Initial notes (1996) on Deleuze,
G. ( 1992) Cinema 1: The Movement
Image, London: The Athlone Press.
NB I took these notes in
1996 ( it is now 2011) , before I had read
anything much else on Deleuze. Some of it makes
more sense now! One
problem is that I am no longer sure about the
origin of the asides in brackets. I have added
doubtful ones in square brackets, not to claim
credit but so as not to malign Deleuze. One day I will go back
and check. The actual works are spattered with
examples from films of all kinds. I have not
seen that many of them,although they are
actually much more accessible now online or via
LoveFilm or equivalent. I have largely omitted
these examples, but indicated where in the text
they can be found for anyone interested.
There is a discussion on the book and the
movement image between Deleuze and two blokes
from Cahiers
which is quite useful -- here
NB
I have collected together all the bits on
Bergson from the 2 volumes here
Cinema raises the old problems
and paradoxes of movement and how to analyse it—as
a series of discrete ‘immobile sections’ together
with some abstract quality of ‘movement’? A series of transitions
between essential ‘poses’ (common in art) or as
‘any – instant – whatevers’ (common in analytical
sciences)? Bergson’s
philosophy can lead into clarifying the dilemmas. Here, it will lead in
turn to attempts to pin down the specific effects
of cinema as a combination of action plus
movement— ‘movement – image’ [image in the
Bergsonian sense of concept, I assume, something
that is both objective and subjective, material
and a representation ?].
For Bergson, movement is a
qualitative change in the whole, that is the
relation between a moving body and its
environment—a hungry dog wants to eat something
and this changes the whole, the dog and the food. Movement is the dynamic,
the ‘vibration’ which changes elements (9). The whole is never given
but always open—durée describes the way in which
human beings relate to that Open.
The Open can be closed in various ways by
classifying things as belonging to sets, or by
pursuing abstractions. Nevertheless,
movement cannot be understood as a closed relation
between immobile sections [I think the argument is
here that even apparently immobile sets still
relate to some mobile section].
Images are best understood as an instant,
when they are immobile, and as movement-images
when they are ‘mobile sections of duration’. There are also
time-images—‘duration images, change images,
relation images… Images
which are beyond movement itself’ (11).
Sets of elements are framed as
in a cinematic image. They
can be saturated with elements, or ‘rarefied’
featuring a single element. There
is a correspondence with the depth focus shot and
the close up. They
may be explicit and pedagogical, as in Godard,
geometric (formalist, featuring lines and angles),
or dynamic (changing irises and other variables). Sometimes they shape the
frame within overall frames, or feature a
vocabulary of gradings and distinctions, of light,
for example. The
cinema also frames the
‘dividual’ (14) [a possible reference to the essay
on social order which emphasises the replacement
of real individuality with a more commercial and
structural version, but also see the Glossary at
the end]: some standard of measurement is applied
to disparate objects , such as faces or
landscapes, which produces deterritorialization. Point of view stances
also feature pragmatic rules, [such as continuity
editing]. There is a
clear implication of a context beyond the frame
too, and this can allude to the notion of the
Open, or the whole again, although this is not the
intended effect of continuity editing which merely
hopes to synthesise different frames. There can also be a
radical allusion to the whole, sometimes suggested
by a single image.
Scenes and shots are cut in two
ways as well. There
can be a succession of sections with an allusion
to the whole duree, combining immobile and mobile
sections. [Camera]
movement expresses the changes in relations in the
wholes [for example Hitchcock’s moving camera
crossing the road and going up and down the stairs
in Frenzy].
In this way, cinema depicts duration—the
shot ‘acts like a consciousness’ (20), but
consciousness invested in the camera rather than
in the spectator or the hero.
Cinema constantly reconstitutes the
relations between wholes and elements, unlike any
participant or viewer. This
is how the films express ideas, in movements and
relations, for example in the combination of
constrained, lattice- like shots and circular
sweeps in the The Third Man,
which is akin to Kafka’s literature (21). Kurosawa has camera
movements like brush strokes in Japanese
characters, and various other spatial metaphors. In these examples, the
shot is the movement image, the mobile section. Shots are more
continuous and varied than natural perception, and
can act as ‘the general equivalent’ of all the
means of locomotion, offering some abstracted
essential movement, intended to emancipate [from
naturalistic perception?] (23).
The fundamental openness of the
whole is suggested by cinematic flexible
recompositions, which express ‘time itself as
perspective or relief’ (24), rather than aiming at
stasis as does photography. This
allusion to movement arises from sequencing
scenes, as in montage, and from the mobility of
the camera [Deleuze says that the early or
contemporary commercial cinema offers mere
sequences of the mobile sections again, with
limited movements]. There
can be an allusion to a depth as well [including
political and theoretical depth].
There are in fact many detailed different
possibilities [listed pages 26-27].
Cinema can never actually represent the
Open, of course, and there are always
discontinuities and ruptures [and conventional
requirements to tell simple stories and impose
naturalistic relations between elements]. The Open
is merely testified to, for example by
deliberately false continuities [montage as in
Eisenstein?]; these show the arbitrary nature of
normal continuity, and invoke [the context], the
‘out of field’.
Shots combine to give montages,
sometimes these can be assembled within shots. There are different
relations between parts and wholes, as a general
way of expressing ideas. Options
include Griffiths on the organic unity of the USA
as the functional adjustment of different strands,
personalised in the form of duels and so on,
through to Eisenstein’s Marxist critiques,
offering new notions of the whole in the form of
dialectical relations between parts and wholes. The various laws of the
dialectic influenced Eisenstein, for example the
shift from quantity to quality.
There also notions of synthesis and
transcendence in the ‘pathetic’ shots—the
connections of objects at different levels of the
dialectic spiral, for example the way individuals
are connected to great events, the way
consciousness dawns. [There
is a very interesting discussion of Vertov and
Dozhenko, with lots of detail].
