eye
becomes the destined organ of this
presence'.
Conventional painting manages hysteria by
remaining within organic representation and
conventional figurative approaches, or
turning to abstract form and 'inventing a
properly pictorial cerebrality' (38). With
the latter, Velasquez remained with
conventional representation and offered
seeming documentaries. He was an important
influence on Bacon as with the portrait of
Pope Innocent X, and there are already
similarities between, say, the armchair and
the parallelepiped. Bacon lets loose
additional presences — 'the brute meat, and
the screaming mouth', showing the
relationship between hysteria and painting
'in full view'. [the example below is
convenient but not necessarily the best
Bacon to illustrate the point] Bacon
himself had doubts about the ethics of this
activity.
Can we talk about
hysteria as a purely aesthetic matter.
Doesn't music also 'extricate pure
presences', where the ear has become 'the
polyvalent organ for sonorous bodies'? What
about poetry and theatre, Artaud or Beckett?
For Deleuze, music involves our bodies in a
particular way — 'it disembodies bodies'
(39) as a way of overcoming the resistance
of any 'inert matter'. It does this in a
further direction then painting, hence its
'superiority'. Painting enables bodies to
escape only to discover their materiality.
Only eyes 'can attend to material existence
or material presence', but music does not
attend to the material reality of bodies,
and does not illustrate hysteria. Its
connection with spirituality arises from its
operation with disembodied bodies. There is
no equivalent to colour [although there
might be 'rudimentary or refined system of
correspondence between sounds and colours'].
Thus music is not hysterical, but rather
illustrates 'a galloping schizophrenia'.
Chapter 8 Painting
Forces
Despite their differences, there is a common
problem facing the arts — 'capturing forces'
(40), never simply a matter of reproducing
or inventing forms. Painting tries to make
invisible forces visible, music,
non-sonorous forces sonorous. Force is
related to sensation, and registers on the
body as a point on a wave. But the sensation
itself is different from the force, and the
trick is to use the sensation to capture
those insensible forces, to 'relax or
contract itself'. Sometimes, the problem
centres on depicting time, or 'the
elementary forces like pressure, inertia,
weight, attraction, gravitation,
germination'. Sometimes insensible forces
employ what is given in another art — 'how
to paint sound'.
This has long been known to painters. For
example Millet argued that the weights
common to two quite different objects was
more important than their 'figurative
distinction' (41). Cézanne too wanted to
render visible the forces that produced
landscapes. Van Gogh depicted 'the
unheard-of force of a sunflower seed'. An
allied problem was 'the decomposition and
recomposition of effects' — how to depict
depth, colour, or movement. Movement in
particular refers back to a force and also
to effects in the form of a multiplicity of
elements [Duchamp, above shows the whole
range of human movement]. The Figure in
Bacon is a response: it makes invisible
forces visible. Bacon is less interested in
depicting effects because he thinks that
painting things like movement have already
been developed adequately. We see the aim in
the series of heads and self portraits,
where external pressures, dilations,
contractions flattening and elongation
agitate the heads. These are 'like the
forces of the cosmos confronting an
intergalactic traveller immobile in his
capsule' (42). Invisible forces strike from
different angles, and the distorted parts of
the face can indicate the zone where the
force is striking. The technique is better
described as deformation not transformation,
something bodily and static, localized. It
also 'subordinates the abstract to the
Figure'. Instead of an abstract form, we get
a zone of indiscernibility, 'common to
several forms, irreducible to any of them',
yet offering clarity [and the example is
becoming–animal discussed earlier — two
clarities merged together]. Cézanne was
perhaps the first to do this, 'by making
truth fall back on the body' [indicating the
bodily effects of the true underlying
forces?]. For both, while the form is at
rest, the structure is moving, bending or
curling. The deformations should not be seen
as the result of torture, but rather as
natural postures exposed to forces like the
desire to sleep or vomit.
Bacon sees the scream as
particularly important, painting the
relationship between forces and the visible
scream [the screaming mouth]. The actual
spectacle is not important, but rather the
forces that produce spectacles, 'and that
even lie beyond pain and feeling' (43).
There is often a dilemma to paint either the
horror or the scream [there are musical
examples too]. Bacon attempts to show the
relationship between the visible open mouth
as an abyss, and visible forces, 'which are
nothing other than the forces of the future'
[with a reference to the same phrase in
Kafka. These future forces are anticipations
of some dreadful events to come?]. For
example, we scream at death, as an
example of coupling the scream and the
force.
Rejecting the violence of the spectacle can
be seen as 'a kind of declaration of faith
in life' which comes through in many of the
interviews, and is summarized by the phrase
about being cerebrally pessimistic, but
nervously optimistic. For him, figuration is
increasingly unimportant, and he reproaches
himself for painting too much horror. Of
course the invisible forces working on us
can be even more horrific — 'every piece of
meat testifies to this' (44). But Bacon
shows these powers as [realized],
concentrated on a body that struggles — 'the
struggle with the shadow is the only real
struggle'. In this way, the visual can
overcome invisible forces. Death is not a
horrific unknowable force, but rather one
'that life detects, flushes out, and makes
visible through the scream'. Bacon does not
believe in death, but sees it is serving
life [Beckett and Kafka do the same]. The
painted Figures are 'indomitable', insistent
and present, and even capable of laughter.
We can read Bacon's paintings to get 'an
empirical list of the forces Bacon detects
and captures' — isolation becoming visible
from the wrapping effects of the field;
deformation, visible only when 'the head
shakes off its face, or the body its
organism'; dissipation as Figures dissolve
into fields, sometimes represented by 'the
strange smile'. There may be other forces
indicated in the coupling between bodies
expressed as a diagram, or revealed only in
triptychs. This is a force like the one
exerted by the light, that both separates
and illuminates. Bacon makes time visible
both through the 'allotropic variation of
bodies' in deformation, and then as some
eternity uniting and separating in the
triptychs in that force.
Chapter 9 Couples and
Triptychs
Since sensations are the result of waves of
force, they can also communicate. Resonance is
one form [I am still unhappy with this except
as some general metaphor -- for one thing,
resonance is not the only form of sympathetic
oscillation, which include the interference
patterns beloved by Barad,who sees them as
universal. For another -- physical, optical
and electro-magnetic forms of resonance
clearly involve transmitting forces. As a
metaphor, I am not sure if Deleuze is
suggesting amplification of sensations,
reciprocation, interference patterns or all 3.
I think he likes the term because it just
suggests some mysterious interactions between
forces, about as precise as 'life force' ].
Thus two Figures can be coupled with coupled
sensations, despite sharing a 'matter of fact'
(46). There is always a danger of having
several Figures because that might reintroduce
narrative, but they can still show relations,
remembering that 'what is painted is the
sensation'.
So where there are entangled Figures, there is
no merger but rather an indiscernibility
provided by precise lines which almost become
autonomous, a diagram. There is no story. [See
below]. Even single Figures show can show
different levels of sensation, implying a kind
of coupling [referring to the crucifixion
scene above]. Figures can be coupled with
their animals.
There is a link to Proust and involuntary
memory. Proust also did not want an abstract
philosophical literature or a figurative or
narrative one. He wanted 'a kind of Figure,
torn away from figuration and stripped of
every figurative function… For example the
Figure–in–itself of Combray' (47). To rely
only on voluntary memory is to risk
illustrating or narrating the past. For
Proust, involuntary memory linked to
sensations at different levels of the body —
the present and the past sensation which when
related produce something irreducible to
either of them [their location in past or
present became 'of little importance' (48)].
Some sensations did not appeal to memory at
all [the examples are paintings or Vinteuil's
music] and there are moments where two
sensations resonate in music, such as the
violin and the piano: the Sonata becomes a
Figure, as does the septet, relating spiritual
calling with bodily pain. The two sensations
are coupled together 'like "wrestlers"… a
"combat of energies"', together producing 'an
ineffable essence, a resonance, an epiphany'.
Proust imprisoned [Combray {'in a cup of tea'}
or Albertine] 'in order to capture their
colours'.
Bacon does not like to paint the dead, or to
paint people in front of him. He prefers
photographs or memories, but memory is not
actually key itself — it is the confrontation
of two sensations, not always negative. Desire
can mix together sensations as can 'sleeping…
art': 'places of a struggle'.
What about the triptych? There is a relation
between separated parts, again neither
narrative no logical, no progression. There is
'a common fact that [unites] diverse
Figures'(49). The figures do not resonate.
There are 'nonnarrative relations… matters of
fact or common facts'. We should not impose a
narrative on Man and Child, for
example — maybe we are being shown all
possible narrations. Here the fact of the
painting must include the separation of
Figures. Maybe the girl is an attendant,
neither observer nor spectator, but only 'a
constant, a measure or cadence' against which
we can assess variation (50). The girl is
stiff while the man seems to be in motion..
Beckett has attendants too [characters who
seem to comment or interrogate themselves].
The attendant can be the circus ring or
camera, sometimes two or more if there are
several Figures.
We get the three rhythms mentioned earlier —
active, passive and attendant. These are not
located in the Figure, indeed [given the
necessary philosophical sensibilities] 'it is
rhythm itself that will become the Figure'
[with another link to Messiaen claiming that
he uses different rhythms as characters, one
active, one passive, one attendant inactive].
The triptych was itself once mobile [movable
wings?]. Bacon however 'makes the triptych
equivalent' [!] to music rather than
furniture, distributing three basic rhythms in
a fundamentally circular organization. So
Bacon paints sensations, 'essentially rhythm'
initially in the Figure: 'the vibration that
flows through the body without organs' (51).
In coupling of sensation rhythm is partly
liberated as resonance, but still constrained
by 'the melodic lines, the points and
counterpoints of a coupled Figure;it is the
diagram of the coupled figure'. In the
triptychs, rhythm is amplified in a forced
movement 'which gives it an autonomy, and
produces in us the impression of time' [pass]
sensations now have no limits as figures are
placed in all sorts of directions. This in
turn produces 'recomposition or
redistribution' so that the rhythm itself
becomes sensation or Figure. Apparently
Rembrandt and Soutine offered earlier versions
— residences in layers, amplitude of light,
the distribution of active passive and
attendant Figures in the Night Watch,
even in still lives, where glasses can be
attendants, with spirals of lemon and
mother-of-pearl opposing each other.
Chapter 10 Note: What Is
a triptych?
[An absurd pseudoscientific opening paragraph
saying 'the hypothesis must be verified {about
the three rhythms}... We can respond to this
question only through an empirical study of
the triptychs'. The paintings are empirical
'facts': Deleuze takes Bacon at his naive word
here. He actually relies on lots of other
words in texts as well Bacon's
interviews and other commentaries on other
painters as seen in the notes. He has already
deployed non-empirical concepts like BwO. He
has not the faintest idea how to verify
hypotheses with empirical data, of course, and
covers his back already: 'since this order, if
it exists, combines many variables, we must
expect it to present very diverse aspects'
(53). It is clear that no empirical example
will ever falsify the hypothesis, and that any
apparent exception can be explained simply as
one of the many diverse aspects and
combinations].
There are different sorts of attendants [and
there are many examples referring to
characters, nude and clothed, observers and
photographers, simulacra of portraits]. There
is another kind of attendant function as well,
something 'more profound', something that sees
the more superficial attendant. The attendant
function turns on 'horizontality, it's almost
constant level'. This can offer a rhythm that
works in two directions ['retrogradable in
itself'] and does not increase or decrease:
the other rhythms of vertical and are
'retrogradable only in relation to each other'
(54).
We find the horizontal feature in the
triptychs — the 'flat hysterical smile' for
example. We are also presented with
horizontals that offer a translation from one
panel to the next, may be as 'a prone body' or
a flattening force [lots of examples to
illustrate]. There can be a 'horizontal
diagram' of couples as in Sweeney
Agonistes [below -- apparently the title
of a poem by TS Eliott]. The very complexity
shows 'an underlying law', where attendant
rhythms appear first as visible characters,
later as a separate 'rhythmic character'. That
can happen when something with an active or
passive rhythm acquires an attendant function
— the sleeping characters can also show
activity or passivity, vivacity [Sweeney
again]. Sometimes characters cease to be
attendants and can acquire other
characteristics — they also rise or fall, or
change.
The other rhythms, active and passive, are
found in a vertical dimension, sometimes
simply depicted with descending or inverted
heads, sometimes by recumbent forms next to
one that appears to rise up from its shadow or
descend into a puddle. These will be examples
of 'a diastolic – systolic opposition'(55),
linked contractions or expansions, sometimes
where particular figures are depicted very
contracted. The Studies of the Male Back
shows some oppositions between something large
and relaxed on the left and tense on the
right, with the centre panel remaining
constant [I'm not sure this is the one he
means].
Other oppositions include those between naked
and clothed figures, which stands for the
'augmentation-diminution opposition' (56).
This can also be indicated by apparently
random extra 'spurts of paint', or missing
portions of Figures, a whole 'game of added
and subtracted values'. These are 'Bacon's
most profoundly musical paintings'.
The oppositions are not equivalent, but rather
offer a 'combinatorial freedom' (57), so a
discharge [the example seems to mean the
discharge of vomit] can be a descent as well
as a dilatation and expansion, and can also
stand in opposition to other figures as a
contraction. 'Everything can coexist and the
opposition can vary or even be reversed
depending on the viewpoint one adopts, that
is, depending on the value one considers'
[quite so]. What remains common is that one
rhythm is a retrogradation of the other, set
against a constant attendant rhythm.
Within the variability, 'in Bacon, primacy is
given to the descent… It is the active that
descends'. [To cover his back --sorry]
sometimes, the descent can refer to sensation
rather than a descent in space. Many other
artists have depicted a difference of
intensity in sensation as a fall [a note
refers us to another commentary]. With Bacon,
flesh descends from bones and sensation
develops by falling from one level to another.
We should not understand the fall in
thermodynamic terms, as entropy, but merely as
emphasizing the difference in level as such.
It shows us the experience of tension [with an
obscure reference to Kant page 58, who
apparently argued that the plurality of
intensity could only be grasped by reference
to negation] — even attaining a maximum is
experiencing a kind of fall. It is the 'most
inward movement or "clinamen" of sensation',
not a matter of misery or failure, and it is
not the same as a fall in space 'except for
convenience and humour' [so I think we've
covered all the grounds]. Thus an intensive
fall can also 'coincide… with a rise', both a
diastole and a systole, because it is 'the
active rhythm'. It follows that 'everything
that develops is a fall', which makes it
possible to identify in each painting what
counts as the fall, although this will vary
from one painting to another. There will also
always be an opposable character to assume the
role of a passive rhythm.
We are now going to summarize the 'laws of the
triptych, whose necessities grounding in the
coexistence of the three panels' [roughly that
there are three rhythms; one is an attendant
rhythm which can circulate through the
painting both as visible characters and
something that is just rhythmic; and that
there are active and passive rhythms with a
number of variations]. Naturally, 'these laws
have nothing to do with the conscious formula'
but are rather a part of 'this irrational
logic, or this logic of sensation, that
constitutes painting' (59). They are not
simple or voluntary, they do not follow the
same succession, say from left to right, nor
is the centre panel always given a 'univocal
role'. What they imply changes. They are found
in extremely variable terms, affected both by
'their nature and their relations'. We end
with a state of complex forces.
Which forces are triptychs specifically
responding to? We have already spotted forces
of isolation and formation and dissipation
between Figure and structure, and movements
between Figures like coupling and deformation.
But there is a third movement and force in
triptychs, even though it can include the
others. It turns on the relations between
Figures 'which are violently projected onto
the field, and are now governed by the uniform
colour or the naked light'. The Figures appear
'like trapeze artists whose milieu is no
longer anything but light and colour' [Three
Bodies,below] [Deleuze also
notes a 'rare exception']. The light and
colour both unifies and separates the Figures,
'a force of separation or division sweeps over
them' and this is not the same as isolation.
Overall we find 'the maximum unity of light
and colour the maximum division of Figures'.
Rembrandt also realized that light can produce
'rhythmic characters' [in the Night
Watch, apparently].
The body of the Figure therefore 'passes
through three levels of force', seen best in
the triptych. We have primary 'facts' however
— the Figure which is to be submitted to
forces, then 'first "matter of fact"', where
two Figures are coupled. Finally, in the
triptychs, the bodies are separated in
'universal light and universal colour that
becomes the common fact'. This is both unity
and separation, shown in paint as 'the colour
field separate while falling into the white
light'. Everything becomes aerial. Time is
only depicted as 'monochromatic eternity. An
immense space-time unites all things' but only
by also introducing the notion of distance,
both in the landscapes and in the panels of
the triptych. The three panels are separated
but not isolated, the borders refer to the
'distributive unity of the three'. This
triptych form is [somehow] universal in Bacon.