French cinema
took a different option, away from Griffiths’
notion into social science, offering mechanical
composition, the notion of a whole as a machine
(including Renoir). Individuals
acted as units, whereas the wholes were depicted
as ‘passion’, a kind of zeitgeist. Mechanical analogies
included industrial machines or rivers, or the
sea. The relations
between the units followed mechanical rhythms, an
algebra to generate the maximum amounts of
movement [part of a drive to establish what was
distinctive about moving pictures—‘ photogeny’]. Alternation rather than
dialectic was offered. There
are links to the Kantian notion of the sublime
here, through the connections between mundane
local movements and movements in nature or the
universe as a whole (46). The
whole is not just the sum of the parts. Instead, French cinema
aimed at ‘simultaneousism’, seen in developments
such as triple screens, polyvision,
superimposition. It
was impossible to quantify the effects of these
techniques, leading to a feeling of
measurelessness and immensity.
German
expressionism used light rather than
movement to get the same effect.
Light and dark are seen as primitive
givens. Instead of
the dialectic, we get stripes, contrasts or
blends. These allude
to the non organic side of life which absorbs life
and death, oppositions between the vital and the
organic ‘as in elan vital’ (51)
[as in Bergson again?]. This
produced a characteristic horror of puppets,
robots, golems and so on. [Clever
stuff on how the transitions from the organic to
the non-organic were coded by the relations of
light and dark, 52-3]. Increasing
intensity produces the formless (another variant
of Kant, the dynamic sublime), via a montage of
contrast.
More philosophical problems
emerged, for example the relations between images
and movements. Was
one ideal and the other material?
However, movements produce images and
images engender movements, at least in human
beings. The cinematic
image also offers possibilities here. For example it organises
gestalts as forms of intentional consciousness,
showing how the world becomes image.
Classical phenomenology
privileges natural perception rather than
cinematic forms, and again Bergson gets closer: he
sees cinematic perception as one possible way to
focus and centre perceptions from a flux. Each set equals an
image. These include
movement for Bergson, necessarily, as a kind of
implied context and set of relations. The images are the
primitive category, and there is an infinite set
of them. The image is
identical with movement (59) and the movement –
image is identical with matter, So Bergson is a
materialist. However,
reality is not a mechanical system which is
closed. The fixed
parts are best seen as a ‘machine assemblage of
movement – images’, hence ‘the universe [is a]
cinema in itself, a metacinema’ (59). Bergson is the theorist
of movement, and solid bodies are seen as merely
temporary [reifications], ‘movements on a plane of
immanence’. Matter is
formed from the identity of the image and the
movement (59). The
mechanistic universe is only a subset,
characterised by its discrete ‘block of space –
time’ one of an infinite number of ‘presentations’
of the plane (59).The image alludes to becoming,
to ‘everything that they have not yet become’
(60).
Potential sites for action are
immanent in the sense that light is [some
constituting medium which diffuses]. There are
connections here with the theory of relativity as
a deliberate project in Bergson.
Light passes on unopposed, and only becomes
an image when it is obstructed, just as in
photography. Matter
is a fixed form of light, leading to an
interesting point about objects not being revealed
until they reflect light. In
a similar way, images are not recognized until
they are perceived, but they do exist
independently of the perceiving subject none the
less.
As with light, so with human
consciousness. Unlike
the old model which sees the consciousness is
shedding light, as a torch beam does, which
classical phenomenology shares, although in a
modified form, ‘For Bergson…
Things are luminous by themselves without
anything illuminating them’ (60).
Living beings are unique images,
however—they focus and organise, they frame and
organise into sequences (action), organise the
flux of variation, operate in the gap or interval
between reception and execution.
Hence the organisation and roles of images
is at the centre of this process, and many are
omitted according to needs. Human
beings have different facets for receiving and
transmitting images. The
reception facets close and isolate images as in
perception or framing (62) [called ‘condensation’
in Bergsonism?] .
At the other end of the interval,
transmission produces unpredictable open
consequences, unintegrated with reception. [Really
unpredictable or emergent as a complex effect of
duration?] This
unpredictability produces new features of human
action, indeterminism around living images. Thus, located on the
plane, images react constantly and infinitely
among themselves; around living matter they are
organised or closed and become centres of
variation. There is
an evolutionary process here—as matter solidifies
into particles, so images are subject to more and
more or elaborate perceptions [this makes a bit
more sense after reading Deleuze on Bergson and
duration].
Perception is therefore
‘subtractive’, producing things ‘minus that which
does not interest us’. In
this way, ‘an atom perceives infinitely more than
we do’ (64) [this is what intentionality does?]. The cinema can deliver
both sets of perceptions, from the ‘total
objective perception which is indistinguishable
from the thing’ to a ‘subjective perception’ (64). The latter is a
perception–image, a subset of the movement-image.
Subtraction is not the only
process. The rest
of the world is recognized as a horizon, a
potential for action again.
Perception is inseparable from action
(64). The distance
between the core and periphery is a way of
thinking about the gap between action and
reaction. There is
a connection between perception–image and
action–image, both of which are subsets or
‘avatars’ of the movement-image (65), an
organisation (‘incurving’) of the universe
rather than a simple subtraction or framing.
There is another possible avatar too—affect,
which ‘fills the gap [between] troubling
perception [and] hesitant action’ (65). This refers to
subjectivity from the inside [normal human
perspective] and to the notion of quality
[Bergson’s separation of multiplicities with
differences of kind and those with difference of
degree?]. Affect
supplies a motor tendency. It is found combined
in human beings. [So
the four types -- movement -image and its three
avatars—are illustrated with examples from
cinema 69-70, and there is particular attention
to Beckett’s work Film, page 66
F. There are implications for time- images too.]
[You can watch all 17 minutes
of Film here
and see if you read it as Deleuze does. It is a
convenient example to match with the extraordinary
levels of interpretation Deleuze offers. Deleuze
says Film is:
an
astonishing attempt...[to] rid ourselves of
ourselves, and demolish ourselves...[like Berkley]
to be is to be perceived, declares Beckett...[the
bit where the character scurries along hugging a
wall, filmed only from the back, is]...a
perception of action, an action-image...[The
bit where the character enters the room and goes
round closing windows, covering mirrors and
evicting pets, filmed largely from the back with
the camera not intruding past 45 degree angles,
is]...the perception of perception or the perception-image...in a double
system of reference...[Then]...
the character...is finally seen [by the
camera] from the front ...[and] ...the last
convention is revealed: the camera...is the double
of [the character], the same face, a patch over
one eye (monocular vision) with the single
difference the [character] now has an anguished
expression and [the camera] has an attentive
expression...We are in the domain of the
perception of affection: the most terrifying, that
which still survives when all the others have been
destroyed: it is the perception of self by self
the affection-image...