Chapter 11 The Painting before Painting…
[The famous one about clichés]. The painter
never works on a blank canvas, which is why
figurative painting doesn't work if it claims
to just represent external objects. There are
many other things in the painter's studio or
'in his head' (61) and these are present 'more
or less virtually, more or less actually,
before he begins his work'. Painters have to
empty the canvas first, to over paint images
that are already there, to replace 'all those
"givens"', which appear as an obstacle as much
as a help.
There are for example, 'figurative givens',
arising from earlier paintings or photographs,
television and so on. This provides us with
'psychic clichés… Ready-made perceptions,
memories, phantasms'. 'clichés are already on
the canvas'(62). It is no good just trying to
transform or deform them because 'this
reaction is still too intellectual, too
abstract', and the cliché can be resurrected.
At best we can parody.
[Then a long quote from DH Lawrence on
Cézanne, 62 – 63. Cézanne wanted to spend his
life painting a real apple rather than clichés
of an apple. He went through deliberate
distortions sometimes parodies. Apparently
'"he wanted true to life representation. Only
he wanted it more true to life"'. Photographic
conventions were already obstacles to this.
Sometimes, apparently he managed to give '"a
complete intuitive interpretation of actual
objects… The real appleyness"' (63), but this
can never just be imitated].
It is worse now that images have multiplied,
and 'even the reactions against clichés are
creating clichés'; abstract painting produced
its own clichés. Lots of other people know
this, and 'the Japanese know that whole life
barely suffices for a single blade of grass'
[!]. Painters experience painting as a
struggle and are often extremely critical of
their own work, including Bacon.
Bacon likes and uses photographs, but sees
them as having no aesthetic value, which is
why he likes the documentary kind like
Muybridge, even if they are illustrative or
narrative. However, Bacon sees that
photographs work in two ways — 'by resemblance
or by convention, through analogy or through a
code' [sounds like the classic iconic
signifier, although that has both rather than
either/or]. They also take on an existence of
their own, which can dominate perception, in
this case people or landscapes that are being
depicted: 'what we see, what we perceive are
photographs' (64). Photographs make
implausible or doctored images appear as
truth. Bacon celebrates these developments.
For him photographs are something that exist,
imposing themselves upon perceptions and thus
being able to 'lay claim to aesthetic
pretensions'. They do not succeed because they
reduce sensation to just the one level [needs
much more explanation. A note on page 133
refers to Foucault's essay on photography and
painting, and notes cases where painters
integrate photographs or the action of
photography. Seems to me to be little more
than an argument that visual realism is
never realistic. Deleuze seems to have a
different emphasis in the books on cinema,
possibly because movement adds levels?]. Art
offers a different sort of deformation [but
Eisenstein is mentioned as an exception,
possibly because the famous shot of the
wounded nurse in Battleship Potemkin
has been borrowed for one of Bacon's scream
paintings?]
Bacon has not attempted to integrate the
photograph into the creative process. He does
paint things that seem to function as a
photograph, as attendants — cameras, a rifle.
But photographs on their own are more
valuable. So they cannot be left behind or
transformed. Better to understand them as 'so
many pre-pictorial givens' (65)
It is necessary first to develop '"the will to
lose the will"' [apparently a phrase Bacon
uses in the interviews], to go beyond the
givens. This seems to be particularly suitable
with photographs, although different givens
require similar stances. Bacon talks about
chance for example, which he uses to develop
'rules for rejection and very precise action'.
It is not the normal understanding of chance,
however. Chance has two parts, with only the
second found in painting. We understand the
first notion by thinking of the blank canvas
as offering somewhere where 'all the places on
it seem to be equivalent… all equally
"probable"' (66), limited only by the
definitions of the canvas itself, its limits
or centre. What the painter wants to do, 'what
he has in his head', then privileges
particular places, the 'pre-pictorial idea'.
This introduces a distribution of equal and
unequal probabilities. The trick seems to be
to make the unequal probability 'almost a
certitude'. Painters can then proceed, but
they still have to beware the cliché. They can
use '"free marks"', commonly referred to by
Bacon, made quickly, 'so as to destroy the
nascent figuration… And give the Figure a
chance, which is the improbable itself'. The
marks are accidental, by chance [what would
Freudians say about that?] in a special sense,
no longer designating abstract possibilities,
but referring to 'type of choice or action
without probability' [is this not really
choosing the improbable rather than another
kind of chance, although the free marks
introduce certain nonrepresentative marks].
These marks are made by the hand of the
painter [without thought?]. They help the
visual image of the Figure emerge. But it is
accident and chance in the second sense that
are at work. Bacon apparently refers to
'manipulated chance, as opposed to conceived
or seen probabilities'[Much of this appears to
be based on a theory by a certain Servien who
distinguished probabilities, which can be
calculated, 'and which concern the dice before
they are thrown', and chance which he
understands as 'the type of choice,
nonscientific and yet non-aesthetic'. This
seems to me to be another way of describing
the effects of the Unconscious. It might link
with the several other commentaries about dice
throws? This seems 'spontaneously close to
Bacon's conceptions, and seems to be
distinctive against those who see 'art as
play']. Much depends on whether the game
offers combinatorial moves like chess, or
throw-by-throw moves like roulette. For Bacon,
art is roulette, played at three tables, like
the three panels of the triptych.
So there is 'a set of probabilistic visual
givens', and Bacon can 'abandon himself' to
them. They are pre-pictorial and will not be
integrated into the painting itself. However
the choice made at each move becomes
pictorial, appearing as manual marks that
reorientate the visual, and will eventually
'extract the improbable Figure from the set of
figurative probabilities' (67) [seems pretty
similar to the deliberate introduction of
random elements, like found art or even like
Roussel's writings? But..]. This has often led
to misunderstanding when Bacon talks about
chance. For example Duchamp used a technique
to let three threads fall on the painting.
This would be using the pre-pictorial givens
as part of the painting, not what Bacon does.
When asked if anyone could make random marks,
Bacon replied that they could do so
abstractly, but would not know 'how to utilize
this chance or how to manipulate it'. It needs
manipulation to turn chance into something
pictorial, an act of painting. Bacon was to
insist that there is only manipulated chance
or utilised accident, against the views of his
colleagues and friends.
So what we see is a stance of 'reckless,
almost hysterical abandon' towards clichés and
probabilities, which are always there. The
painter must fully embrace them ['must enter
into the canvas before beginning']. He knows
what he wants to do, but does not initially
know how to get there, requiring a step out of
the canvas. In this sense, we are always in
the canvas, in the pre-pictorial, but the
trick is to get out of cliché and probability.
Random manual marks give him a chance [sic] to
do this, even though they can actually add
nothing or even 'botch' the painting (68).
To fight against clichés requires 'much guile,
perseverance, and prudence' renewed at every
moment of every painting. 'It is the way of
the Figure' [pass!]. It is not enough to
abstract from the figurative. The Figure is
always still figurative, it represents
something and narrates something [quite so,
especially for the viewer, although Bacon
hopes that these representations and
narrations are not the conventional ones. For
him they might even include 'a surrealistic
tale (head – umbrella – meat...)'. Overall,
there is a complex opposition of the Figure to
the figurative [rather than admitting that
Bacon has failed to fully oppose them], one
that does not compromise the opposition. First
there is a pre-pictorial figuration, a cliché,
a probability, which can never be 'completely
eliminated'. But there is a second figuration
arising from the act of painting, and this
time it is the 'result of the Figure… an
effect of the pictorial act' [well I can see
that it's an effect of an act, but making it
the result of the Figure is just excessive
philosophising?]. There is a 'pure presence of
the Figure', a representation that has been
reconstituted, a figuration that has been
recreated. The photograph does the first
figuration but is not adequate to reality, and
has to be recovered. This takes place only
after 'a leap in place… a deformation in
place, the emergence in place of the Figure:
the pictorial act'. The painters 'know how' is
crucial [a method], to disorganize and deform
first figurations, before restoring them to a
whole. Painting is an act that reunites free
manual traits and the visual whole. The traits
are important first to enable the creative
elements of figuration. Bacon says the formula
is 'create resemblance, but through accidental
and non-resembling means' (69). Painting
constantly oscillates between a beforehand and
an afterward, 'the hysteria of painting'.