So – OK this is pretty
understandable, but the next bit is much more
...er...contestable...
The
end [fade-out on the character rocking in a chair
and a close-up eye] suggests – death immobility,
blackness. But, for Beckett, immobility, death,
the loss of personal movement and of vertical
stature...are only a subjective finality...only a
means in relation to more profound end. It is a
question of attaining once more the world before
man...the position where movement was...under the
regime of universal variation, and where light,
always propagating itself, had no need to be
revealed...[Proceeding to ] the extinction of
action-images, perception-images and affection
images, Beckett ascends once more to the luminous
plane of immanence, the plane of matter and its
cosmic eddying of movement -images. He traces the
three varieties of image back to the mother
movement-image...Beckett’s originality is to be
content to elaborate a symbolic system of simple
conventions [how much the camera can reveal of the
character] – according to which the three images
are successively extinguished – as the condition
which makes possible this general tendency of
experimental cinema (66—68).
There are two references in
this section to Beckett’s own commentary on the
film –in French. They offer Beckett’s own analysis
of the film – according to Deleuze, Beckett says
there are three ‘moments...the street, the
staircase the room’. But Deleuze says his schema
of action-image ‘groups the street and the
staircase, while the perception image covers the
room and the affection image the ‘hidden room and
the dozing of the character in the rocking chair’
(n 31, 272). A couple of issues seem relevant : in
the first place, the writer is highlighted as the
author of the film, not the director – for the
first and only time as far as I can see, since in
every other example it is the director, ignoring
altogether the writer, not to mention the actors,
the lighting camerapersons and the technical crew. [My colleague Ian Gilhespy reminded me
of this--There is a performance of Krapp's Last Tape
directed by Beckett here].
In Film, was it not likely
to be Keaton who added the clowning bits [blimey –
I sounded like Zizek there]? While
we are here, the concept of genre is not
critically discussed either throughout and is
taken to be an artistic term, never a commercial
one.
In Note 32, we are told Beckett
has not done enough in his commentary ‘to represent the set of
all the movements’ (227). It seems it was Fanny
Deleuze who completed the picture with a rather
baffling diagram (see below -- I can't see a point
B can you?). O is the
character, OE is the camera. No doubt this makes a
nice neat diagram -- but is this the only reasons
for theorising like this – some notion of
completion, mastery or explanatory power? The
symmetry of the diagram somehow guarantees the
validity of the classification? This reminds me of
the obsessive listing and classifying in Anti-Oedipus
or Thousand
Plateaus
Of course these are also centred
readings, with the philosophical meanings given
pride of place. I think the film can be read
equally well as being about identity and the
‘social mirrors’ that support it – the views of
other people, photos, actual mirrors etc. The
film adds the perceptions of pets as mirrors.
But it could equally be seen as about stardom
and anonymity, no doubt.
Peirce’s work on signs is also
useful, if we see the sign is a particular type of
image, one which represents (from the point of
view of composition, generation or even
extinction). There is
work to be done on the relations between Peirce’s
classifications and Deleuze’s types of image [see
Glossary].
Films usually have montages or
assemblages of different images, and often one is
usually dominant [in experimental film the
perception image tends to be dominant]. Shots correspond too—the
long shot indicates perception, the midshot
action, the close up affect.
The shots can help us offer a whole
readings of films (70).
The
perception-image can be subjective
or objective, the former belonging to a
participant and the latter external. These can
shift. The subjective image can become a
collective one as the camera moves among the
characters, taking on an anonymous generalised
viewpoint rather than a single pov. This is
definitely not naturalistic, and corresponds to
the difference between direct and nondirect
speech. Pasolini especially used this linguistic
analogy, and his camera develops
a ‘free indirect discourse’ (72). [There is an
aside on Bakhtin on this too, pointing out the odd
tendency to be a subject in speech capable of
referring to oneself as an object – I think (73).
The process parallels the use of dialects in an
utterance] This shows the duality of the (ordinary
empirical) subject and a (necessary)
Transcendental Subject (73).
However, in such discourses, there is never
a complete formal split but rather ‘an oscillation
of the person between 2 points of view of himself’
(74) [A necessary, ironic reflexivity?]. The
camera itself often does this oscillation – it
observes and comments on actors as they act,
rather than obediently doing subjective and
objective perceptions. An example is Pasolini’s
‘insistent’ or even ‘obsessive’ framing (74)
(where the camera frames the scene before and
after the actor is in it). Cameras can also use
different lenses on the same image, including
‘excessive use of the zoom’ (74). This shows the
‘cinema of poetry’ [NB I noted to myself that all
this is derived from Deleuze’s critical perception
and it might contrast strongly with what the
directors themselves believed they were doing].
The effect can be to produce some sort of
reflexivity among the actors too as they watch
themselves acting, and as the directors become
neurotic (75)
Bergson considered the
subjective as showing where images vary according
to one central and privileged image rather than
constant variation. Subjective variations can
produce the objective after [a sort of relativist]
moment, where lots of
movements of points of view allude to a notion of
the Absolute or the Sublime. This is expressed in
French cinema’s obsession with flowing water, as
an embodiment of variation and flow [lots of
examples follow pp78-9].
Vertov developed a notion of
gaseous perception. He clearly aimed at
demonstrating the movement-image, showing the
possibilities of universal variation in a whole
cinema of interaction and variation rather than a
standard materialist perception. The human eye was
seen as immobile, and thus inevitably subjective
(the centre of variation). By contrast, the camera
showed movement through montage, which objectified
perception, to overcome ‘boundaries and distances’
(81 –quoting Vertov). It does this by adopting the
perspective of matter [images are materialist],
for example by establishing intervals and gaps
that prefigure the role of the human subject. The
gaps between two correlated images replace
consecutive images, and when these are collected,
an assemblage of matter ap[pears, a deciphering of
reality. Vertov extends from suggesting images
joined by a subject to variation as such [the
example here is, obviously, Man With
a Movie Camera]. There are even montages of
elements of an image. Vertov strayed into
formalist dialectics of matter rather than the
humanism of Eisenstein, or the ‘spiritual ’ aims
of French cinema’s depiction of natural objects.