Everything is already there, but the painter
has to be engage in 'manual labour' (sic) to
make the Figure emerge.
Chapter 12 The Diagram
[In the Guattari sense? A sketch of virtual
forces? If so, hardly 'empirical' as in
Chapter 10 -- nor are concepts like the BwO or
becoming animal, of course]
Back to the theme about the battle between the
painter and the givens, requiring preparatory
work — sketches are the easiest example.
Actual painting comes afterwards. In Bacon's
case he makes random marks, scrubs or wipes
the canvas 'in order to clear out locales or
zones (colour patches)' (70), or throws paint.
The idea is to remove the givens, especially
the figurative ones. [Quoting an example
discussed in Bacon's own interviews] a mouth
can be elongated, and a space inserted into
it, a head partly cleared away.
Bacon called these graphs or diagrams and
talked about inserting zones into the head,
or using rhinoceros skin as a pattern. For
Deleuze, 'cosmic units were substituted for
the figurative unit' (71). The
idea is to induce a catastrophe in the middle
of all the givens.
The marks are 'irrational, involuntary,
accidental, free, random' [very odd thing to
say]. They are 'a-signifying',
nonrepresentative or nonnarrative. They are
'manual traits', where, 'it is as if'[!] the
hand is independent of will or sight, and is
'guided by other forces'. They 'attest to the
intrusion of another world'. They break with
conventional optical figurative organization.
As a result, there is only 'a catastrophe,
chaos'. There are still two risks of failure,
Bacon says, to remain with the conventional
figurative and optical organization, or to
overload the diagram. When it works well we
have a diagram as 'the operative set of
a-signifying and nonrepresentative lines and
zones, line strokes and colour patches'. This
is to be suggestive or to raise other
possibilities, but diagrams must be used in
order to take the next step to constitute
something ['(the pictorial fact)' (72)], or a
Figure. Just as the object is no longer
figurative, so the eye gains 'another power'.
A diagram in Van Gogh might consist of sets of
'straight and curved hatch marks' that will
'raise or lower the ground, twist the trees,
or make the sky palpitate'. Painters can
become more or less aware of using a diagram.
Diagrams produce both chaos and 'a germ of
order or rhythm', or in Bacon's words 'it
"unlocks areas of sensation."'. It is
preparatory work. All painters have
experienced the contradictory effects, as 'a
properly pictorial experience' not just a
psychic one. The dangers are faced continually
in Cézanne or Klee. Painting is the only art
that 'necessarily integrates its own
catastrophe', although painters vary in terms
of how they embrace chaos.
There might in fact be three 'great paths' to
designate modern painting. The first is
abstraction, which reduces the abyss and the
manual to a minimum, acting as 'an asceticism,
a spiritual salvation' (73). This helps us
just cross over chaos to produce 'a new and
purely optical space' with no manual or
tactile elements. The shapes do still possess
tension, however, as a depiction of manual
movement and invisible forces. Abstract
painting develops 'a symbolic code' rather
than a diagram, something digital, units that
are often grouped in terms of opposition
['according to Kandinsky,
vertical–white–activity,
horizontal-black–inertia, and so on']. There
are even attempts to develop an explicit
visual code, like Herbin's plastic alphabet
[which looks really gripping]. Abstraction is
the answer to chaos, tumult and the abyss: it
opens up 'a spiritual state for the man of the
future, a man without hands', operating in 'a
pure and internal optical space', as a
sanctuary.
The second path is 'abstract expressionism or
art informel'. This uses the abyss or
the chaos to produce the totality of the
painting. There is only a diagram. The lines
are manual rather than based on optical
geometry, and lines and patches delimit
nothing [examples, page 74, include Pollock
and the northern Gothic line again]: there's
nothing else on the surface. It is less
figurative than abstract art [which still uses
lines to depict outlines]. Classical painters
refer to this as '"to paint between things"'
[quoting an art historian on Velasquez].
Turner's late watercolours can be seen to be
'an unparalleled catastrophe'. Kandinsky and
Mondrian offer lines and shapes without
contours. Pollock offers 'a decomposition of
matter' itself, exposing all its granulations.
The diagram is closest to catastrophe and here
'modern man discovers rhythm' in the form of
'a manual power that is spread out "all
over"'. Rhythm emerges 'as matter and
material'. The hand is liberated, or the body
is in action painting. The easel is abandoned
in favour of material on the ground. The
tactile dominates the optical. In Pollock it
is tending towards the diagram dominating the
whole of the painting, replacing the notion of
preparatory work; the rejection of visual
sovereignty or even visual control; the
development of lines that are more than lines
[examples of fibres, laminations or strata on
page 75].
American critics see abstract expressionism as
particularly relevant to modern man, in that
pictorial space loses tactile referents [and
thus notions of depth and contour] found in
classical painting. Although they might have
liberated a space which they saw as purely
optical, it is still a manual space, on a
canvas that is planar and impenetrable, using
colour that is still gestural. The eye cannot
rest in this space, which is 'the manual space
of what is seen, of violence done to the eye'.
Abstract painting did more to escape the
tactile, leaving the eye to do representation.
We see here a modern tendency to dispense with
the easel, classically associated with
figurativeness, the painter as observer of
nature [maybe, page 76], and a conventional
delimitation and internal organization. For
Mondrian, the painting 'must create its own
relations with the divisions of the room in
which it will be hung', so he's really doing
something more like mural painting. Pollock
rediscovers the Gothic line and creates 'an
entire world of equal probabilities': their
lines start and continue off the frame, they
break with 'organic notions of symmetry' in
favour of 'mechanical repetition elevated to
intuition.' Bacon develops the triptych to
both unite and separate.
The third option is represented by Bacon. He
does not like paintings that have visual and
spatial code instead of involuntary diagrams,
because this makes them 'inevitably cerebral',
lacking sensation, no chance of any 'direct
action upon the nervous system', no tension
[it has been internalized in the optical forms
and thus neutralized]. Abstract codes can be
reduced to 'symbolic coding of the figurative'
(77). Abstract expressionism means the diagram
will cover the entire painting: the methods
are violent and messy, and sensations of time
confused. For Bacon, the diagram must not
proliferate. The contour must be saved, the
diagram must remain controlled, catastrophe
must not submerge the whole. The diagram
offers 'the possibility of fact — it is not
the fact itself'. Some figurative givens must
remain, to let the Figure emerge which will
'make the sensation clear and precise'. We
must emerge from the catastrophe.
The malerisch period was when Bacon
got closest to letting the diagram cover the
painting, but even there, clear Figures and
rigorous contours can be found, with 'power of
vibration and non-localization (the mouth that
smiles or screams)'. The localization of
random traits and scrubbed zones are 'a third
path… neither optical… nor manual'.
Chapter 13 Analogy.
So we need a diagram which is not reduced to a
code but nor does it cover the entire
painting. Cézanne developed such a middle way,
retaining both the experience of chaos and
'fighting to limit and control it at any
price' (78). [Deleuze admits that preparatory
work is necessary 'in that we are no longer
"innocent"']. We can think of it as an
emerging geometry or geology, which then
organizes colours 'for the earth to rise
towards the sun' [quoting a commentary on
Cézanne]. There is a notion of temporality,
but also an indissoluble connection between
these two moments: 'the geometry is its
"frame" and colour is the sensation'.
Cézanne called this 'the motif', consisting of
both sensation and frame intertwined.
Sensation on its own is not enough because
sensations are 'ephemeral and confused'
[leading to a critique of Impressionism,
extended in a note on page 136]. The frame
alone is too abstract. Sensations must be
given 'duration and clarity', and the geometry
must be 'made concrete or felt' (79), in a
process or relation.
To make this possible, we must see geometry as
having 'properly pictorial uses'. We have
already argued that there can be a digital
code from the basic units [lines and other
geometric forms]. These are not just
mathematical arrangements, but 'are indeed
aesthetic' because they 'internalize a manual
movement'. However painting is turned into a
code as we see best with abstract painting
[and there is a quotation from a certain
Sérusier that the point is to reduce all forms
to the smallest number of constituent forms —
lines, arcs, angles]. Cézanne reversed the
emphasis, suggesting that cylinders spheres or
cones could be used to '"treat nature"',
especially to paint volumes, like stovepipes
or arms. This is an analogical use of geometry
not digital [and much discussion then goes on
about the difference — sometimes analogical
means analogue].