American cinema was influenced
by Vertov too, aiming to discover molecules of
matter or ‘photogrammes’. Their programme
corresponds with Castenada as an attempt to stop
the world, see the gaps between objects etc [D
really likes Castenada!]. A US experimental film
is described as an illustration (86).
The
affection-image. The face in
close-up shows this best. A face is any image
(even a clock face) which shows a ‘reflecting
surface and intensive micro-movements’, which
indicate normally hidden aspects [a better start
than the pseudy delirium of the commentary on
faces and faciality in Thousand Plateaus].The
passive immobile surface signifies a surface while
the micromovements show the hidden effects of
desire, hence different kinds of close up [LCU and
VLCU?]. [Very large close ups] offer a series of
images that produces a qualitative leap, such a
movement from one ‘pole’ to the other. Griffiths
and Eisenstein illustrate the possibilities (91f).
Eisenstein aimed to show the progression from
individual to dividual ( ‘an immensely collective
reflection...the unity of power and quality’
(92)).
It is possible to use light and
dark on a face to signify a relation to matter
generally [amazing examples 92—3]. In a close up
of the face, images escape from boundaries and
immediate contexts, producing ‘pure affect’
,located in ‘any-space-whatever’(97). The same
effect can be generated by CUs of other parts of
the body or of things. Both the object and what it
expresses can be seen as related, as in the icon
[Peirce?], ‘the set of the expressed and its
expression’ (97). When actualised, the qualities
of affection-images become the ‘quale’ of the
object, the actual emotions or impulses
[associated with it] (97), and thus its
action-images.
This is easier to see [!] in
concrete or relational terms, rather than via
Peirce’s insistence on ‘first’ qualities:
‘qualities or powers considered for themselves
without reference to anything else, independently
of ...their actualisation’ (98). Better to
describe these as affection-images (not just
action or image), preserving the idea of
potentiality. These can only be expressed by ‘a
face, a face-equivalent or a proposition’(99),
especially in CU. In CU, faces lose their normal
function, to individuate, socialise [have a social
role] or relate/communicate. Instead, faces in CU
offer allusions to nihilism, the void, Fear, as
the face expresses nothingness [fucking weird
stuff! A fancy example of the uncanny in Freud?].
Power qualities are not
produced by real events since they pre-date them.
They are both expressed for themselves and then
realized or embodied [See DeLanda on how inorganic
elements preform complex molecules without human
intervention etc?]. Faces in CU also show pure
(‘virtual’) relations, especially how objects and
emotions are related. These relations are shown in
montage (including internal montages as different
bits of the same CU are shown). The ways in which
faces turn away from and towards [objects]
expresses relations – singularities and relations
form complex unities like the dividual again –
‘that which neither increases or decreases without
changing qualitatively’ (105) [seems completely
opposite to the earlier definitions]. We can see
how faces are linked to propositions. These are
virtual relations of possibility and potentials
rather than real(ized) relations, but
demonstrating the latter can allude to the former
(the example is the Besson film Joan
of Arc which shows the realized trial but
alludes to the expressed passion of Joan) [Pretty
simple point after all the fuss?]. Further
examples (107) lead to the definition
of a CU as a shot framed so as to eliminate depth
or perspective, or to include a fragment of a
field, to allude to a virtual relation.
It is possible to convey
‘any-space-whatever’ in other ways too. The Besson
film shows fragmentations of space, deframings,
collision-type links. The any-space-whatever is
demonstrated as a concrete singular space rather
than an abstraction. It has ‘lost its
homogeneity’, it alludes to an infinite number of
possible linkages, to potentiality (109). So the
a-s-w is another way to express the
affection-image, as well as a face [make your
bleeding mind up, and/or stop making this up as
you go along!]. The a-s-w would be a ‘qualisign’
for Peirce. Rapid montage can allude to pure
power/quality [ I am
not at all sure I know what this means -- another
argument with Peirce? A repetition of the earlier
point?].
The a-s-w is constituted [in
Besson? Always?] by the play of light and shadows,
especially shadows. These represent the virtual,
the infinite. Expressionism offers a ‘lyrical
abstraction’ of the alternatives (112-3) according
to whether light and dark alternate or are seen as
opposites. There are possible ‘spiritual’
parallels, producing the classic different types
of ethical choices, including no choice; moral
necessity; physical necessity; psychological
necessity (from desire) [Expressionist cinematic
equivalents of techniques of neutralisation?].
Alternatives also appear according to whether one
is aware of the choices or not – one can choose to
choose or live unaware of choice. These are also
illustrated in lyrical abstractions where the
theme is avoiding false choices, choices that lead
to no choice (Faust), or a choice to renew choice
even if it ends in self sacrifice. Themes can
develop into a denial that there is even a self
rather than just actualisations of possible
selves, a ‘moralism opposed to morality’ and
‘faith opposed to religion’ (116).
These are further examples of
the relationship between philosophy and the cinema
– the choice to choose is beyond specific choices;
the light constitutes the whites, blacks and
greys; fragments suggest the whole; spaces suggest
any-space-whatever.
Whole new dimensions are added
with colour. [And there is an aside about musical
comedy ‘extracting an unlimited virtual world from
a conventional state of things’ 118]. It is not
that colour codes affect – colour is affect, it
absorbs objects into relations (examples discuss
Antonioni and Bergman). The asw is now a matter of
absorption, an empty space. [An aside notes that
post-War cities are also full of empty spaces,
potentials, asw]. Experimental films offer
examples (122) [one good example is provided – a
slow zoom to explore a room].
The
action-image. This
is an intermediate form between action and affect,
between the ASW/affect pair and the ‘detached
milieux/mode of behaviour’ pair.
It also belongs to the ‘originary
world/elementary impulse’ pair.
The originary world can be seen as a pure
set, the source of origin of actual milieu. Impulses are seen as the
initial energy required to seize fragments. This provides a
naturalist rather than realist notion of
actualised forms. [All
references to Bergson’s philosophy, I assume]. Primordial origins can
be alluded to as well (125) faith, understood as
being immanent to the originary.
They can be represented by symptoms (‘the
presence of impulses in the derived world’), and
idols and fetishes (‘the representation of the
fragments’) (125). These
aspects are illustrated in the cinema of Stroheim
and Bunuel (and the examples here include the
drawing room in Exterminating Angel,
the desert of columns in Stylites). These are films about
the originary world which ‘carries the milieu
along’, and represents both origin and end (as in
the escape of the bourgeoisie from the drawing
room, only to end in a cathedral).
The effects of the originary world on real
milieu often appear as degradation or cyclical
return, although both tend to represent the
negative effects of time.
Impulses are always directed at
fragments (including shoes or even ‘invalids’). Impulses can carry on
until they cross boundaries and exhaust other
milieu. They are
deeper and more general than affects attached to
objects. They can
cross social boundaries (the beggars in Viridiana) and aim at the general
goal of fragmenting, gathering up the scraps and
ending in the death impulse. Bunuel is is a naturalist in this
sense rather than a structuralist proper. He alludes to faith
rather than religion, however, in his particular
way of discussing spirituality and choice which
connects into the tradition of lyrical
abstractionism discussed above.
[A commentary ensues on a
number of directors who represent such a
naturalism—133f]. The
role of female actresses in American cinema can
allude to the originary—‘originary women’ (134),
esp. King Vidor in Duel in the Sun
[much discussed by Mulvey
as an example of a fiery tempestuous woman who
disrupts normal male society, but has to be killed
as a result --trailer
here ]. However,
staying at the level of impulse is the problem and
there is a tendency to stray into realism, of
actualised milieux and behaviour. Losey is
discussed (137): his trick is to allude to
originary violence as too great to be actualised,
even in the characters. Here
too, women offer an escape into something outside
the ‘hermetic’ world of men.
Action –
image, the large form.
Milieux are made concrete and actualised in
action – images proper—‘realism’.
This can still be linked to originary
milieu. Realism can
include fictional realism, as in the dream,
defined merely by ‘milieux which actualise a mode
of behaviour which embodies’ (141).
The action-image is the relation between
the two. Milieux can
actualise several qualities and powers which
interact on a character, producing a response, and
a new situation. The
process of individualisation produces a kind of
duel, between man and milieu, or an hourglass
structure—the broad and narrow dimensions
represent the broad and narrow dimensions of the
character. This is
the ‘large form—“Situation/Action/Situation”’
(141). Each stage has
its characteristic signs, including ‘synsign’ and ‘binomial’ [using Pierce
again]. The example
here is the walkdown/shootout in the western.
Documentaries can be seen as a
subtype of the action image. Flaherty gives an
example of the duels between communities and
hostile milieu, without third terms, for which he
has been criticised (like the role of colonising
powers and the effects on community). For example, Nanook [clip
here] represents duels between man and
environment producing survival and changed
situations.
There is a psycho – social
subtype in King Vidor, an ‘ethical’ realist form
relating individuals and collectivities. It is possible for
individuals do not always trial for change the
situation, and they can even produce worse
results. The form is
still realist, sometimes hourglass, rather than
the Expressionist notion of entropy discussed
earlier, and there is still a focus on concrete
milieux and their pathologies, or specific
behavioural disorders. This
is the world of the born loser, the heroic drunk
or criminal, especially in its film noir variant. The rise and fall
narratives of gangster movies also fit—here the
milieu of the underworld is a ‘false community’, a
jungle, while the behaviour of the hero also
reveals fundamental flaws, which can sometimes be
exploited by the minor characters [including the
femme fatale?]. The
films act as critics of society—or as a
compensatory nightmare to strengthen the American
dream (145).
In the western, the landscape
encompasses via metaphors of ‘breath’ [sic, 146]
or later, colour codes, especially the ‘sky and
its pulsations’ (146). The
community and the land is mediated by a leader. The milieu itself can
‘breathe’ especially in Ford movies, and can bring
together minorities in a melting pot. We are close to epics
here, but westerns also include elements of
tragedy and romance. Ford
offers change as a spiral movement rather than a
circle which permits ethical commentaries, for
example of the transformation of natural law to
written law. There
are also ‘healthy’ dreams about a community,
‘vital illusions, or realist illusions which are
more true than pure truth’ (148).
There are variations on the
birth and rebirth of a nation in American cinema
as well, just as in Soviet cinema, but in an
‘organic’ dialectic [there are British organicist
analogies too]. This
often takes place via analogy or parallels between
American and other civilisations, especially
classical civilisations, and develops notions of
the growth of vigorous national states which have
two elements of the American dream—the melting
pot, and the ‘ferment which creates leaders’
(148). These
historical themes are found in all the other
American genres too, including gangsters. This is an ideological
form of history of course [with references to
Nietzsche on history, 149 f], for example the
‘monumental’ themes (great buildings and events
for example) which are linked periods and tend
towards the universal. There
are the usual problems in grasping the real
movements of history with its tensions, which are
often represented and individualised as duels. ‘Antiquarian’ themes
involves the reconstruction of past societies as
some kind of social context for the present. ‘Ethical’ themes depict
the battle between good and evil, decadence and
vigour in a ‘constant discovery of America’ (151). These are often all work
together to produce ‘a strong and coherent
conception of universal history’ (151).
So there are common elements
among the genres: (a) organic composition and
combinatories in typical action images (sky,
landscape etc.)and ‘encompassers’
[ see Glossary], movement within images; (b)
movements which contract into a duel which must be
produced by convergent lines from a situation, as
in the ‘large form’ like the hourglass
[illustrated with reference to M];
(c) duels themselves present moments of
simultaneity where parallels converge; (d) duels
dovetail and interact with other duels; (e) the
large gap between the milieu and behaviour can
only be bridged progressively, because the power
of the hero needs to be developed, for example by
a group, and only after moments of doubt or
impotence. Strength
can be transferred from one character to another.