[First a lot of pants about brains —
analogical language belongs to the right
hemisphere, 'or, better, to the nervous
system', whereas digital belongs to the left].
Analogical language features relations of
things like 'expressive movements,
paralinguistic signs, breaths and screams'.
Artaud's theatre shows that a language can be
developed from these [hmm --by definition I
assume]. Painting elevates colours and lines
to a state of analogical language. When we
think of animal language, the analogical
dimension refers to their use of 'cries,
variable colours, and lines (attitudes,
postures)' (80).
It is not just a matter of convention for
digital and resemblance for analogical
languages, since gestures do not just resemble
what they signal. Nor is it just a matter that
digital languages need to be learned, whereas
analogical languages seem obvious, produced by
'a certain presence that makes itself felt
immediately'; However, the analogical requires
an apprenticeship too, as painting itself
shows. So, instead of 'a clear-cut theory' we
must turn to 'practical studies' [!].
Digital language can be used to do several
things — combine abstract elements, combine
elements to produce a message or narrative,
which implies 'an isomorphic relation to a
referential set' (80), or produce an
autonomous result from the possibilities of
the code itself [the example is a portrait
produced by a computer: Bacon refers to a
'"shorthand of figuration"'. I think better
examples would be the ways in which film
produces emergent qualities from the
technological potentials of the equipment. I
would also think that digital processes allow
much more innovation and transversalism but it
also ends in idealism?]. So codes can imply
analogy, isomorphism or resemblance.
Similarly, an analogy has two forms depending
on whether resemblance produces or is itself
the product. In the first case, the relations
between the elements of one thing produce an
image of it in another thing, having been made
to 'pass directly', as in photographs which
capture relations of light. Resemblances might
be deliberately left loose or decomposed, but
analogy 'is figurative' and resemblances
primary to it. In the other case, resemblance
can appear from 'non-resembling means' (81),
as when the code produces something from its
own internal potentials: the resemblance is
produced by 'completely different relations'.
This can also be applied to sensation — the
resemblance arises by being produced
sensually, not as a symbolic product of a
code. This is 'aesthetic Analogy' — it does
not feature resemblance nor code and is 'both
nonfigurative and non-codified'.
[Then a brief discussion on CS Peirce, and how
icons based on isomorphism can still develop
general qualities and therefore become more
like diagrams]. Musical synthesisers show
these differences. Analogical ones are
modular, connecting different elements which
are all 'actual and sensible'. Digital
synthesisers have to codify first, and the
'plane' depicting possible combinations is
infinite. The first kind can use filters to
modify the 'basic colour of a sound', its
timbre, usually by subtracting frequencies,
but digital ones have additional possibilities
to add new elements, to synthesize a range of
previously codified elements. What they have
in common is the ability to modulate, not just
deliver simple [realist] resemblance [conveyed
in a typically baffling sentence referring to
'intensive subtractions… an addition of
subtractions that constitutes modulation and
sensible movement as a fall' — the note on
page 137 refers to a French commentary on
digital and analytic syntheses].
Painting is 'the analogical art par
excellence' (82), and it helps analogy find
its own language through a diagram. Sometimes
there are mixtures in actual paintings, where
abstract painting is codified and programmed,
but also contain elements which are more than
just the code — 'the abstractionists often
happen to be great painters'. We have a kind
of 'digital expression of the analogical'
where analogies pass through codes not
diagrams. Similarly, art informel
extends the diagram to the entire painting so
that it becomes a diagram for the analogical
flux, not something that mediates it.
Happily there are middle ways where diagrams
constitute analogical language, and we return
to Cézanne. This is not a conservative middle
way, however. As 'an analogical language,
painting has three dimensions': planes and
their connections, 'which replaces
perspective'; colour 'which tends to suppress
[realist] relations of value and contrasts of
shadow and light'; the body 'which exceeds the
organism and destroys the form–background
relationship'. It is a form of liberation for
all three, born from an initial catastrophe
and then diagram, where planes collide,
colours become confused, and bodies
off-balance, 'in a state of perpetual fall'
(83). However, to avoid complete chaos, planes
still offer conventional junctions, bodies
regain balance in a deformation not
transformation, and modulation can find
meaning in a technical formula, 'the law of
Analogy'. It is not just a matter of breaking
from black-and-white and shading to depict
relief — there are new types of relief. In
Cézanne's case, there was apparently an
operation to juxtapose tints 'brought together
in the order of the spectrum' to depict both
expansion and contraction, connected to
horizontal and vertical planes, a contraction
experienced by the body as a point of
imbalance or fall. The sensation has been
realized for Cézanne [way beyond my competence
here, but, according to Smith P. (1996) Interpreting
Cézanne. London: Tate Publishing,
Cézanne used colour to depict contours and
distances etc but also had a separate notion
that colours had a natural harmony which was
natural -- as the sun moved across the sky,
colours modulated into tints of various
harmonic kinds. He wanted to impose this
schemes on the paint regardless of other
colour functions to make a sensation -- a
compound of something found in nature and a
feeling or emotion we attached to it {as in
topophilia -- he attached his own values to
his local landscape for example}]
Bacon is obviously different from Cézanne. He
offers shallow or superficial depths by
joining or even merging vertical and
horizontal planes. Colour appears as modulated
flat patches and also as large surfaces or
fields, 'which imply axes, structures or
armatures', changing nature through
modulation. There are different forces
exercised on bodies. However Bacon has also
elaborated painting as analogical language. He
does not operate with a code, but produces
true motifs ['the conic scream that combines
with the verticals, and the extended
triangular smile that merges with the
horizontals' (84)]. But the whole painting is
analogical, especially in the treatment of
colours, which are no longer relations of
value of light and shadow. Black and white
become 'liberated', turned into true colours,
offering presence and density, or intense
clarity respectively. There can still be
relief or contours, but these have new
functions to relate armatures with bodies, 'a
relation of coexistence or proximity modulated
by colour'. Contours can become membranes as
we saw. Here the diagram does not code, but
rather modulates. Its 'involuntary manual
order' breaks with conventional figures, but
at the same time, it 'defines [new]
possibilities of fact' [no doubt in the Bacon
sense of fact -- I still don't see why this is
left uncriticized along the usual
anti-positivists lines]. Lines are liberated
to become armatures, colours are used in
modulation; together, the Figure can be
produced, as 'the new resemblance inside the
visual whole', but as the realization of a
diagram.
Chapter 14 Every Painter
Recapitulates the History of Painting in His
or Her Own Way…
We can start with the Egyptians and their art
as 'an assemblage of bas-relief' (85).
According to somebody called Riegl, this
linked hand and eye, allowing 'the eye to
function like the sense of touch… A tactile,
or rather haptic function'. This is best
revealed in the 'frontal and close view… Since
the form and the ground lie on the same plane
of the surface, equally close to each other
and to ourselves', both separated and unified
by the contour as 'the common limit'. Regular
curves, rectilinear contours, isolates one
form as an essence, 'a closed unity' that
never changes. There is also an attempt to
'incorporate volume by covering the funerary
cube with a pyramid'. The pyramid is to be
understood as a 'Figure that only reveals to
us the unitary surfaces of Isosceles triangles
on clearly limited sides' (86). These notions
of planar and linear essences extend to
animals, plants, 'the Sphinx and the Lotus'
which have 'perfect geometrical form' while
being mysterious, alluding to the 'mystery of
essence'.
In some senses Bacon is 'an Egyptian' — form
and ground lie on the same plane, the Figure
has presence, everything is depicted with
clarity. Bacon actually paints sphinxes. He
also thinks that essence or eternity
characterize art. His remark that he was
attracted by sculpture but realized that he
could do the same thing in painting. The
sculpture he had in mind clearly would have
had armatures, Figures and contours — Deleuze
thinks that would be 'a bas–relief type of
sculpture', although his Sphinx is not clear
but scrambled.