There is an emphasis on
behaviour as mobile from one milieu to another. Behaviour is to be
structured by the milieu. [Then
there is an odd bit about the differences between
passive vegetable and active animal forms, terms
which make a link with Bergson—vegetables
‘accumulate the explosive on the spot, whilst the
animal undertakes the demolition’ 156]. War films are an example
of these alternating forms of structuring. Or Baby
Doll, [clip]
with its slow
accumulation of tensions then a violent release. Or combinations of
little episodes which accumulate [On
the Waterfront is the example]. There is a tendency for
greater toughness and exaggeration of this
process, linked to the collapse of the American
dream (157). These
films feature real behaviourism because they see
behaviours as caused, although internal
motivations are important too.
In fact the focus is often on the internal
dimension, the whole point of fictional realism. This inner focus is what
overcomes the artificiality of realism and of
acting. These the
elements must appear in the image—each action
image displays an ‘emotion/object’ pair, as much
as any other pairing of aspect and face, impulse
and fetish. The
inner, the ‘impression’ links the situation and
the explosive action.
The action
image small form. This is an
alternative possible form linking
action/situation/image (see above) where action
‘discloses’ the situation which triggers off new
actions, moving from an habitus to a partially
disclosed situation, a local example. This disclosure can be
elliptical rather than spiral, constructed around
events rather than organic, and comedic rather
than epic. The signs
here act as indexes. The
initial actions are an index for the situations,
which implies a lack of knowledge, a ellipsis [for
example as in sudden shifts forward in time. Other examples include
highly condensed metonyms and metaphors—a shirt
collar falling from a drawer indicates an affair]. This offers a ‘reasoning
image’ (161), where the audience has to work
things out. There are
also indices of equivocity [for skilled readers
only?], where only slight differences appear in
actions, but where these lead to two very
different interpretations, hence the ellipsis. These often linked with
the need to be economical, as in the French new
wave.
Again there are different
genres: (a) the comedy of manners; (b) the costume
film as descriptions of an habitus.
Unlike historical epics of the large form,
which are about historical developments and so on,
these are about habits [with a possible pun to
allude to dresses]: dress here acts as an index;
(c) Grierson and free cinema instead of Flaherty,
featuring concrete modes leading to social
situations as sites of struggle, enabling the
underdog perspective to appear; (d) the detective
film, where actions become indices; (e) westerns
as well, especially those produced by Howard
Hawks, which replaced the organic encompassers
with ‘pure functionalism’, functional groups
rather than organic communities, nor to work based
but arbitrary, often collections of travellers. Here local interiors
offer unexpected events in contrast to large
experience, such as the odd bits where the
functions of men and women interchange in Hawks
movies; (f) the neowestern, which focuses on micro
politics in small groups, such as The
Wild Bunch, where the bigger groups fade
out—there is racial indifference for example. There are no grandiose
actions, no dream, focus on local westerns rather
than ‘the west’, episodes are linked by a broken
line or vector rather than an organic form; (g)
burlesque which is devoted to this shift, for
example in Chaplin [how small differences in
behaviour reflect large differences in reality of
the situation—a shaking body can indicate sobbing
or shaking a cocktail] (169).
Analogy merely shows complete differences
between situations. Chaplin
films are vectors joining these episodes. Another example would be
Harold Lloyd on the demonstration of the
‘perception image’—he appears to be driving a
large car but this is revealed as him cycling
behind it. Both
comedians did gestures which could be comic or
tragic/emotional. Some
commentary was also offered, as when Hitler and
the little man were seen as similar—the idea being
that social forces or discourses produce one
rather than the other (172).
The talkies introduce
discourses of this kind [commentaries,
dialogues?]. These
links to the larger forms in Chaplin. It is different for
Keaton, who locates himself in large milieux and
borrows scenes from films of those, for example
Griffith, producing large gaps between the
location and the comic action.
This gap can be bridged in a number of
ways: (a) the ‘trajectory gag’, a rapid sequence
of actions [jumping gaps, sliding down poles,
running along trains and so on]; (b) the ‘machine
gag’ where weird ( ‘Dadaist’) machines are
produced (175) with definite functions. This can involve
‘minoring’, where the immensity of machines is
reduced to a personal scale, alluding to a
political ‘anarchistic machine’ to assert human
rights to use the big machines (176). Machines can also offer
‘recurrent gags’ with absurd causal sequences [as
in Heath Robinson]. Minoring links the action to
the situation, recurrent gags ‘make the hero equal
to the situation’ (177).
Figures. The figure is a
sign of ‘deformations, transformations, or
transmutations’ (178). Scripts
can be turned into either large or small forms
according to the conceptions of the director
(which can turn on a sudden realization of the
signifying power of some detail, for example ) [Storm Over Asia is the example –clip here -- or Ordinary
Fascism –clip
here -- where everyday events tell the
story]. In the first
example, a dialectic of quantity quality shifts
tell the story, a guided small form.
Other directors saw the dialectic in terms
of parts and wholes which produced a larger form
[Dozhenko is the example]. In
Eisenstein the issue is the reconciliation of
opposites, a transforming form [the discussion
turns on how big forms produced concrete
embodiments. In 1996
I read this as rather Hegelian, or buts,
presumably it is much more to do with the
actualization of virtual potentials in Deleuze’s
own philosophy?] (181). In Eisenstein, development
of the small level, the concrete or embodied
becomes ‘pathetic’ [I do not know if this has a
special meaning]. Such
transformation is often done via special images,
such as the theatrical interludes in Ivan... [clip
here] The links between these images are
indirect, via an
image which prefigures, or indexes, depending on
whether one is moving from action to situation or
vice versa.
This leads to discussion of
figures of discourse, such as tropes, where a word
in the figurative sense replaces another
word—metaphor, metonym, synecdoche.
There are also imperfect tropes such as
allegories or personification, all cases where
words are substituted for each other in a strictly
sense, as in reversals. There
are also a ‘figures of thought which do not pass
through any modifications of words (deliberation,
concession, support, prosopaeia)’ (183). In each case, cinema has
figures which correspond. [Prosopaeia is ‘a
rhetorical device in which a speaker or writer
communicates to the audience by speaking as
another person or object’, according to the
indispensable Wikipedia.]
There are also visions. The example is Herzog’s
cinema, depicting visionaries where actors exceed
the requirements of the situation, leading to
sublime action (in the large form) and heroic
action (which is appropriate). Herzog also
demonstrates the enfeeblement and reduction of the
small form [with some weird examples 185].
Transformations take place in
particular domains: (a) the physio – biological
milieu which acts as a transmitting fluid; (b) the
mathematical domain, describing space and
relationships like the whole and the part, the
global and the local: elements of the local make
sense by connection to a global (187); (c) the
aesthetic domain, such as the landscape [and there
is a weird aside about Chinese painting which
apparently operates according to principles of
either insisting that the elements have a unity in
the One, or that elements are separated into
distinct autonomous events. This
produces metaphors of breath, circle, spiral for
the former, and broken line or wrinkled stroke for
the latter—so some earlier allusions are
explained?] Kurosawa’s cinema is the example,
where the exposition of all the given factors in
the situation is followed by explosive action. This is not the same as
the usual sequence from situation to action,
though, since the givens are quantitative: an
actual situation is depicted with allusions to a
notion of ‘any quantity whatever’’ [this seems to
lead to some sort of critique of positivism here,
with its failure to grasp the quantitative
properly by acting too hastily and literally,
acting or reacting before a considered approach].
In the Seven
Samurai, the question is not the
pragmatic one of how to defend a village, but the
more general issue of ‘what is a samurai today?’
(191). [Deleuze’s
admits that this looks ‘mundane humanist’ (192)].
Another approach [Mizogauchi]
displays the opposite tendencies, developing from
the small form (192 f). The
small scenes are linked, for example by high angle
shots for individual scenes, and contiguous shots
‘which produces a sliding effect’ (193). There is a persistence
of medium shots and circular movements of the
camera, and the use of a special kind of ‘rolling
shot… [which]
unravels successive fragments of the space to
which are… attached
vectors of a different direction’ (194) [the
commentary referred to here is in French]. This leads to a
lengthening, the connection of fragments and a
demonstration of vectors increase, demonstrating
the ‘line of the universe’’,
linking together heterogeneous elements. The lines go through
women for this director, although he is aware of
the social appearance of women as prostitutes or
oppressed. Reality
thus appears as disconnected, disoriented. [God
knows what this actually looks like but try this
clip from Ugetsu]
The
crisis. Peirce
discusses ‘thirdness’, signifiers, their law or
relation, as for itself, irreducible to actual
examples. There is a
focus on acts rather than actions interpretations
or relations, on natural and abstract relations
rather and signification and the law, on natural
unities and progressions [the
example here is again one of painting and how
portraits led to an interest in the face and then
to the circumstances of painting art]. There is less interest
in abstract connections through geometrical
properties. This
approach in necessarily involves
mental/intellectual/cognitive aspects.
Affection-images and
action-images imply some mental or intellectual
element, but the latter can have its own image. This image can
explicitly signify ‘relations, symbolic acts,
intellectual feelings’, and a direct relationship
with thought. [A
strange discussion ensues on burlesque and the
Marx Brothers—Groucho represent symbolic reasoning
as comedy as in “either my watch has stopped or
this man is dead”]. Hitchcock
was always more interested in relations than a
mere whodunit, crimes was seen as a part of the
wider set of relations, of exchange, say: this becomes a symbolic
act of which the actors are unaware, although the
camera explains (for example why the hero of Rear Window has hurt his leg—we see
pictures of a racing car). Even
the audience can be seen as the third term, since
there reactions become part of the film.
English philosophy developed an
interest in relations as a key element of logic. The relation became the
starting ‘postulate’ of the film for Hitchcock
[who was therefore interested in English
philosophy or somehow influenced by it?]. His films develop
possible variations and changes, were action is
often determined by ‘experienced conjunctions;
because… although… sense…
if… even if’
(202). To do this,
Hitchcock develops specific signs of
relationships—not the detective’s account, but
various ‘marks’ (where some natural or customary
series is being referred to) and ‘demarks’ (where
one term leaps out of natural relations, such as
birds, or the crop sprayer out of context). There also
symbols—concrete objects bear a relation, where a
key can indicate a marital relation, birds become
representative of the relations of nature, or
objects express nodes of abstract relations [no
example given here —maybe the dead stuffed birds
in Psycho express the weird
relation between Norman and hiss dead mother?] Hitchcock’s work led to
a crisis in traditional images of the cinema,
because the emphasis on relations casts into doubt
the status of the images of concrete objects
themselves—they become mere terms in a relation
(205).
This crisis was always there
though. There was
always a tendency to deny action as such in favour
of showing relations. The
milieux in sequences of situation and action are
seen as no longer decisive, but merely one
constitutive element of action, part of a
multiplicity rather than a decisive fact. The same goes for
decisive actions—these in turn become, turn into
improvisation, develop the present for their own
sake rather than a part in a narrative. The crisis has its
origin in a number of external and internal
(artistic) impulses. [These
look rather like a list of the factors that have
produced postmodernism—the War, the end of the
American dream, the consciousness of minorities,
excessively imagery, and the effects of
experimental narratives from literature (206)]. Conventional sequences
of situation and action are no longer believable,
and new signs emerge [we have here the usual claim
that changes detectable by French intellectuals
somehow represent real changes grasped by
everybody].
In the new cinema:
1.
The
image refreshes situations which are ‘dispersive’,
with multiple characters and narratives, for
example Altman.
2.
The lines of the universe
are broken, become elliptical, featured discrete
and segmented actions rather than regular
transformations, or are replaced by chance—‘white
events’— rather than expressions of personal
interest [the example here is the actions in Taxi Driver]
There is indifference, the interchangeability of
the action-image and the affection-image.
3.
There is the dominance of
the stroll rather than the journey or the project
or initiation. Aimless
movements, repetitions, things that can happen
anywhere.
4.