There are other influences from 'the entire
history of Western painting' [ambitious
project then]. Christianity subjected form or
Figure to 'a fundamental deformation'. God was
no longer a simple essence because he had been
incarnated. This also introduced into
Christianity 'the event, or even the
changeable, the accident'. This makes even
Christian painting familiar, so that the
painter can be 'indifferent to the religious
subject' and since God incarnates, he can be
depicted as objects [a note, page 138, extends
the idea that the beautiful must always
contain something accidental as well, as a
kind of original sin]. Man experiences himself
as an accident, implying a fall, and the
accident comes to dominate over the essence in
painting [a legacy of the Egyptian notion that
the form can indicate the essence, Deleuze
says]
Greek art had already distinguished planes,
invented perspective and relief. The optical
space here implies 'a distinct viewing that is
never frontal' (87), with form and ground on
different planes united by perspective.
Objects can overlap. 'Light and shadow fill up
space and make it rhythmic' [pass -- I'm still
unclear about this term -- a systematic
alternation of light and shadow?]. The contour
now depicts just the form and makes the
foreground primary. The accidental has been
organized optically into a phenomenon, 'a
"manifestation" of essence'. Painting has
discovered its own aesthetic laws and work is
both 'organic and organized, plastic'.
Figuration is one result, where the form
'expresses the organic life of man as subject'
[and as part of the organic world, a note on
138 suggests].
This optical space is no longer just haptic,
although it still has tactile values, but is
subordinated to vision: it is 'tactile–optical
space' (88) expressing not essence 'but
connection; that is the organic activity of
man' [supported by a quote from Maldiney, who
does a lot of work here]. The organic contour
becomes a mould, helping to develop a perfect
optical form. This does not vary by plays of
shadow and light. It is an individuated form,
operating 'through visual variations and
diverse points of view'. There are associated
with this 'an extraordinary set of properly
pictorial inventions'.
The way forward after this is either to
develop still further a purely optical space
no longer referred to tactility, or to 'the
imposition of of violent manual space'
reasserting the tactile — as in automatic
writing. We find both in Byzantine and Gothic
art. The claim becomes a background, and an
'active support of impalpable forms' depicted
increasingly by light and shadows. Eventually,
these 'rhythms of light and shadow' will
develop even more autonomy for optical forms.
The tactile is no longer relevant. 'Indistinct
zones become essential', even when objects are
depicted clearly, there is still some
communication with shadow, darkness and the
background 'and in a relationship that is
specifically optical' religious sentiment
changes as well, delivering a notion of
'spiritual assumption, a "grace" or "miracle"'
(89). There is a notion of more autonomous
composition. Essence and law is created, forms
transformed or transfigured, from dark to
light. There is a notion of disintegration in
composition, as things ascend into the light,
and this is the tradition that appears even in
abstract painting — 'disintegrating factors…
relations of value, of light and shadow, of
clarity and obscurity… an optical code'.
In the Barbarian or Gothic art organic
representation gives way, but not to the
purely optical, rather to the tactile — the
vital and violent Northern line, characterized
by speeds and changing direction, representing
'the most bizarre and intense kind of life, a
non-organic vitality' (90) [this is based on
Worringer}. The line is too complex to be a
simple line and the plane is no longer a
surface. Nor do contours outline things. The
line can be composed of certain strokes —
'traits of the body or the head, traits of
animality or humanity' which provide 'an
intense realism', but in the sense of
deformation not transformation. The line
becomes indiscernible, common to different
animals and also resulting from pure
abstraction. The principle is 'an operative
geometry of the trait or the accident' — the
line constantly encounters obstacles or
accidents, and must divert and sometimes
intensify. We have a manual space with 'manual
aggregates'. Sometimes the effect is to make
'the body exceed the organism', uniting
separate organisms, independently of optical
characteristics.
The tendencies towards pure optical and pure
manual spaces are not incompatible. Both
challenge classical representation, and both
discover 'new and complex combinations and
correlations' (91) [a baffling example follows
— realizing the potentials of light
independently of forms means that curved forms
can be 'decomposed into flat strokes that
change direction, or even into strokes
dispersed inside the mass' — referred to
Wolfllin]. The source of accidents becomes
unclear — the light or the manual line.
Apparently, if we look at a Rembrandt upside
down and close-up we will 'discover the manual
line as the reverse of optical light' [Try it
with the still life above?]
Colour complicates matters. It seems to be
purely optical and becomes increasingly
independent of the form. Colour can depict
additional relations: 'relations of value'
based on contrast, whether 'tones are dark or
light, saturated or rarefied'; 'relations of
tonality' based on the spectrum and the
opposition of colours, so that tones 'can be
defined as warm or cool'[discussed further in
a note on page 139]. These are constantly
mixed and combined [examples pages 91 – 92].
We find in Cézanne local tones, shadows and
lights, and then a 'sequence of tones in the
order of the spectrum, a pure modulation of
colour that tends to be self-sufficient' and a
note on page 140 has a debate on whether
Cézanne equated warm and cool with light and
dark]. Nevertheless, relations of value tend
to refer to the functions of distant vision,
and modulations of colour 'recreate(s) a
properly haptic function' where tones are
arranged in progressions and regressions.
Thus if relations of value dominate, we get
predominantly optical spaces, and with
relations of tonality we get more of 'haptic
space'. The same colour [tones of grey in this
case] will produce optical or haptic effects.
The haptic is not optical nor tactile in the
earlier senses. Warm and cool tones can even
imply 'eccentric or concentric movement of
expansion or contraction' and there are other
oppositions as well. For example, optical
spaces tend to deliver 'an intimacy' [a
familiarity?]. There is also a danger of
restoring narrative ['we represent what we
think we can touch, but we narrate what we
see, what seems to be happening in the light
or what we presume is happening in the
shadows' (93). Heading toward abstraction,
such as 'a pure code of black-and-white' is
one way to avoid this. Colourism offers a more
analogical alternative — the mould it offers
is also depicting modulation, 'a continuous
creation of space, the spatializing energy of
colour' [an equally baffling note on page 140
tries to describe the difference between
moulding and modulation, with the latter as 'a
continuous, temporal mould… A continuous and
perpetually variable manner']. Thus colourism
can avoid both narrative and conventional
figuration, and move closer 'to the pure state
of a pictorial "fact" which has nothing left
to narrate'. This follows from the
(re)constitution of the haptic function of
sight. Egyptian values have appeared in
these new forms.
Chapter 15 Bacon's Path
[Definitionally?] the work of [only] 'a
great painter' (94) should be grasped as a
form of 'historical recapitulation… stopping
points and passages, which are extracted from
or reconstitute an open sequence' [almost a
specific description of a plane of
consistency?] Thus Bacon has Egyptian
elements, although there is no search for
essence and 'humankind is an accident'.
Background is separated from foreground not
through classic perspective but through 'a
"shallow" depth'. This appears to break the
notion of the haptic world and inaugurate a
tactical – optical world, but eventually, 'a
pure optical world… tends to free itself'
(95), and forms are severed from tactical
connections. The dangers of figuration and
narration re-emerge. Bacon proceeds to cut
through the conventions of the tactical
optical or pure optical worlds in the form of
a manual diagram which overturns both optical
and tactile connections. He also constantly
tries to avoid the intimacy of homely
depictions, associated with the conventional
use of light and shadow [which is what I think
D means by 'chiaroscuro']. Zones of
indiscernibility are opposed to the optical
and represent 'an unbridled manual power… a
frenetic zone in which the hand is no longer
guided by the eye… [appearing] as chance,
accident, automatism or the involuntary'.
The diagram is a point of relative rest amidst
'immense agitation' (96). It can therefore act
'as a relay', remaining localized and
requiring something to emerge from it: 'the
diagram always has effects that go beyond it'.
It breaks with conventional optical relations
but must still become 'reinjected into the
visible whole', resulting in a haptic world,
where the values of warm and cool colour
indicate expansions and contractions. These
colours do 'not depend on the diagram' but
emerge from it.
The colourists are painters who 'substitute
relations of tonality relations of value',
operating with 'pure relations of colour' to
produce forms, shadows, lights and even time
[definitionally demonstrated best in the
'masterpieces']. Colourists do use black and
white, light and dark, but these are treated
as colours and show tonal relations. In
colourism proper, colour itself is the
variable relation, 'on which everything else
depends' (97). They push colour 'to its pure
internal relations (hot – cold, expansion –
contraction)' and everything else follows —
'Form and ground, light and shadow, bright and
dark. Colour produces a particular kind of
clarity, not tangible form or optical light
but the relation between 'complementary
colours' [a note on page 141 refers back to
Cézanne's method: 'he saw modelling as a
succession of colours progressing from warm to
cool. His great interest lay in determining
each of the colours exactly… [allowing] him to
observe oppositions down to half tones'. Van
Gogh by contrast experimented with 'broken
tones where complementary colours are mixed in
unequal proportions producing 'a variety of
grey', and this can be contrasted to new
complementary colours']. A particular kind of
sense is produced — 'a haptic site of
colour-space as opposed to the optical sight
of light–time'.
[Then a brief aside about the differences
between Newton and Goethe]. The 'practical
rules of colourism are… The abandonment of
local tone; the juxtaposition of un-blended
touches; the aspiration of each colour to
totality by appealing to its complementary
colour; the contrasting of colours;… the
prohibition of mixtures except to obtain a
"broken" tone; the juxtaposition of two
complementary or similar colours, one which is
broken and the other pure; the production of
light and even time through the unlimited
activity of colour; the production of clarity
through colour' [referred back to Gowing on
Cézanne]. A masterpiece combines different
tendencies — '(linear–tactile, luminist,
colourist)', sometimes differentiating and
opposing them. Colourism gives a haptic sense
back to sight, and uses terms like '"touch",
"vividness", "seizing hold of life",
"achieving clarity"'.
Cézanne risked reproducing a code with his
reliance on the order of the spectrum. There
were two additional 'demands' [from whom
exactly? Gowing again], for 'a homogeneous
ground and an aerial armature, perpendicular
to the chromatic progression'; 'the demand for
a singular or specific form which the size of
the colour patches seem to put in question'.
The problem arose with attempting to create
'large sections of homogeneous colour' to act
as fields, while experimenting with forms
[citing a certain G Duthuit], apparently
combining 'a "unity of vision" and a
singularised perception' (98) [then a learned
discussion about the differences between
Cézanne and Gauguin on the use of colour, and
a quote from van Gogh admitting to being an
arbitrary colourist]. Apparently, uniform
patches of colour imply 'a passage or tendency
with very fine differences of saturation',
while the volume of the form uses broken
tones, but this is 'another type of passage in
which the colour seems to have been fired and
baked in a kiln'. These are additional
modulations. This is rediscovered when we move
from landscapes to portraits, because 'the
flesh calls for broken tones' (99), and the
trick is to make these tones resonate with
uniform flat fields.
Bacon recognized the properties of flesh and
its colour and used broken tones to produce
the body, while bright tones produced the
armature or the field. The whole problem lies
in relating these two. In Bacon, vivid colours
act as shores and broken colours as flows.
Time itself is depicted in the chromatic
variation of broken tones and as eternity in
the monochrome of the fields. This is still
dangerous if the broken tones of the Figure of
blend and lose their clarity [an interesting
note on page 142 says that Bacon prefers oils
to acrylics because the latter are more
predictable]. This tendency can be found in
Gauguin and also in Bacon's malerisch period
[although Deleuze insists that for Bacon, dark
curtains and the like should be seen as
separating two planes, foreground and
background, and this preserves clarity, at
least 'in principle']. Bacon saw the danger
himself and moved to depict the shallow depth
separating the planes in a more haptic space.
Chapter 16 Note on Colour.
The three fundamental elements were the
armature, the Figure, and the contour. There
are other contours in some of the paintings
that seem to 'belong to' (101) the armature or
the figure, sometimes even suggesting a mould.
Deleuze prefers to think that the contour
relates to 'different modalities of colour'
and points in particular to a third element,
not a volume but a line — things like the
round areas, puddles, even the armchair. They
are all about colour and its modulation,
relations between colours.
The Figure at a Washbasin (below, has
been analyzed by a certain M Le Bot (102)
which refers to rivers of colour blocked by
reefs which confine and fix, 'broad flows of
colour' which result in 'a dynamic that makes
the gaze glide from the bright ochre to the
red'. [This work is also the only one I can
find that mentions the directional arrow,
fairly common in the paintings but unremarked
by Deleuze except here: the arrow shows the
direction of gaze]. For Deleuze, the ochre is
a background shore, while the contour is 'an
autonomous power', the crimson on which the
Figure is standing. The Figure itself is, as
before, a flow of broken tones. However there
are also 'secondary yet indispensable
elements'. One is the wash basin which cuts
across the field as 'a second autonomous
contour' surrounding the head. Another is the
pipe which divides the field of colour in
half. Then the blind occupying the shallow
depth between the field and the figure, making
the entire painting relate 'to one and the
same plane'. The broken tones in the Figure
incorporate the tones of the field and also of
the cushion and wash basin: 'It is a rich
communication of colours'.
Then we have to distinguish 'the mode of the
shore or the field' and its relation to the
armature. In the tryptitches we often see
fields of monochrome colours, as in the Three
Studies for Figures at a Crucifixion (below).
The relations between the colours are not just
those of value, not just varying in intensity
or saturation, according to proximity to
particular zones [presumably front and back,
for example, or lit and shaded]. Proximity is
depicted in several ways, however: sometimes
with 'clear-cut sections of another intensity
or even another colour' (103); sometimes by
limiting or containing the field by another
contour taking up a section of the painting.
Here, this contour 'still belongs to the
field' because it is less 'concise' than other
contours [the orange and red sections in 3
Studies again, especially on the left
panel?]. On other occasions the field is
interrupted by a thin bar [including in Washbasin
above] or by another band of colour.
In the 'purest pictorial situation', the field
is not sectioned or limited but covers the
entire painting. Other contours are
encompassed. These are 'truly aerial' and
depict 'a maximum of light like the eternity
of a monochrome time, "Chronochromie."'' (104)
[also the title of 'a work by Oliver Messiaen
incorporating 18 bird songs' we are told in a
note on page 143]. Sometimes, the field itself
can display 'subtle internal variations that
depend on relations of proximity' (104),
sometimes shown where a ribbon crosses a
field. The effect is to produce 'a kind of
temporal or successive perception of the field
itself'. Generally, though, the smaller and
more localised the contour, 'the more aerial
the triptych will be' [the 1970 Triptych
below is the example — 'the blue circle and
the ochre apparatuses seem to be suspended in
a sky'. There is also a temporal perception —
time is eternity.
Overall, a uniform field of colour can provide
a structure by displaying different zones of
proximity with contours. The armature is
something connected with both field and
horizontal plane defined by a large contour
'which implies an active presence of the
shallow depth' or 'the system of linear
apparatuses' that deny all depth [the 1970
Tryptitch again]. There are other devices,
where particular sections can sometimes
include a localised black section [although,
bafflingly, this can also be 'total or
constituting the entire field — Three
Studies for the Human Body above]. The
black section does the same as the curtains,
making 'the field of colour project itself
forward', filling the shallow depth. Other
examples show black sections retreating from
the field — no problem for Deleuze because it
merely shows 'that Bacon did not reach this
new formula for black all at once'.
When we look at Figures, we see flows of
colour, often as broken tones constituting
flesh [with one exception, apparently]. This
sets up an opposition to monochrome shores
with its vivid and pure flat colour. In
polychromatic colours blues and reds feature —
'precisely the dominant tones of meat' — in
bodies and heads. [One example is the portrait
of Miss Muriel Belcher, below].
This helps break with the
figurative possibilities, including the notion
of tragedy and suffering when painting meat
[undoubtedly an early aim for Bacon — what a
happy coincidence between his name and the
idea of painting meat]. There can be other
colours like ochres, but the affinity with
meat dominates in broken tones.
Other aspects of the Figure, like clothes or
shadows might preserve conventional values of
light and dark, 'a completely different
regime' (105). There is a regime that traces
minute variations in the body 'as the content
of time' to contrast with the eternity
depicted by the shores or fields, but there is
also a place where 'colour–structure gives way
to colour–force', where each colour shows the
exercise of a force on a body or head; 'it
immediately renders a force visible'. Although
variations in the the field can hint at
proximity, colours themselves indicate
proximity but on the diagram, 'as the point of
application or agitated locus of all forces'.
This can still be spatial, but it is also
'topological', acting at a distance, possibly
located elsewhere than the head.
The contour can include other contours, and
here colour retains a more conventional
'tactile–optical function', connected to the
function of the closed line, for example when
contours appear at an angle, indicating
horizontal planes separate from the vertical.