Cliché becomes important
as a unifying principle of sets of elements rather
than totality and linkage. Unities
are provided by actualities (news, interest items,
songs) and the ‘eye of the camera’ [which seems to
refer to some internal monologue of a third
party]. These become
inner psychic clichés. The
inside becomes like the outside [the examples are
the clichés in Altman]. The
political function of this is to make the outside
tolerable, almost as a plot (209).
5.
The condemnation of this
conspiracy takes the form of attacks on or
demonstrations of the power of the mechanical
reproduction of images and sounds.
There is a potential role here for cinema
in offering a critical reflection of its own role
(210). Directors
become aware of their own activities in selecting
images, for example. However
it is common to direct this, at least in American
cinema, both into a critique of misappropriation
in two abstract repetitions of themes of [Altman
again] to mere parody for—American cinema now has
its own traditions to dominate it.
Critical
trends
in Europe include: (a) Italian cinema post-War. The cinema had escaped
fascism both, so there was no need to preserve
national honour (as in France), permitting new
beginnings to include the excluded. [The example
here is Rossellini]. Neo-realism is the precursor
of the five characteristics of the sign mentioned
above, as in the fragmented scenes of Rome Open
City, and voyaging for the characters in Bicycle Thieves.
Fellini also offers a plethora of asw, but
there is a reconstruction in the form of clichés
of Italianness. There
is a condemnation of the mafia conspiracy too (212
– 13).(b)The French new wave features the
voyage-form for the present in its own right,
offering random links, again
lots of asw. There is
also ‘making false’: warping perspectives, slowing
down of time and an alteration of gestures (213)
as signs of the new realism. There are clumsy
fights rather than stylised duels. There is an
awareness that these have become clichés too. (c)
New German cinema where the characters can choose
to become clichés, leading to a general theme of
suspicion of a general conspiracy aimed at
enslavement.
There
are problems with these trends too, including the
danger of descent into parody. There are examples
of thoughtful reflection on what an image is in
Godard, extracted from clichés. There are links to
Hitchcock as well as Marx in the French new wave
(pursuing common interests in mental images and
thirdness), but also an interest in smashing the
system of perception-action – effect, a deliberate
prolongation of the crisis in order to liberate a
new thinking image.
NB
There is also a glossary – I don’t know if it
really helps though! It shows how Deleuze
interprets Peirce (and Bergson) for his
commentary. I have scanned it and included it
below (217-8):
Glossary
ACTION-IMAGE: reaction of the
centre to the set [ensemble].
AFFECTION-IMAGE: that which
occupies the gap between an action and a reaction,
that which absorbs an external action and reacts
on the inside.
IMAGE CENTRE: gap between a
received movement and an executed movement, an
action and a reaction (interval).
MOVEMENT IMAGE: the acentred
set [ensemble] of variable elements which act and
react on each other.
PERCEPTION-IMAGE: set
[ensemble] of elements which act on a centre, and
which vary in relation to it.
PERCEPTION-IMAGE (the thing):
Dicisign: term
created by Peirce in order to designate
principally the sign of the proposition in
general. It is used here in relation to the
special case of the ‘free indirect proposition’
(Pasolini). It is a perception in the frame of
another perception. This is the status of solid,
geometric and physical perception.
Reume: not to
be confused with Peirce’s ‘rheme’ (word). lt is
the perception of that which crosses the frame or
flows out. The liquid status of perception itself.
Gramme (engramme or
photogramme): not to be confused with a
photo. It is the genetic element of the
perception-image, inseparable as such from certain
dynamisms (immobilisation, vibration, flickering,
sweep, repetition, acceleration, deceleration,
etc.). The gaseous state of a molecular
perception.
AFFECTION-IMAGE (quality or
power):
Icon: used by
Peirce in order to designate a sign which refers
to its object by internal characteristics
(resemblance). Used here in order to designate the
affect as expressed by a face, or a facial
equivalent.
Qualisign (or
potisign): term used by Peirce in order to
designate a quality which is a sign. Used here to
designate the affect as expressed (or exposed) in
an any-space-whatever. An any-space-whatever is
sometimes an emptied space, sometimes a space the
linking up of whose parts is not immutable or
fixed.
Dividual: that
which is neither indivisible nor divisible, but is
divided (or brought together) by changing
qualitatively. This is the state of the entity,
that is to say of that which is expressed in an
expression.
IMPULSE—IMAGE (energy):
Symptom:
designates the qualities or powers related to an
originary world (defined by impulses).
Fetish:
fragment torn away, by the impulse, from a real
milieu, and corresponding to the originary world.
ACTION-IMAGE (the force or
act):
Synsign (or
encompasser): corresponds to Peirce’s
‘sinisign’. Set of qualities and powers as
actualised in a state of things, thus constituting
a real milieu around a centre, a situation in
relation to a subject: spiral.
Impression:
internal link between situation and action.
Index: used by
Peirce in order to designate a sign which refers
to its object by a material link. Used here in
order to designate the link of an action (or of an
effect of action) to a situation which is not
given, but merely inferred, or which remains
equivocal and reversible. We distinguish in this
sense indices of lack and indices of equivocity: the two
senses of the French word ellipse (ellipse and
ellipsis).
Vector (or line of the universe): broken
line which brings together singular points or
remarkable moments at the peak of their intensity.
Vectorial space is distinguished from encompassing
space.
IMAGE AT TRANSFORMATION
(reflection):
Figure: sign
which, instead of referring to its object,
reflects another (scenographic or
plastic image); or which reflects its own
object, but by inverting it (inverted image); or
which directly reflects its object (discursive
image).
MENTAL IMAGE (relation):
Mark:
designates natural relations, that is, the aspect
under which images are linked by a habit which
takes [fait passer] us from one to the other. The
demark designates an image tom
from its natural relations.
Symbol: used by
Peirce to designate a sign which refers to its
object by virtue of a law. Used here in order to
designate the support of abstract relations, that
is to say of a comparison of terms independently
of their natural relations.
Opsign and sonsign:
pure optical and sound image which breaks the
sensory-motor links, overwhelms
relations and no longer lets itself be expressed
in terms of movement, but opens directly on to
time.
|