Yet this is a 'subordination to the line in
appearance only' (106). Contours are
autonomous elements, so the line can be
determined by colour: it 'creates the line and
the contour'. Sometimes, contours appear as
decoration, when they are 'treated as rugs'
for example. Small contours can seem to
celebrate colour in itself, rather like 'the
halos of premodern painting': as with halos,
we have 'a coloured pressure that ensures the
Figure's balance and makes one regime of
colour pass into another'.
So colour does not just relate warm cool,
expanding and contracting. There are
whole 'regimes of colours' which can be
related, as in the harmony between pure and
broken tones. This also develops 'haptic
vision', as a kind of totality including all
the other three elements and making them
'communicate and converge in colour'. Is this
just down to 'superior "good taste"' as
somebody called Fried evidently thought? Did
Bacon learn his trade as a decorator? There is
'good taste' displayed in the armature and the
fields, but also bits of bad taste,
anti-decoration, as with elements that make
the Figures into monsters, or when rugs have
'a particularly ugly pattern' [a comment
suggests Bacon sought out particularly hideous
ones]. Even so, these effects only indicate 'a
lingering figuration'. We can see them instead
as 'the most natural of poses, in accordance
with the everyday task that occupies them in
the momentary forces that are confronting
them', or when we consider rugs '"figurally"'
[that is according to the interest in the
Figure not the figuration?]. Here, hideous
rugs serve to 'decompose the vertical field'
[the example is Man and Child above]
and help us move from the field of violet to
the broken tones of the Figure, once we see
them as colour contours. This indicates 'a
creative taste in colour, in the different
regimes of colour, which constitute a properly
visual sense of touch, or a haptic sense of
sight' (107).
Chapter 17 The Eye and the Hand
It is not just that eyes judge and hands
execute. There might be 'dynamic tensions,
logical reversals, and organic exchanges and
substitutions' (108). Sometimes the hand can
be subordinated by paintbrush and easel, but
the paintbrush is never satisfactory. Hands
can offer several 'values… The digital, the
tactile, the manual proper, and the haptic'.
The digital subordinates the hand to the eye
and all the hand does is to choose units that
correspond to visual forms: the eye dominates
the work producing an '"ideal" optical space'
and optical code. However, there are still
manual referents at the virtual level —
'depth, contour, relief, and so on, tactile
referents'. If this is relaxed subordination,
'a veritable insubordination of the hand' is
also possible, imposing on sight 'a space
without form and movement without rest'. This
'dismantles the optical'. This is what Deleuze
meant by referring to the manual aspects. The
haptic does not permit dominance of either eye
or hand, but rather discovers 'a specific
function of touch', (109) not subordinated to
the optical or tactile [a note on page 143
reminds us that 'haptic' is Reigl's term]. As
we saw, it developed first in Egyptian art.
Developing it in a modern context requires
'violence and manual insubordination'.
Conventional figuration is 'rather like the
consequence of [tactile–optical] space'. It is
always there, if only virtually or in 'the
head of the painter', Bacon argued. This space
is to be disrupted through 'a catastrophe… the
manual "diagram"', made of 'insubordinate
colour patches and traits'. Even if we start
with the figurative form, a diagram can
intervene 'and scrambles it' and something
completely different emerges — 'the Figure'.
Examples include the 1946 Painting
above, [I repeat it below] which began by
Bacon wanting to paint a bird alighting on a
field. But the lines 'suddenly took on a kind
of independence and suggested "something
totally different," the man under the
umbrella'. The portraits might include some
organic resemblance, but also something 'more
profound… in which the organs… can no longer
be discerned'. This follows from '"the paint
moving from one contour into another"'
[quoting Bacon's interviews]. This shows that
the diagram is far from being a coded formula.
It is not just that we pass from one form to
another, from bird to umbrella, because in the
portraits there is only a single form.
Referring back to the 1946 Painting,
Bacon himself says that the bird existed first
in the intention of the painter, but this
eventually gave way to a whole, not only the
painting, but 'to the umbrella series' (110).
We can see the diagram still in the 'scrambled
zone, below and to the left' [the confused
colours n the 'rug'?] and it communicates
'through the black shore'. If the bird is an
intentional figurative element, it develops a
correspondence or analogy not to the umbrella
form, itself still figurative, but to 'the
series or the figural whole': that is the
'specifically aesthetic analogy' — the arms of
the meat are analogues to wings, but there are
sections of the umbrella which refer to
falling or closing. Far from a simple analogy,
there are 'completely different relations,
which create a complete Figure'.
The diagram ['diagram–accident'] is not
transformed but it scrambles the intentional
figure of the bird by adding 'non-formal
colour patches and traits that function only
as traits of birdness, of animality'. These
are nonfigurative and it is from then that the
'final whole emerges' and from which the
'power of the pure Figure' appears. The
diagram imposes indiscernibility between the
two forms — one 'no longer, and the other, not
yet'. It stops the second form becoming a
conventional figure. Between the two 'it
imposes the Figure'. The form has been
deformed, subjected to 'original relations
which are substituted for the form' — meat
flows, the umbrella seizes, the mouth is made
jagged like a beak. So 'formless forces' are
introduced and distributed, located on the
deformed parts.
So everything is done inside the same form. We
might start with an intentional figurative
head, but then scramble it 'from one contour
to the other'. (111).This is often done by
'the coloured grey' which permits new
relations to appear, the broken tones, a break
with resemblance. However, there is 'a more
profound resemblance, a nonfigurative
resemblance — that is a uniquely figural
Image'. We have produced resemblance 'with
non-resembling means'. Bacon expresses the
general formula in a number of ways, lines as
well as colours, traits as well as patches, a
notion of distance. So figurative lines can be
scrambled by extending or hatching them, new
distances, new relations between, as when the
mouth goes right across the face [in one of
Bacon's own examples] [with a repetition of
the example about including the distances of
the Sahara in a portrait].
The diagram must remain localised, not cover
the entire painting, not create a catastrophe
or scramble the whole thing. It is intended to
break tones rather than mix colours. It is a
manual element which is 'reinjected into the
visual whole'. It has consequences which are
emergent, and if nothing emerges, it fails.
The Figure emerges 'both gradually and all at
once' [! The example again is the 1946
Painting — apparently, the whole is
given at once, while the series is
constructing gradually, which makes far more
sense]. We also take different perspectives,
as we note 'the heterogeneity of the manual
diagram and the visual whole', a shift first
from optical eye to hand, and then from the
hand to the eye. We can also see these shifts
as a process instead, 'a "slow leak,"' (112)
[presumably quoting Bacon himself]. In this
process, we move from 'hand to haptic eye',
from 'manual diagram to haptic vision'.
This is 'the great moment in the act of
painting' because it is painting's solution to
'the problem of a pure logic: how to pass from
the possibility of fact to the fact itself'
[Bacon's terms again apparently, but a note on
page 44 notes an analogy to Wittgenstein]. The
diagram is the possibility of fact, but the
painting presents a particular fact — 'the
pictorial fact'. This implies that there are
several forms in the one and same Figure,
'like so many necessary accidents continually
mounting on top of one another' [citing Bacon
again]. This quality overcomes the limits of
the figurative and the narrative: the
pictorial fact no longer tells a story, and
represents only 'its own movement'. Apparently
arbitrary elements appear as 'a single
continuous flow [Michelangelo was one of the
first to depict the pictorial fact instead of
a narrative religious fact, we are told in a
note on page 144]. Organic resemblances may
remain, but something is also revealed — 'the
revelation of the body beneath the organism,
which makes organisms and their elements crack
or swell, imposes a spasm on them, and puts
them into relations with forces' both internal
and external, sometimes via specific time, and
sometimes via eternal time. The bodies in
Bacon are not to be understood through
narratives of suffering — these are natural
postures 'as if we caught them "between" two
stories'.
The pictorial fact needs no other
justification. Everything is now made clear.
The activity of painting in Bacon 'evoke this
direct manual activity that traces the
possibility of fact' (113). This pictorial
fact may have come from the hand, but it can
also be seen as 'the formation of a third eye,
haptic eye, haptic vision of the eye' which
offers a new clarity, surpassing 'the duality
of tactile and optical'. It is 'born of the
diagram'.
back to Deleuze page
|
|